Skip to main content
Log in

Partially dominant choice

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper proposes and analyzes a model of context-dependent choice with stable but incomplete preferences that is based on the idea of partial dominance: an alternative is chosen from a menu if it is not worse than anything in the menu and is also better than something else. This choice procedure provides a simple explanation of the attraction/decoy effect. It reduces to rational choice when preferences are complete in two ways that are made precise. Some preference identification and choice consistency properties associated with this model are analyzed, and certain ways in which its predictions differ from those of other recently proposed models of the attraction effect are also discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This term is widely used by psychologists and consumer/marketing researchers to describe such situations; see, for instance, Shafir et al. (1993). In the philosophy of choice literature, the term “unresolved conflict” has been used synonymously by Levi (1986).

  2. A binary relation \(R\) on a set \(X\) is reflexive if \(xRx\) holds for all \(x\in X\).

  3. See Gerasimou (2012) for such an application of the axiom.

  4. Bossert et al. (2005) and Eliaz and Ok (2006) study aspects of this model when a weaker structure on the domain and a richer structure on preferences are assumed, respectively.

  5. The logical independence of these axioms is proved in “Appendix 2”.

  6. Some choice theorists (e.g., Masatlioglu et al. (2012) and Ok et al. (2015)) interpret this pattern as one instance of the attraction effect and argue that another instance is manifested in the pattern \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) and \(C(\{x,y,z\})=y\) (which obviously leads to a violation of a-WARP and hence of Property \(\alpha \)). If one accepts that \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) means that the agent always (or almost always) chooses \(x\) and rejects \(y\) at this menu and that this agent (almost) always chooses \(y\) and rejects \(x,z\) at \(\{x,y,z\}\), then this interpretation of the attraction effect, while possibly true for some decision makers, does not seem to be immediately supported by existing experimental data that are primarily based on between-subject designs and one-shot choices from only one of these menus for each subject. Careful experimental work that would shed light on this issue is certainly desirable.

  7. Bernheim and Rangel (2009), Rubinstein and Salant (2012), Manzini and Mariotti (2012), Cherepanov et al. (2013) and Fleurbaey and Schokkaert (2013) are recent studies that are concerned with the problem of eliciting welfare preferences in models of bounded-rational or nonstandard behavior. Galichon and Quah (2013) outline some recent trends in revealed preference theory more generally.

  8. Indeed, in this case \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) would reveal \(x\succ y\), \(C(\{x,y\})=y\) would reveal \(y\succ x\) and \(C(\{x,y\})=\{x,y\}\) would reveal \(x\nsucc y\) and \(y\nsucc x\).

  9. See Apesteguia and Ballester (2013) for a recent reformulation of this model.

  10. In other relevant work, Kamenica (2008) studied a market model in which alternatives convey information to the consumers in ways that may induce changes in market shares that are consistent with the attraction effect. Bordallo et al. (2013) studied context effects in a parametric model of choice based on a menu-dependent utility function that is linear on quality and price and is generally distorted by the relative salience of quality and price in a given menu in favor of one attribute for each good. In this special environment, that model too can explain the attraction effect.

References

  • Apesteguia, J., Ballester, M.: Choice by sequential procedures. Games Econ. Behav. 77, 90–99 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J.: Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica 26, 121–127 (1959)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, T., Sengupta, K.: Characterization of generalized weak orders and revealed preference. Econ. Theory 3, 571–576 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B.D., Rangel, A.: Beyond revealed preference: choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Q. J. Econ. 124, 51–104 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bordallo, P., Gennaioli, N., Shleifer, A.: Salience and consumer choice. J. Polit. Econ. 121, 803–843 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, W., Sprumont, Y., Suzumura, K.: Maximal-element rationalizability. Theory Decis. 58, 325–350 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherepanov, V., Feddersen, T., Sandroni, A.: Revealed preferences and aspirations in warm glow theory. Econ. Theory 54, 501–535 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Clippel, G., Eliaz, K.: Reason-based choice: a bargaining rationale for the attraction and compromise effects. Theor. Econ. 7, 125–162 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: Review of R. D. Luce, “Individual Choice Behavior: A Theoretical Analysis”. Am. Econ. Rev. 50, 186–188 (1960)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehlers, L., Sprumont, Y.: Weakened WARP and top-cycle choice rules. J. Math. Econ. 44, 87–94 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz, K., Ok, E.A.: Indifference or indecisiveness? Choice-theoretic foundations of incomplete preferences. Games Econ. Behav. 56, 61–86 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz, K., Richter, M., Rubinstein, A.: Choosing the two finalists. Econ. Theory 46, 211–219 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., Schokkaert, E.: Behavioral welfare economics and redistribution. Am. Econ. J. Microecon. 5, 180–215 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galichon, A., Quah, J.K.H.: Symposium on revealed preference analysis. Econ. Theory 54, 419–423 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: Asymmetric dominance, deferral and status quo bias in a theory of choice with incomplete preferences. MPRA working paper 40097 (2012)

