Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Public Choice 3-4/2021

09.04.2021

A Talmudic constrained voting majority rule

verfasst von: Ronen Bar-El, Mordechai E. Schwarz

Erschienen in: Public Choice | Ausgabe 3-4/2021

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Talmudic Law requires a minimal supermajority (13 out of 23) for conviction, but at the same time, provides that a unanimous conviction leads to a mistrial. We derive the necessary and sufficient conditions for sincere and strategic voting and show that under the Talmudic rule, the probability of the first type judicial error is lower than that computed by Feddersen and Pessendorfer (Am Polit Sci Rev 92(1):23–35, 1998) and Coughlan (Am Polit Sci Rev 94(2):375–393, 2000). However, the probability of a second type error marginally is higher.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
For generalizations of Condorcet’s theorem under relaxations of Condorcet’s restrictive assumptions, see, for example, Grofman et al. (1983), Ladha (1992), Berend and Paroush (1998) and Ben-Yashar and Nitzan (2017a, b). For application of the Condorcet Theorem in a different field, see Ben-Yashar et al. (2018). For a comprehensive literature survey, see Nitzan and Paroush (2017).
 
2
The same view was expressed, for example, by the Israeli Supreme Court justice Yoram Danziger in the 16th annual conference of the Israeli Bar Association in Eilat (April 2016).
 
3
In the United States, unanimity is required for conviction in major felonies in 48 states (Reichelt 2006), except Oregon and Louisiana, in which conviction is allowed with a supermajority of 10 jurors against 2 (Johnson v. Louisiana, 406 U.S. 356 (1972). Apodaca v. Oregon, 406 U.S. 404 (1972)), but unanimity is required if the jury is small (5 or 6 jurors: Burch v. Louisiana, 441 U.S. 130 (1979). A supermajority is also required in many countries for approval of constitutional amendments.
 
4
Sanhedrin Ch. 1 §6. The Mishnah (from the Hebrew מִשְׁנָה “study by repetition”) is the earliest major written codex of the Jewish Rabbinic “oral law” tradition, redacted by R. Yehuda HaNasi around 200 CE.
 
5
Babylonian Talmud, Sanhedrin 17b, translated by Rabbi Jacob Shachter, (Epstein 1994). The Talmud (from the Hebrew תַּלְמוּד “study”) contains collections of rabbinical traditions, mainly interpretations of the Mishnah. The earlier version of the Talmud, the Jerusalem Talmud, was redacted around 400 CE. The prevailing version, the Babylonian Talmud, was redacted around 500 CE. The Mishnah is written in Hebrew and the Talmudim in Aramaic.
 
6
Sanhedrin (from the Greek συνέδριον, “sitting together” or “assembly”) is a tribunal of 23 jurors appointed in every city in the Land of Israel (Deuteronomy 16, 18). In addition, the Great Sanhedrin of 71 justices convened in the Hall of Hewn Stones located beside the Temple in Jerusalem.
 
7
Shachter’s translation of פּוֹטְרִין אוֹתוֹ as “acquitted”, is compatible with the mainstream commentators’ understanding. However, other translations are possible (see below footnotes 10 and 22).
 
8
For a survey of rabbinical explanations, see Glatt (2013). Glatt indicated that although the R. Kahana ruling (according to mainstream interpretation) seems as a “technicality” stemming from harsh legal formalism, no Talmudic commentator suggested such an explanation. That claim is, however, inaccurate. See, for example, Halevi (1963, Ch. 9).
 
9
E.g., Abulafia (1992, Sanhedrin 17a) quoted in Tosfot Rosh, (Sanhedrin 17a) and Safrai (1964).
 
10
Literally, פּוֹטְרִין אוֹתוֹ can be translated in this vein, but this translation is inconsistent with many other Talmudic topics. See Rabinovitch (2011, Laws of Sanhedrin Ch. 9 §1) and Hallevi (1966).
 
11
See for example Maimonides Laws of Sanhedrin, Ch. 9 §1, and see footnote 23 below.
 
12
See Perla (1973, positive commandment 97, our translation): “Why it cannot be anticipated that the jury will find a new point in favor of the defendant? Not because it is definitely impossible to acquit him according to the law, but because each juror sees that none of his colleagues finds any point for the defendant, and thus he concludes that the defense really has no hope and consequently does not pay attention to search for such a point, although it is still possible that with careful and cautious examination the defendant may be found innocent”.
 