  • Gerasimou, G: Incomplete preferences and rational choice avoidance. Mimeo (2012)

  • Huber, J., Payne, J.W., Puto, C.: Adding asymmetrically dominated alternatives: violations of regularity and the similarity hypothesis. J. Consum. Res. 9, 90–98 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamenica, E.: Contextual inference in markets: on the informational content of product lines. Am. Econ. Rev. 98, 2127–2149 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I.: Hard Choices: Decision Making Under Unresolved Conflict. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1986)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lombardi, M.: Reason-based choice correspondences. Math. Soc. Sci. 57, 58–66 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, M.: Indifference and incompleteness distinguished by rational trade. Games Econ. Behav. 67, 300–314 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., Mariotti, M.: Sequentially rationalizable choice. Am. Econ. Rev. 97, 1824–1839 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., Mariotti, M.: Categorize then choose: boundedly rational choice and welfare. J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 10, 1141–1165 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mariotti, M.: What kind of preference maximization does the weak axiom of revealed preference characterize? Econ. Theory 35, 403–406 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masatlioglu, Y., Nakajima, D., Ozbay, E.Y.: Revealed attention. Am. Econ. Rev. 102, 2183–2205 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H.: Choice functions over a finite set: a summary. Soc. Choice Welf. 2, 147–160 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ok, E.A., Ortoleva, P., Riella, G.: Revealed (p)reference theory. Am. Econ. Rev. 105, 299–321 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A., Salant, Y.: Eliciting welfare preferences from behavioural datasets. Rev. Econ. Stud. 79, 375–387 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, T.: Choice functions, “rationality” conditions, and variations of the weak axiom of revealed preference. J. Econ. Theory 13, 414–427 (1976)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.: Choice functions and revealed preference. Rev. Econ. Stud. 38, 307–317 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.: Social choice theory: a re-examination. Econometrica 45, 53–89 (1977)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafir, E., Simonson, I., Tversky, A.: Reason-based choice. Cognition 11, 11–36 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simonson, I.: Choice based on reasons: the case of attraction and compromise effects. J. Consum. Res. 16, 158–174 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A.: Elimination by aspects: a theory of choice. Psychol. Rev. 79, 281–299 (1972)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Georgios Gerasimou.

Additional information

I thank Mark Dean, Takashi Hayashi, Paola Manzini, Marco Mariotti, John Quah, Michael Richter, Jörg Stoye, Christopher J. Tyson, workshop/seminar/conference audiences at Cambridge, Amsterdam, St Andrews, Queen Mary-London, EBIM 2010 (Bielefeld), ESEM 2011 (Oslo), RES 2012 (Cambridge), SIRE-BIC 2013 (Edinburgh), SAET 2013 (Paris) and AMES 2013 (Singapore) and two referees of this journal for useful comments/discussions on previous versions of the paper, the main idea of which originates in my doctoral dissertation at the University of Cambridge. The first version of the paper was titled “Choice in the Presence of Attractions” (June 2011). Financial assistance from the Scottish Institute for Research in Economics is gratefully acknowledged. Any errors are my own.

Appendices

Appendix 1: Proofs

Proof of Proposition 1

It is well known that (a) \(\Rightarrow \) (b) and (d) \(\Rightarrow \) (a). It will be shown that (b) \(\Rightarrow \) (c) \(\Rightarrow \) (d).

(b) \(\Rightarrow \) (c). Suppose \(a\)-WARP is violated. Then \(C(\{x,y\})=x\), \(x\in A\) and \(y\in C(A)\) for some \(x,y\in X\) and \(A\in {\mathcal {M}}\). Since \(y\not \in C(\{x,y\})\), this obviously violates Property \(\alpha \). Thus, \(a\)-WARP is satisfied. Suppose \(b\)-WARP is not. There are \(A\in {\mathcal {M}}\) and \(x,y\in A\) such that \(x\in C(A)\), \(y\in A\!{\setminus }\!C(A)\) and \(y\in C(\{x,y\})\). Since Property \(\alpha \) holds and \(x\in C(A)\), it follows that \(x\in C(\{x,y\})\) too. Thus, \(C(\{x,y\})=\{x,y\}\). Since \(A\supset \{x,y\}\) and Property \(\beta \) holds, \(C(\{x,y\})=\{x,y\}\) and \(x\in C(A)\) implies \(y\in C(A)\), a contradiction. Therefore, \(b\)-WARP is also satisfied.

(c) \(\Rightarrow \) (d). Define the relation \(\succsim \) on \(X\) by \(x\succsim y\) if \(x\in C(\{x,y\})\). Since all binary menus are included in \({\mathcal {M}}\) and \(C\) is nonempty-valued, \(\succsim \) is complete. Suppose \(x\succsim y\) and \(y\succsim z\) and assume to the contrary that \(x\not \succsim z\). Completeness implies \(z\succ x\), i.e., \(C(\{x,z\})=z\). By assumption, \(A:=\{x,y,z\}\in {\mathcal {M}}\) and \(C(A)\ne \emptyset \). It follows from a-WARP that \(x\not \in C(A)\). Suppose \(y\in C(A)\). Since \(x\in A\!{\setminus }\!C(A)\) and \(y\in C(A)\), it follows from b-WARP that \(C(\{x,y\})=y\). This contradicts the postulate \(x\succsim y\). Similarly, \(z\not \in C(A)\). Thus, \(x,y,z\not \in C(A)\), which is impossible. This establishes that \(x\succsim z\) and therefore that \(\succsim \) is also transitive, hence a weak order.

Now let \(x\in C(A)\) and suppose there exists \(y\in A\) such that \(y\succ x\). Since \(C(\{x,y\})=y\), \(y\in A\) and \(x\in C(A)\), this contradicts a-WARP. Thus, \(x\succsim y\) for all \(y\in A\). Conversely, suppose \(x\succsim y\) for all \(y\in A\) and suppose \(x\not \in C(A)\). It holds that \(z\in C(A)\) for some \(x\ne z\in A\). Since \(z\in C(A)\), \(x\in A\!{\setminus }\!C(A)\) and \(x\in C(\{x,z\})\) by assumption, b-WARP is contradicted. Thus, \(\succsim \) rationalizes \(C\). Finally, since all binary menus are included in \({\mathcal {M}}\), \(\succsim \) is unique. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

It is straightforward that (a) \(\Rightarrow \) (b), (b) \(\Rightarrow \) (c) (cf Observation 1) and (d) \(\Rightarrow \) (a). It will be shown that (c) \(\Rightarrow \) (d). Suppose \(C\) satisfies CIR and \(a\)-WARP. Define \(\succ \) by \(x\succ y\) if \(C(\{x,y\})=x\). This is asymmetric by definition. From CIR and the full-domain assumption, it is also complete. Suppose \(x\succ y\), \(y\succ z\) and \(x\nsucc z\). From CIR, \(x\nsucc z\) implies \(z\succ x\). Since \(C\) is nonempty-valued, \(C(\{x,y,z\})\ne \emptyset \). Suppose \(x\in C(\{x,y,z\})\). Since \(a\)-WARP holds, this contradicts the postulate \(z\succ x\). Therefore, \(x\not \in C(\{x,y,z\})\). Similarly, \(y,z\not \in C(\{x,y,z\})\). Thus, \(C(\{x,y,z\})=\emptyset \), a contradiction. It follows then that \(x\succ z\). Thus, \(\succ \) is also transitive and hence a strict linear order.