13
To ensure free votes and deliberations, Jewish law provides that the King and the High Priest cannot be members of the Sanhedrin (bSanhedrin 18b), and “…in capital charges we commence [deliberation and votes] with [the opinion of] those on the side [benches]” (Mishnah, Sanhedrin 4 §2).
 
14
See for example Zvi Hirsch Hayout’s gloss on Sanhedrin (17a).
 
15
See Kings I (21, 13).
 
16
See for example, Exodus (23, 6), Deuteronomy (16, 19), Kethuboth (101a), Sota (21a).
 
17
See Mishnah (Avot 1, §1).
 
18
For a discussion of the Jewish law philosophy see Sect. 5.
 
19
We assume that \(p < 1\), since if there existed a juror with \(p = 1\), that divine juror would be enough to ensure that justice is done.
 
21
Assuming “contamination” would strengthen our results.
 
22
See also Duran (1910, pp. 20–21) and Povarsky (2000, Sanhedrin Volume A, 17b). Literally, פּוֹטְרִין אוֹתוֹ bears HaCohen’s translation as well.
 
23
More accurately, there is no continuous tradition of rabbinical rulings in Jewish criminal law. According to the Talmudic tradition, the Sanhedrin ceased to discuss criminal cases at 30 AC (Rosh-Hashana 31a), and was dismantled at 425 AC by a Roman decree. Post-Talmudic Jewish law authorities (except Maimonides) concentrated mainly on ritual and civil laws that remained relevant for Jewish religious and communal life in the Diaspora. The mainstream translation of פּוֹטְרִין אוֹתוֹ as “acquitted” was suggested by commentators, not decisors, and the Talmudic literature distinguishes strictly between these two functions. It should also be emphasized that HaCohen suggested his adjudication in his commentary on Maimonides who quoted R. Kahana’s ruling literally, arguing that by פּוֹטְרִין אוֹתוֹ both R. Kahana and Maimonides meant “dismissed”. In the absence of a continuous Jewish criminal law ruling tradition, HaCohen’s interpretation is valid as any alternative interpretation.
 
24
See Mishnah (Sanhedrin Ch. 5 §5) and Maimonides Laws of Sanhedrin Ch. 12 §3.
 
25
See Sanhedrin (34a), Maimonides Laws of Sanhedrin Ch. 11 §1, Babad (1924, commandment 77 §3), Uziel (1964 Vol. 4, Hoshen Mishpat Ch. 11) and more.
 
26
In Sect. 4.4 we show that their claim is inaccurate.
 
27
Geradi and Yariv (2007) indicated that previous literature almost ignored the possibility of a pre-vote deliberation. They showed that, on the one hand, if pre-vote communication among jurors is precluded, different voting-rules may generate different equilibria, and on the other hand with pre-vote deliberation all decision rules except the two types of unanimity rule (requiring a unanimous consensus to acquit or requiring a unanimous consensus to convict) generate the same set of equilibria regardless of the information and preferences structure or the deliberation protocol. In fact, they showed that with deliberation and non-unanimous voting rules the outcomes are implemented unanimously, but this result is expected from Aumann’s (1976) Agreement Theorem. (See also footnote 14).
 
28
“Do not say at voting ‘it is sufficient that I behave as my mentor’ but say what you really think”. (Tosefta, Sanhedrin Ch. 3 §8). The Tosefta (from the Aramaic תּוֹסֶפְתָּא, “addition”) is a collection of traditional rulings that were omitted from the Mishnah. According to the rabbinic tradition the Tosefta was redacted by R. Oshaya and R. Hiya (pupils of R. Yehuda HaNassi) in the third century CE.
 
29
Especially in light of Gunn et al. (2016), as explained above.
 
30
A natural interpretation of \(p\) and \(q_{j}\) is measures of jurors’ competence and standard of proof, respectively (Coughlan 2000). That is, juror \(j\) prefers to convict whenever \(\beta > q_{j}\), and in this sense \(\left( {1 - q_{j} } \right)\) measures juror \(j\)’s extent of “reasonable doubt”.
 