Suppose \(x\in C(A)\). It follows from \(a\)-WARP that \(y\nsucc x\) for all \(y\in A\). Now suppose the converse is true. From CIR this implies \(x\succ y\) for all \(y\in A\!{\setminus }\!\{x\}\). Suppose \(x\not \in C(A)\). From nonempty-valuedness, \(w\in C(A)\) for some \(w\in A\). Since \(x\succ w\) from above, and since \(a\)-WARP holds, this is a contradiction. Thus, \(C(A)=\{x\in A: y\nsucc x\) for all \(y\in A\}\). Finally, since all binary menus are included in \({\mathcal {M}}\), \(\succ \) is unique. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3

It is straightforward that (b) implies (a). Conversely, define \(\succ \) by \(x\succ y\) if \(C(\{x,y\})=x\). Let \(A\in {\mathcal {M}}\) and \(x\in A\) be such that \(y\nsucc x\) for all \(y\in A\). From nonempty-valuedness, \(x\in C(\{x,y\})\) for all \(y\in A\). From Property \(\gamma \), \(x\in C(A)\). Now let \(x\in C(A)\) and suppose, per contra, that \(y\succ x\) for some \(y\in A\). Since this is equivalent to \(C(\{x,y\})=y\) and a-WARP holds by assumption, this is a contradiction. Finally, since all binary menus are included in \({\mathcal {M}}\), \(\succ \) is unique. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4

Suppose there exists an acyclic relation \(\succ \) on \(X\) such that (2) holds. Assume, per contra, that a-WARP is violated. There exist \(x,y\in X\) and \(A\in {\mathcal {M}}\) such that \(C(\{x,y\})=x\), \(x\in A\) and \(y\in C(A)\). From \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) and (2b) it follows that \(x\succ y\). Since \(y\in C(A)\) it also follows from (2a) or (2b) (if \(C(A)=A\) or \(C(A)\subset A\), respectively) that \(x\nsucc y\). This is a contradiction.

Now let \(A_1,\ldots ,A_k\in {\mathcal {M}}\) be such that \(A_1\ne \{x\}\), \(x=C(A_1)\) and \(x\in C(A_i)\), \(2\le i\le k\). Define \(A:=\bigcup _{i=1}^kA_i\). It is implied by (2b) and \(C(A_1)=x\) that \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A_1\) and \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A_1\). Moreover, \(x\in C(A_i)\) and (2) imply \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A_i\). Thus, \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A\) and \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\). From (2b), this implies \(x\in C(A)\). Hence, Weak Property \(\gamma \) is satisfied.

Finally, suppose \(x\in C(A)\) and there exists \(z\in A\!{\setminus }\!C(A)\). This implies \(C(A)\subset A\). Hence, (2b) and \(x\in C(A)\) implies \(x\succ y\) and therefore \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) for some \(y\in A\). From (2b) and \(x\succ y\), it also follows that \(y\not \in C(A)\). Thus, Partial b-WARP is also satisfied.

Conversely, assume that \(C\) is nonempty-valued and satisfies a-WARP, Weak Property \(\gamma \) and Partial b-WARP. Define the asymmetric relation \(\succ \) on \(X\) by \(x\succ y\) if \(C(\{x,y\})=x\). Suppose \(\succ \) is not acyclic. There exist \(x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_k\in X\) such that \(x_1\succ x_2\succ \ldots \succ x_k\succ x_1\). By assumption, \(B:=\{x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_k\}\in {\mathcal {M}}\), while \(C(B)\ne \emptyset \) is also true by assumption. Thus, \(x_i\in C(B)\) for some \(i\le k\). From the \(\succ \)-cycle above, it follows that there is \(x_j\in B\) such that \(x_j\succ x_i\), i.e., \(C(\{x_i,x_j\})=x_j\). This contradicts a-WARP.

Suppose \(A\in {\mathcal {M}}\) is such that \(x\nsucc y\) and \(y\nsucc x\) for all \(x,y\in A\). Let \(x\in C(A)\) and \(C(A)\subset A\). If \(|A|=2\), then \(A=\{x,y\}\) for some \(y\in X\), and \(x\succ y\) obviously holds, a contradiction. Suppose \(|A|>2\). From Partial b-WARP, there exists \(y\in A\!{\setminus }\!C(A)\) such that \(x\succ y\), which is a contradiction too. It follows, therefore, that \(C(A)=A\). In the other direction, let \(C(A)=A\) and suppose \(x\succ y\) for some \(x,y\in A\). Since \(y\in C(A)\) by assumption, this is a violation of a-WARP. This establishes (2a).

To establish (2b), let \(C(A)\subset A\) for some \(A\in {\mathcal {M}}\). Suppose \(x\in C(A)\). If \(z\succ x\) for some \(z\in A\), then a-WARP is violated. Moreover, \(x\in C(A)\), \(C(A)\subset A\) and Partial b-WARP together imply \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\!{\setminus }\!C(A)\). Thus, \(x\in C(A)\) and \(C(A)\subset A\) implies \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A\) and \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\). In the other direction, suppose there is \(x\in A\) such that \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A\) and \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\). This implies \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) for some \(y\in A\) and, since \(C\) is nonempty-valued, \(x\in C(\{x,z\})\) for all \(z\in A\). Let \(F:=\{x,y\}\) and label all other elements in \(A\) by \(z_1,\ldots ,z_k\). Also, let \(G_i:=\{x,z_i\}\). Since \(x=C(F)\), \(x\in \bigcap _{i=1}^kC(G_i)\) and \(\bigcup _{i=1}^kG_i\cup F=A\), it follows from Weak Property \(\gamma \) that \(x\in C(A)\). Finally, suppose \(C(A)\) consists of all \(x\in A\) with the above two properties and assume to the contrary that \(C(A)=A\). Since there exist \(x,y\in A\) such that \(C(\{x,y\})=x\) by assumption, while \(y\in C(A)=A\) also holds by assumption, a-WARP is violated. Hence, \(C(A)\subset A\). As above, uniqueness is straightforward. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 5

It is obviously true that (a) always implies (b). To show that the converse implication holds under the stated conditions fix an arbitrary integer \(n>2\) and assume that \(x\in A\) implies \(y\not \in C(A)\) for all \(A\in {\mathcal {N}}\). Then, \({\mathcal {N}}\) includes all subsets with \(n\) elements and there are \(n-2\) distinct alternatives that are incomparable to everything in \(X\). Let \(S\) be the set of all these \(n-2\) alternatives. Also, let \(T=S\cup \{x,y\}\). Since \(T\) has \(n\) elements, it follows that \(T\in {\mathcal {N}}\). Suppose \(w\in C(T)\) for some \(w\in S\). Since \(w\) is universally incomparable and \(C\) is PD, the above can happen if and only if \(C(T)=T\). In this case, \(y\in C(T)\) also holds, which contradicts (b). Thus, \(w\not \in C(T)\) for all \(w\in S\). Moreover, since \(x\in T\), it follows from (b) that \(y\not \in C(T)\). Hence, \(C(T)=x\). Since \(C(T)\subset T\), it follows from (2b) that \(x\succ z\) for some \(z\in T\). Since \(x\nsucc w\) for all \(w\in S\) by assumption, it follows that \(x\succ z\) for some \(z\in T\!{\setminus }\! {S}=\{x,y\}\). Since \(\succ \) is irreflexive, this implies \(x\succ y\). \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 3

Suppose first that \(w,x,y,z\) are such that \(w\succ x\), \(y\succ z\) and no comparison is possible in all other pairs. It holds that \(C(\{w,x,y,z\})=\{w,y\}\) and \(C(\{w,y,z\})=y\), in violation of Property \(\alpha \). If \(x\succ z\) is also true, then \(C(\{x,y,z\})=\{x,y\}\) and \(C(\{w,x,y,z\})=\{w,y\}\), in violation of Property \(\beta \). These preferences finally lead to the PD choices \(C(\{w,z\})=\{w,z\}\), \(C(\{w,y\})=\{w,y\}\) and \(C(\{w,y,z\})=y\), in violation of Property \(\gamma \).