31
We follow Coughlan (2000) in endogenizing \( {{m}}_{{j}}^{{G}}\) and \( {{m}}_{{j}}^{{I}}\) by specifying a juror’s perceptions about the consequences of mistrial. Coughlan explained that “These perceptions may incorporate many different factors, but it seems reasonable to model the utility of mistrial as simply the expected utility of an additional trial before a new jury”. In a footnote he added: “I also could discount the expected utility of future trials or apply a fixed cost/disutility to each new trial. Mistrial utilities incorporating these factors still allow calculation of the refined necessary and sufficient conditions for sincere voting, but analysis of such utility structures significantly increases the complexity of the presentation without providing much additional insight”. Recall that in this model there is no time dimension and consequently no discount factor. Thus, all what a juror has to consider is the possibility that after a number of repeated mistrials, the defendant will finally be either convicted or acquitted.
 
32
Throughout the paper we simulate the results under the assumption that \(q \in \left( {\frac{1}{2},1} \right)\) since we assume that a juror prefers to acquit a guilty than to convict an innocent. This assumption is well established in the Western judicial code (Blackstone 1830) and also in the Jewish judicial code as explained in Sect. 5.
 
33
Below (Sect. 3.3.4) we compare this result with Coughlan’s.
 
34
Feddersen and Pessendorfer (1998) calculated the (unique) symmetric responsive equilibrium strategies for a general\({\text{k}}^{*}\)\(\sigma \left( {q_{j} ,i} \right) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}c} 0 & {\beta < q_{j} } \\ {\frac{{p\left( {1 + \sqrt[{k - 1}]{{\left( {\frac{{1 - q_{j} }}{{q_{j} }}} \right)\left( {\frac{1 - p}{p}} \right)^{n - k + 1} }}} \right)}}{{p - \left( {1 - p} \right)\sqrt[{k - 1}]{{\left( {\frac{{1 - q_{j} }}{{q_{j} }}} \right)\left( {\frac{1 - p}{p}} \right)^{n - k + 1} }}}}} & {\beta \ge q_{j} } \\ \end{array} } \right.\)\(\sigma \left( {q_{j} ,g} \right) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}c} {\frac{{\sqrt[{n - k}]{{\left( {\frac{{1 - q_{j} }}{{q_{j} }}} \right)\left( {\frac{p}{1 - p}} \right)^{k} }} - 1}}{{p\left( {1 + \sqrt[{n - k}]{{\left( {\frac{{1 - q_{j} }}{{q_{j} }}} \right)\left( {\frac{1 - p}{p}} \right)^{k} }}} \right) - 1}}} & {\beta < q_{j} } \\ 1 & {\beta \ge q_{j} } \\ \end{array} } \right.\)
 
35
Since \(\lim_{n \to \infty } \beta \left( {r,n - 1, n} \right) = 1\), it follows that \(\exists {\overline{\text{n}}}\) such that \( {\beta }\left( {{{r,n}} - {{1, n}}} \right) > {{q}}_{{{j}}}\) for every \( {{n}} > {\overline{{n}}}\). Feddersen and Pessendorfer (1998) showed that in this case, \(\sigma \left( {q_{j} ,i} \right) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}c} 0 & {\beta < q_{j} } \\ {\frac{{p\sqrt[{n - 1}]{{\frac{{\left( {1 - p} \right)\left( {1 - q_{j} } \right)}}{{pq_{j} }}}} - \left( {1 - p} \right)}}{{p - \left( {1 - p} \right)\sqrt[{n - 1}]{{\frac{{\left( {1 - p} \right)\left( {1 - q_{j} } \right)}}{{pq_{j} }}}}}}} & {\beta \ge q_{j} } \\ \end{array} } \right.\) and \(\sigma \left( {q_{j} ,g} \right) = 1\).
 
36
More accurately, Coughlan showed that (under certain assumptions) informative-sincere voting is compatible with Nash equilibrium in this model if \(\left( {\frac{r}{1 - r}} \right)\left( {\frac{1 - p}{p}} \right) \le \frac{{q_{j} }}{{1 - q_{j} }} \le \left( {\frac{r}{1 - r}} \right)\left( {\frac{p}{1 - p}} \right)\).
 
37
Nevertheless, keep in mind that odd number of jurors is important only if conviction is not conditional upon unanimous approval.
 
38
If \( {{n}}\) is odd, the condition coincides with condition quoted in footnote 36. If \( {{n}}\) is even, the necessary and sufficient condition is \(\left( {\frac{r}{1 - r}} \right)\left( {\frac{1 - p}{p}} \right)^{2} \le \frac{{q_{j} }}{{1 - q_{j} }} \le \left( {\frac{r}{1 - r}} \right)\) or \(\left( {\frac{r}{1 - r}} \right) \le \frac{{q_{j} }}{{1 - q_{j} }} \le \left( {\frac{r}{1 - r}} \right)\left( {\frac{1 - p}{p}} \right)^{2}\).
 
39
Notice that even under Coughlan’s revelation mechanism, if \(\beta \left( {r,n - 1, n} \right) > q_{j}\) for any \(k < n,\) then as long as \(n_{c} < n\) in the preliminary straw vote, even if \(n_{c} = n\) in the final vote there is still a “reasonable doubt” according to the societal norms. This problem is aggravated in odd juries, because satisfaction Coughlan’s conditions in this case requires ceiling \(q\) but \(\beta \left( {r,n - 1, n} \right) \le q_{j}\) implies that \(q\) is close to 1.
 
40
Baharad et Al. (2012) suggested an algorithm for estimation of jurors’ competence, based on their previous decisions. However, the application of this algorithm faces two major problems. First, the algorithm implicitly assumes that jurors have always vote informatively. Second, we still have no way to know whether a past decision was, indeed, correct.
 
41
By Feddersen and Pessendorfer, assuming \(q_{j} = q\ \forall j \in N\), the probabilities of Type I and Type II errors under the unanimity rule are \(L_{I}^{\rm UN} = \left( {\gamma_{I} } \right)^{n} = \left( {\frac{{\left( {2p - 1} \right)\sqrt[{n - 1}]{{\frac{{\left( {1 - q} \right)\left( {1 - p} \right)}}{pq}}}}}{{p - \left( {1 - p} \right)\sqrt[{n - 1}]{{\frac{{\left( {1 - q} \right)\left( {1 - p} \right)}}{pq}}}}}} \right)^{n}\) and \(L_{G}^{\rm UN} = 1 - \left( {\gamma_{G} } \right)^{n} = 1 - \left( {\frac{2p - 1}{{p - \left( {1 - p} \right)\sqrt[{n - 1}]{{\frac{{\left( {1 - q} \right)\left( {1 - p} \right)}}{pq}}}}}} \right)^{n}\).
 
42
Taking the limits of \( {{L}}_{{I}}^{{UN}}\) and \(\it {\text{L}}_{\text{G}}^{\text{UN}}\) (see footnote 41) yields \(\lim_{n \to \infty } L_{I}^{{{\text{UN}}}} = \left( {\frac{{\left( {1 - q} \right)\left( {1 - p} \right)}}{pq}} \right)^{{\frac{p}{2p - 1}}}\) and \(\lim_{n \to \infty } L_{G}^{{{\text{UN}}}} = \left( {\frac{{\left( {1 - q} \right)\left( {1 - p} \right)}}{pq}} \right)^{{\frac{1 - p}{{2p - 1}}}}\).
Under Feddersen and Pessendorfer’s calibration \(\lim_{n \to \infty } L_{I}^{{{\text{UN}}}} = 2.27 \times 10^{ - 1}\) and \(\lim_{n \to \infty } L_{G}^{{{\text{UN}}}} = 0.47\), while under our alternative calibration \(\lim_{n \to \infty } L_{I}^{{{\text{UN}}}} = 1.87 \times 10^{ - 6}\) and \(\lim_{n \to \infty } L_{G}^{{{\text{UN}}}} = {0}{\text{.999}}\).
 
43
This result is unsurprising since in Coughlan’s model the optimal rule is \(k^{*} = n\).
 
44
Zechariah 8, §16.
 
45
Jerusalem Talmud, Sanhedrin 1,1. For further discussion, see Lipschütz and Schwarz (2020).
 
46
The only human attributed with perfect judicial competence in Judaism is the Messiah (bSanhedrin 93b). According to the Talmudic tradition (Rosh-Hashana 21b), King Solomon’s pretension of being able to judge intuitively without witnesses or evidence was refuted by God, and even that wisest man could not really identify the real mother based on his analysis of the mothers’ behavior in the Judgment of King Solomon (Kings I, 3:16–28). The Babylonian Talmud (Makkot 23b) concludes that the verdict “she is the mother thereof” was actually issued by a celestial voice.
 
47
For a comprehensive discussion of this issue, see Abraham (2016).
 
48
Deuteronomy (8, 6, and 28, 9), Babylonian Talmud Sota (14a) and more.
 
49
See Maimonides, Laws of De’ot (general proper behavior, Ch. 7 §1–2).
 
50
See Mishnah Sanhedrin (5, §4).
 
51
An entire tractate (Horayot) is dedicated to remedies for Sanhedrin’s errors.
 
52
Exodus 23, 2.
 
53
Midrash (from the Hebrew דְּרָשָׁה, “sermon” or “exegesis”), is a collection of exegesis of Biblical texts and homiletic stories as taught by the Sages.
 
54
The Midrash interprets Abraham’s nickname “the Hebrew” from עֵבֶר (over, or side). That is, the entire world is on the one side while he is on the other side. (Midrash Rabba on Genesis, 42,1), See also Ibn Ezra’s commentary on Exodus (23,2).
 
55
See Baba-Batra (93a), Maimonides Laws of Torts (8, §14), Laws of Sanhedrin (20, §1) and more.
 
56
Maimonides, Book of Commandments, (negative commandment 290), Translated by Berel Bell.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Abraham, M. (2016). Truth yet not steadfast (Hebrew: אמת ולא יציב). Tel Aviv: Miskal - Yeditoth Aharotnoth Books and Chemed Books. Abraham, M. (2016). Truth yet not steadfast (Hebrew: אמת ולא יציב). Tel Aviv: Miskal - Yeditoth Aharotnoth Books and Chemed Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Abulafia, M. (1992). Hidushei Haramah - Yad Rama (Hebrew). Jerusalem: Bnei Torah Library. Abulafia, M. (1992). Hidushei Haramah - Yad Rama (Hebrew). Jerusalem: Bnei Torah Library.
Zurück zum Zitat Aristotle. (1885). Politics (trans by B. Jowett). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Aristotle. (1885). Politics (trans by B. Jowett). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Aumann, R. J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. The Annals of Statistics, 4(6), 1236–1239.CrossRef Aumann, R. J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. The Annals of Statistics, 4(6), 1236–1239.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Austin-Smith, D., & Banks, J. (1996). Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. American Political Science Review, 90(1), 34–45.CrossRef Austin-Smith, D., & Banks, J. (1996). Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. American Political Science Review, 90(1), 34–45.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Babad, J. (1924). Minchat Hinuch. Vilnius: Rosenkranz and Schriftsetzer. Babad, J. (1924). Minchat Hinuch. Vilnius: Rosenkranz and Schriftsetzer.
Zurück zum Zitat Baharad, E., Goldberger, J., Koppel, M., & Nitzan, S. (2012). Beyond Condorcet: Optimal aggregation rules using voting records. Theory and Decision, 72(1), 113–130.CrossRef Baharad, E., Goldberger, J., Koppel, M., & Nitzan, S. (2012). Beyond Condorcet: Optimal aggregation rules using voting records. Theory and Decision, 72(1), 113–130.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. (2017a). Are two better than one? A note. Public Choice, 171(3–4), 323–329.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. (2017a). Are two better than one? A note. Public Choice, 171(3–4), 323–329.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. (2017b). Is diversity in capabilities desirable when adding decision makers? Theory and Decision, 82(3), 395–402.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. (2017b). Is diversity in capabilities desirable when adding decision makers? Theory and Decision, 82(3), 395–402.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., Krausz, M., & Nitzan, S. (2018). The effect of democratic decision-making on investment in reputation. Public Choice, 177(1–2), 155–164.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., Krausz, M., & Nitzan, S. (2018). The effect of democratic decision-making on investment in reputation. Public Choice, 177(1–2), 155–164.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Berend, D., & Paroush, J. (1998). When is condorcet jury theorem valid? Social Choice and Welfare, 15, 481–488.CrossRef Berend, D., & Paroush, J. (1998). When is condorcet jury theorem valid? Social Choice and Welfare, 15, 481–488.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Blackstone, W. (1830). Commentaries on the laws of England (Vol. 2). New York: Collins & Hannay. Blackstone, W. (1830). Commentaries on the laws of England (Vol. 2). New York: Collins & Hannay.
Zurück zum Zitat Condorcet, N. C. de. (1785). Essai sur l'application de l'analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix (French). Condorcet, N. C. de. (1785). Essai sur l'application de l'analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix (French).
Zurück zum Zitat Coughlan, P. J. (2000). In defense of unanimity jury verdict: Mistrials, communication, and strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 94(2), 375–393.CrossRef Coughlan, P. J. (2000). In defense of unanimity jury verdict: Mistrials, communication, and strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 94(2), 375–393.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Duran, S. (1910). Milhemet Mitzvah. Piotrków: Palman. Duran, S. (1910). Milhemet Mitzvah. Piotrków: Palman.
Zurück zum Zitat Epstein, I. (Ed.). (1994). Babylonian Talmud, The Soncino edition. Translated by J. Shachter. London: Soncino Press. Epstein, I. (Ed.). (1994). Babylonian Talmud, The Soncino edition. Translated by J. Shachter. London: Soncino Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Feddersen, T., & Pessendorfer, W. (1998). Convicting the innocent: The inferiority of unanimous jury verdict under strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 92(1), 23–35.CrossRef Feddersen, T., & Pessendorfer, W. (1998). Convicting the innocent: The inferiority of unanimous jury verdict under strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 92(1), 23–35.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Geradi, D., & Yariv, L. (2007). Deliberative voting. Journal of Economic Theory, 134, 317–338.CrossRef Geradi, D., & Yariv, L. (2007). Deliberative voting. Journal of Economic Theory, 134, 317–338.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Glatt, E. (2013). The unanimous verdict according to the Talmud: ancient law providing insight into modern legal theory. Pace International Law Review, 3(10), 317–335. Glatt, E. (2013). The unanimous verdict according to the Talmud: ancient law providing insight into modern legal theory. Pace International Law Review, 3(10), 317–335.
Zurück zum Zitat Grofman, B., Owen, G., & Feld, S. L. (1983). Thirteen theorems in search of the truth. Theory and Decision, 15(3), 261–278.CrossRef Grofman, B., Owen, G., & Feld, S. L. (1983). Thirteen theorems in search of the truth. Theory and Decision, 15(3), 261–278.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gunn, L. J., Chapeau-Blondeau, F., McDonnell, M. D., Davis, B. R., Allison, A., & Abbott, D. (2016). Too good to be true: When overwhelming evidence fails to convince. Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, A, 472(2187), 20150748.CrossRef Gunn, L. J., Chapeau-Blondeau, F., McDonnell, M. D., Davis, B. R., Allison, A., & Abbott, D. (2016). Too good to be true: When overwhelming evidence fails to convince. Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, A, 472(2187), 20150748.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat HaCohen, M. S. (2002). Or Sameach. Jerusalem: Masoret Israel Institute. HaCohen, M. S. (2002). Or Sameach. Jerusalem: Masoret Israel Institute.
Zurück zum Zitat Halevi, H. D. (1963). Dvar Hamishpat (Hebrew: דבר המשפט). Tel Aviv: Mossad Harav Kook. Halevi, H. D. (1963). Dvar Hamishpat (Hebrew: דבר המשפט). Tel Aviv: Mossad Harav Kook.
Zurück zum Zitat Hallevi, E. E. (1966). The correct interpretation of (Sanhedrin 17a)/ פוטרין אותו". "פוטרין" זה מהו? Tarbiz (Hebrew), 90–91. Hallevi, E. E. (1966). The correct interpretation of (Sanhedrin 17a)/ פוטרין אותו". "פוטרין" זה מהו? Tarbiz (Hebrew), 90–91.
Zurück zum Zitat Janis, I. L. (1982). Groupthink: Psychological studies of policy decisions and fiascoes. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Janis, I. L. (1982). Groupthink: Psychological studies of policy decisions and fiascoes. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Zurück zum Zitat Ladha, K. K. (1992). The condorcet jury theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36(3), 617–634.CrossRef Ladha, K. K. (1992). The condorcet jury theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36(3), 617–634.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lando, H. (2009). Prevention of crime and the optimal standard of proof in criminal law. Review of Land and Economics, 5(1), 33–52. Lando, H. (2009). Prevention of crime and the optimal standard of proof in criminal law. Review of Land and Economics, 5(1), 33–52.
Zurück zum Zitat Lipschütz, I., & Schwarz, M. E., (2020). Fairness versus economic efficiency: Lessons from an interdisciplinary analysis of Talmudic Bankruptcy Law. Review of Law and Economics, 16(3), 45–57. Lipschütz, I., & Schwarz, M. E., (2020). Fairness versus economic efficiency: Lessons from an interdisciplinary analysis of Talmudic Bankruptcy Law. Review of Law and Economics, 16(3), 45–57.
Zurück zum Zitat Mukhopadhaya, K. (2003). Jury size and the free rider problem. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 19(1), 24–44.CrossRef Mukhopadhaya, K. (2003). Jury size and the free rider problem. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 19(1), 24–44.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nitzan, S., & Paroush. J., (2017). Collective decision making and jury theorems. In Parisi, F. (Ed), The oxford handbook of law and economics. New York: The Oxford Univdrsity Press. Nitzan, S., & Paroush. J., (2017). Collective decision making and jury theorems. In Parisi, F. (Ed), The oxford handbook of law and economics. New York: The Oxford Univdrsity Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Perla, Y. F. (1973). Commentary on Se’adia’s Gaon book of commandments (Hebrew: ספר המצוות לרס"ג עם פירוש רי"פ פערלא). Jerusalem: Torah Books Fund. Perla, Y. F. (1973). Commentary on Se’adia’s Gaon book of commandments (Hebrew: ספר המצוות לרס"ג עם פירוש רי"פ פערלא). Jerusalem: Torah Books Fund.
Zurück zum Zitat Povarsky, D. (2000). Shiurei Rabbi David Povarsky. Benei-Brak: Unknown. Povarsky, D. (2000). Shiurei Rabbi David Povarsky. Benei-Brak: Unknown.
Zurück zum Zitat Rabinovitch, N. L. (2011). Yad Pshuta (Hebrew: יד פשוטה). Jerusalem: Me’aliot. Rabinovitch, N. L. (2011). Yad Pshuta (Hebrew: יד פשוטה). Jerusalem: Me’aliot.
Zurück zum Zitat Reichelt, J. D. (2006). Standing alone: Conformity, coercion, and the protection of the holdout juror. University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 40, 569. Reichelt, J. D. (2006). Standing alone: Conformity, coercion, and the protection of the holdout juror. University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 40, 569.
Zurück zum Zitat Safrai, S. (1964). The correct interpretation of the talmudic passage "סנהדרי שראו כולן לחובה פוטרין אותו". Tarbiz (Hebrew), 40–42. Safrai, S. (1964). The correct interpretation of the talmudic passage "סנהדרי שראו כולן לחובה פוטרין אותו". Tarbiz (Hebrew), 40–42.
Zurück zum Zitat Uziel, B. H. (1964). Mishpetei Uziel. Jerusalem: Mossad Harav Kook. Uziel, B. H. (1964). Mishpetei Uziel. Jerusalem: Mossad Harav Kook.
Metadaten
Titel
A Talmudic constrained voting majority rule
verfasst von
Ronen Bar-El
Mordechai E. Schwarz
Publikationsdatum
09.04.2021
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Choice / Ausgabe 3-4/2021
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-021-00895-w

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3-4/2021

Public Choice 3-4/2021 Zur Ausgabe