Next, let \(A=\{x,y,z\}\), \(B=\{x,z\}\) and suppose \(x\succ y\) and that all other options are incomparable. Then, \(C(A)=x\), \(\{x\}\subset B\subset A\) and \(C(B)=\{x,z\}\), but \(z\not \in C(A)=x\), showing that Aizerman’s axiom is not satisfied. Now suppose \(A=\{x,y,w,z\}\), \(B=\{x,y,w\}\), \(w\succ y\), \(x\succ y\), \(x\succ z\), \(z\succ w\) and all other pairs consist of incomparable options. These preferences imply \(C(\{x,y\})=x=C(A)\) but \(C(B)=\{x,w\}\), in violation of Weak WARP. Next, consider \(A=\{w,x,y\}\), \(B=\{x,y,z\}\), \(x\succ w\), \(y\succ z\) and let all other alternatives in \(A,B\) be incomparable. It holds that \(C(A)=x\) and \(C(B)=y\), in violation of Weakened WARP.

To verify that Reference Consistency is not satisfied in general, suppose \(x\succ z\), \(w\succ y\) and that incomparability applies to all other pairs of options derived from these four. It holds that \(C(\{w,x,y,z\})=\{w,x\}\). Moreover, \(C(\{w,z\})=\{w,z\}\) and \(C(\{x,y\})=\{x,y\}\), the menu \(\{w,x,y,z\}\) is \(C\)-awkward, the menus \(\{x,y\}\) and \(\{w,z\}\) form a \(C\)-cover of \(\{w,x,y,z\}\), and \(C(\{w,x,y,z\})\cap \{w,z\}\ne C(\{w,z\})\), \(C(\{w,x,y,z\})\cap \{x,y\}\ne C(\{x,y\})\).

Now suppose \(x,y\in C(A)\). Since this implies \(x\nsucc y\) and \(y\nsucc x\), it follows that \(C(\{x,y\})=\{x,y\}\). Therefore, a PD \(C\) satisfies Rationality of Indifference. Finally, to see that such a \(C\) also conforms with ERR notice that \(w\in C(A\cup \{x\})\) and \(w\in C(A\cup \{y\})\) implies \(z\nsucc w\) for all \(z\in A\cup \{x,y\}\) and \(w\succ z',z''\) for some \(z'\in A\cup \{x\}\) and \(z''\in A\cup \{y\}\). Hence, \(w\succ z\) for some \(z\in A\cup \{x,y\}\), which ensures that \(x\in C(A\cup \{x,y\})\). \(\square \)

Appendix 2: Axiom independence

The tightness of the axiomatic system of Proposition 4 is established here by means of counterexamples. Let \(X=\{w,x,y,z\}\) and \({\mathcal {M}}=\{A:A\ne \emptyset ,\; A\subseteq X\}\). Each of the following cases provides an example where choices satisfy all but one axiom (singletons are ignored for brevity):

Not a-WARP

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\})= & {} w,\;\; C(\{w,y\})=\{w,y\},\;\; C(\{w,z\})=\{w,z\}, \\ C(\{x,y\})= & {} \{x,y\},\;\; C(\{x,z\})=x,\;\; C(\{y,z\})=y \\ C(\{w,x,y\})= & {} C(\{w,y,z\})=\{w,y\},\;\; C(\{w,x,z\})=\{w,x\},\;\; C(\{x,y,z\})=\{x,y\} \\ C(X)= & {} \{w,x,y\} \end{aligned}$$

Not Weak Property \(\gamma \)

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\})= & {} w,\;\; C(\{w,y\})=\{w,y\},\;\; C(\{w,z\})=\{w,z\}, \\ C(\{x,y\})= & {} \{x,y\},\;\; C(\{x,z\})=x,\;\; C(\{y,z\})=y \\ C(\{w,x,y\})= & {} C(\{w,y,z\})=C(\{w,x,z\})=w,\;\; C(\{x,y,z\})=y \\ C(X)= & {} w \end{aligned}$$

Not Partial b-WARP

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\})= & {} w,\;\; C(\{w,y\})=\{w,y\},\;\; C(\{w,z\})=\{w,z\}, \\ C(\{x,y\})= & {} \{x,y\},\;\; C(\{x,z\})=x,\;\; C(\{y,z\})=\{y,z\} \\ C(\{w,x,y\})= & {} C(\{w,y,z\})=\{w,y\},\;\; C(\{w,x,z\})=w,\;\; C(\{x,y,z\})=y \\ C(X)= & {} \{w,y\} \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gerasimou, G. Partially dominant choice. Econ Theory 61, 127–145 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0869-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0869-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation