Skip to main content

2021 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

Becoming a Good Human Being: Aristotle on Virtue and Its Cultivation

verfasst von : Jörn Müller

Erschienen in: Handbuch Tugend und Tugendethik

Verlag: Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

In deliberate contrast to the ethical intellectualism of Socrates, Aristotle develops a complex conception of virtues as character traits which are closely tied to the different elements and stages of their cultivation: in the gradual process of becoming good, ‘learning by doing’ is the central cornerstone for establishing a close connectivity between emotion and reason as well as between desire, decision and right action. Virtue as a perfection of human nature engenders the best possible integration of irrational striving with reason in the soul and is thus the constitutive component of human flourishing.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
I will not take into account the Magna Moralia, another ethical treatise which is attributed to Aristotle but was probably not written by himself.
 
2
All quotations from Aristotle are taken from Barnes 1984, with the notable difference that aretē is translated as “virtue” and not as “excellence”.
 
3
Accordingly, Aristotle shows the tendency to use aretē without further specification as a shorthand expression for ethical or character virtue. I will follow this usage.
 
4
There are also other ‘losers’ in Aristotle’s ethics, i.e. character types who cannot make moral progress (Curzer 2012, Chap. 17).
 
5
This is one of the reasons why Aristotle deliberately turns his back on the Socratic notion of a virtue-technē (Angier 2010, Chap. 2): He does not subscribe to the idea that knowledge of the good is sufficient for moral motivation.
 
6
Another interesting approach to solve the problem of acquiring moral motivation is provided by Fossheim (2006), who points to mimēsis as habituation of the fine in musical performances. This idea ties in nicely with the basic Aristotelian structure of learning by doing (and not by simply being affected).
 
7
For this translation see Lorenz 2009, pp. 196–197.
 
8
This seems to tie the mean closely to a single scale, but it is also possible to define courage and the two extremes surrounding it in terms of the emotion of confidence and not only with regard to fear, as Aristotle himself recognises (NE 1107a33). Yet then there are more than two opposites involved.
 
9
This reading is to a certain extent indebted to the conception of metriopatheia, which in Aristotle’s school, the Peripatos, was later pitted against the Stoic ideal of apatheia, i.e. the extirpation of passions in the wise person.
 
10
If this were the case Aristotle would probably have used pros tina instead of pros hēmas (Brown 1997, p. 89).
 
11
For further passages in NE and EE see Moss (2011) with a thorough discussion.
 
12
It is an open discussion of whether this more substantial understanding of the role of phronēsis commits Aristotle to a ‘grand-end view’ according to which practical wisdom operates with a comprehensive blueprint of the overall human good in determining human conduct (Kraut 1993) or if phronēsis only deliberates about more limited local ends (Broadie 1991, pp. 198–202).
 
13
This conjunction does not pertain to the other intellectual virtues: one can be wise in theoretical matters (sophos) without possessing practical wisdom (NE 1141b3–8).
 
14
It is better to avoid the often used expression ‘unity thesis’ for the relationship between the virtues in Aristotle: this formula fits only for the Socratic point of view, according to which all virtues are ultimately identical. Aristotle, instead, argues for a ‘reciprocity thesis’.
 
15
The reciprocity thesis might also be conceived of as a kind of regulative ideal (Russell 2014, pp. 215–216).
 
16
As does Korsgaard (1996, esp. p. 205); contra: Whiting (2002). There are some ‘Kantian’ readings of Aristotle’s notion of virtue, apart from Korsgaard also by Sherman (1997) and Hursthouse (1999, Chaper 4). However, Aristotle does not share Kant’s overriding concern for morality (in the modern sense) and would probably regard Kantian virtues as mere forms of strength of will.
 
17
For kalon as the object of virtuous choice see, e.g., NE 1115b12–13. See also Cooper (1999, pp. 264–279) for the three kinds of desires which correspond to the fine, the advantageous and the pleasurable.
 
18
The attempt by Gardiner (2004) to distinguish between basic and non-basic virtues in Aristotle lacks sufficient textual backing.
 
19
For lists of the Aristotelian virtues and their spheres see Gottlieb (2009, p. 112) and Curzer (2018, p. 115).
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Angier, Tom. 2010. Technē in Aristotle’s ethics: Crafting the moral life. New York: Continuum. Angier, Tom. 2010. Technē in Aristotle’s ethics: Crafting the moral life. New York: Continuum.
Zurück zum Zitat Barnes, Jonathan (ed.). 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Barnes, Jonathan (ed.). 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Broadie, Sarah. 1991. Ethics with Aristotle. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press. Broadie, Sarah. 1991. Ethics with Aristotle. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Brown, Lesley. 1997. What is “the mean relative to us” in Aristotle’s ethics? Phronesis 42: 77–93.CrossRef Brown, Lesley. 1997. What is “the mean relative to us” in Aristotle’s ethics? Phronesis 42: 77–93.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brown, Lesley. 2014. Why is Aristotle’s virtue of character a mean? Taking Aristotle at his word (NE ii 6). In The Cambridge companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 64–80. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brown, Lesley. 2014. Why is Aristotle’s virtue of character a mean? Taking Aristotle at his word (NE ii 6). In The Cambridge companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 64–80. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Burnyeat, Miles. 1980. Aristotle on learning to be good. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty, 69–92. Berkeley: University of California Press. Burnyeat, Miles. 1980. Aristotle on learning to be good. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty, 69–92. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Charpenel, Eduardo. 2017: Ethos und Praxis: Der Charakterbegriff bei Aristoteles. Freiburg i. Br., München: Karl Alber. Charpenel, Eduardo. 2017: Ethos und Praxis: Der Charakterbegriff bei Aristoteles. Freiburg i. Br., München: Karl Alber.
Zurück zum Zitat Coope, Ursula. 2012. Why does Aristotle think that ethical virtue is required for practical wisdom? Phronesis 57: 142–163.CrossRef Coope, Ursula. 2012. Why does Aristotle think that ethical virtue is required for practical wisdom? Phronesis 57: 142–163.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cooper, John. 1999. Reason and emotion. Essays on moral psychology and ethical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Cooper, John. 1999. Reason and emotion. Essays on moral psychology and ethical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Curzer, Howard. 2005. How good people do bad things: Aristotle on the misdeeds of the virtuous. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 28: 233–256. Curzer, Howard. 2005. How good people do bad things: Aristotle on the misdeeds of the virtuous. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 28: 233–256.
Zurück zum Zitat Curzer, Howard. 2012. Aristotle and the virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Curzer, Howard. 2012. Aristotle and the virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Curzer, Howard. 2018. Aristotle and moral virtue. In The Oxford handbook of virtue, ed. Nancy E. Snow, 104–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Curzer, Howard. 2018. Aristotle and moral virtue. In The Oxford handbook of virtue, ed. Nancy E. Snow, 104–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fossheim, Hallvard. 2006. Habituation as mimesis. In Values and virtues. Aristotelianism in contemporary ethics, ed. Timothy D. J. Chappell, 105–117. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fossheim, Hallvard. 2006. Habituation as mimesis. In Values and virtues. Aristotelianism in contemporary ethics, ed. Timothy D. J. Chappell, 105–117. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Gardiner, Stephen. 2004. Aristotle’s basic and non-basic virtues. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20: 261–295. Gardiner, Stephen. 2004. Aristotle’s basic and non-basic virtues. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20: 261–295.
Zurück zum Zitat Gill, Mary Louise. 2015. Virtue and reason in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In Bridging the gap between Aristotle’s science and ethics, eds. Devin Henry and Karen Margrethe Nielsen, 94–110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gill, Mary Louise. 2015. Virtue and reason in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In Bridging the gap between Aristotle’s science and ethics, eds. Devin Henry and Karen Margrethe Nielsen, 94–110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Gottlieb, Paula. 2009. The virtue of Aristotle’s ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Gottlieb, Paula. 2009. The virtue of Aristotle’s ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Halbig, Christoph. 2013. Der Begriff der Tugend und die Grenzen der Tugendethik. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp. Halbig, Christoph. 2013. Der Begriff der Tugend und die Grenzen der Tugendethik. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
Zurück zum Zitat Halper, Edward. 1999. The unity of the virtues in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 17: 115–143. Halper, Edward. 1999. The unity of the virtues in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 17: 115–143.
Zurück zum Zitat Hoffmann, Magdalena. 2010. Der Standard des Guten bei Aristoteles: Regularität im Unbestimmten. Freiburg i. Br: Karl Alber. Hoffmann, Magdalena. 2010. Der Standard des Guten bei Aristoteles: Regularität im Unbestimmten. Freiburg i. Br: Karl Alber.
Zurück zum Zitat Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hursthouse, Rosalind. 2006. The central doctrine of the mean. In The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 96–115. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. Hursthouse, Rosalind. 2006. The central doctrine of the mean. In The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 96–115. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Hutchinson, D. S. 1986. The virtues of Aristotle. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Hutchinson, D. S. 1986. The virtues of Aristotle. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Zurück zum Zitat Irwin, Terence. 1988. Disunity in the Aristotelian virtues. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 7: 61–78. Irwin, Terence. 1988. Disunity in the Aristotelian virtues. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 7: 61–78.
Zurück zum Zitat Irwin, Terence. 2010. The sense and reference of Kalon in Aristotle. Classical Philology 105: 381–402.CrossRef Irwin, Terence. 2010. The sense and reference of Kalon in Aristotle. Classical Philology 105: 381–402.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. From duty and for the sake of the noble. In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics. Rethinking happiness and duty, eds. Stephen P. Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, 203–236. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. From duty and for the sake of the noble. In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics. Rethinking happiness and duty, eds. Stephen P. Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, 203–236. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Kraut, Richard. 1993. In defense of the grand end. Ethics 103: 361–374.CrossRef Kraut, Richard. 1993. In defense of the grand end. Ethics 103: 361–374.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kraut, Richard. 2012. Aristotle on becoming good: Habituation, reflection, and perception. In The Oxford handbook of Aristotle, ed. Christopher Shields, 529–557. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kraut, Richard. 2012. Aristotle on becoming good: Habituation, reflection, and perception. In The Oxford handbook of Aristotle, ed. Christopher Shields, 529–557. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Kristjánsson, Kristján. 2007. Aristotle, emotions, and education. Aldershot: Ashgate. Kristjánsson, Kristján. 2007. Aristotle, emotions, and education. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Zurück zum Zitat Lawrence, Gavin. 2013. Human excellence in character and intellect. In A companion to Aristotle, ed. Georgios Anagnostopoulos, 419–441. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. Lawrence, Gavin. 2013. Human excellence in character and intellect. In A companion to Aristotle, ed. Georgios Anagnostopoulos, 419–441. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Lear, Gabriel Richardson. 2006. Aristotle on moral virtue and the fine. In The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 116–136. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. Lear, Gabriel Richardson. 2006. Aristotle on moral virtue and the fine. In The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 116–136. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Leighton, Stephen. 1992. Relativizing moral excellence in Aristotle. Apeiron 25: 49–66.CrossRef Leighton, Stephen. 1992. Relativizing moral excellence in Aristotle. Apeiron 25: 49–66.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lennox, James. 1999. Aristotle on the biological roots of human virtue: The natural history of natural virtue. In Biology and the foundation of ethics, eds. Jane Maienschein and Michael Ruse, 10–31. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lennox, James. 1999. Aristotle on the biological roots of human virtue: The natural history of natural virtue. In Biology and the foundation of ethics, eds. Jane Maienschein and Michael Ruse, 10–31. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Leunissen, Mariska. 2012. Aristotle on natural character and its implications for moral development. Journal of the History of Philosophy 50: 507–530.CrossRef Leunissen, Mariska. 2012. Aristotle on natural character and its implications for moral development. Journal of the History of Philosophy 50: 507–530.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Leunissen, Mariska. 2017. From natural character to moral virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Leunissen, Mariska. 2017. From natural character to moral virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lockwood, Thornton C. 2013. Habituation, habit, and character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In A history of habit. From Aristotle to Bourdieu, eds. Tom Sparrow and Adam Hutchinson, 19–36. Lanham: Lexington Books. Lockwood, Thornton C. 2013. Habituation, habit, and character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In A history of habit. From Aristotle to Bourdieu, eds. Tom Sparrow and Adam Hutchinson, 19–36. Lanham: Lexington Books.
Zurück zum Zitat London, Alex. 2001. Moral knowledge and the acquisition of virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics. Review of Metaphysics 54: 553–583. London, Alex. 2001. Moral knowledge and the acquisition of virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics. Review of Metaphysics 54: 553–583.
Zurück zum Zitat Lorenz, Hendrik. 2009. Virtue of character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 177–212. Lorenz, Hendrik. 2009. Virtue of character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 177–212.
Zurück zum Zitat McDowell, John. 1996. Deliberation and moral development in Aristotle’s ethics. In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics. Rethinking happiness and duty, eds. Stephen P. Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, 19–35. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. McDowell, John. 1996. Deliberation and moral development in Aristotle’s ethics. In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics. Rethinking happiness and duty, eds. Stephen P. Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, 19–35. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Moss, Jessica. 2011. “Virtue makes the goal right”: Virtue and Phronesis in Aristotle’s Ethics. Phronesis 56: 204–261. Moss, Jessica. 2011. “Virtue makes the goal right”: Virtue and Phronesis in Aristotle’s Ethics. Phronesis 56: 204–261.
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, Anselm. 2004. Aristotle’s conception of ethical and natural virtue: How the unity thesis sheds light on the doctrine of the mean. In Was ist das für den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur und Güterlehre, eds. Jan Szaif and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, 18–53. Berlin: de Gruyter. Müller, Anselm. 2004. Aristotle’s conception of ethical and natural virtue: How the unity thesis sheds light on the doctrine of the mean. In Was ist das für den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur und Güterlehre, eds. Jan Szaif and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, 18–53. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, Jörn. 2006. Physis und Ethos. Der Naturbegriff bei Aristoteles und seine Relevanz für die Ethik. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. Müller, Jörn. 2006. Physis und Ethos. Der Naturbegriff bei Aristoteles und seine Relevanz für die Ethik. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, Jörn. 2013. Wann kann man ein Leben glücklich nennen? Aristoteles und das Solon-Problem. In Glück, Tugend und Zeit. Aristoteles über die Zeitstruktur des guten Lebens, ed. Walter Mesch, 41–62. Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler. Müller, Jörn. 2013. Wann kann man ein Leben glücklich nennen? Aristoteles und das Solon-Problem. In Glück, Tugend und Zeit. Aristoteles über die Zeitstruktur des guten Lebens, ed. Walter Mesch, 41–62. Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, Jörn. 2014. Was Aristotle an ethical determinist? Reflections on his theory of action and voluntariness. In Fate, providence and moral responsibility in ancient, medieval and early modern thought, eds. Pieter d’Hoine and Gerd van Riel, 75–99. Leuven: Leuven University Press. Müller, Jörn. 2014. Was Aristotle an ethical determinist? Reflections on his theory of action and voluntariness. In Fate, providence and moral responsibility in ancient, medieval and early modern thought, eds. Pieter d’Hoine and Gerd van Riel, 75–99. Leuven: Leuven University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, Jörn. 2019a. Spot the differences! The hidden philosophical anthropology in Aristotle’s biological writings. In Aristotle’s anthropology, eds. Geert Keil and Nora Kreft, 118–139. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Müller, Jörn. 2019a. Spot the differences! The hidden philosophical anthropology in Aristotle’s biological writings. In Aristotle’s anthropology, eds. Geert Keil and Nora Kreft, 118–139. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, Jörn. 2019b. ‘Learning by doing’? Aristotle on the habituation of moral character. In Aristotle on logic and nature, ed. Jan-Ivar Lindén, 177–209. Leuven: Peeters. Müller, Jörn. 2019b. ‘Learning by doing’? Aristotle on the habituation of moral character. In Aristotle on logic and nature, ed. Jan-Ivar Lindén, 177–209. Leuven: Peeters.
Zurück zum Zitat Nussbaum, Martha. 1987. Non-relative virtues: An Aristotelian approach. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13: 32–53.CrossRef Nussbaum, Martha. 1987. Non-relative virtues: An Aristotelian approach. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13: 32–53.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rapp, Christof. 2006. What use is Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean? In The virtuous life in Greek ethics, ed. Burkhard Reis, 99–126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rapp, Christof. 2006. What use is Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean? In The virtuous life in Greek ethics, ed. Burkhard Reis, 99–126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Russell, Daniel. 2014. Phronesis and the virtues (NE vi 12–13). In The Cambridge companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 203–220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Russell, Daniel. 2014. Phronesis and the virtues (NE vi 12–13). In The Cambridge companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 203–220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Russell, Daniel. 2015. Aristotle on cultivating virtue. In Cultivating virtue, ed. Nancy E. Snow, 17–48. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Russell, Daniel. 2015. Aristotle on cultivating virtue. In Cultivating virtue, ed. Nancy E. Snow, 17–48. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Santas, Gerasimos. 1996. The structure of Aristotle’s ethical theory: Is it teleological or a virtue ethics? Topoi 15: 59–80.CrossRef Santas, Gerasimos. 1996. The structure of Aristotle’s ethical theory: Is it teleological or a virtue ethics? Topoi 15: 59–80.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sherman, Nancy. 1989. The fabric of character. Aristotle’s theory of virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sherman, Nancy. 1989. The fabric of character. Aristotle’s theory of virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Sherman, Nancy. 1997. Making a necessity of virtue. Aristotle and Kant on virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Sherman, Nancy. 1997. Making a necessity of virtue. Aristotle and Kant on virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Simpson, Peter. 1992. Contemporary virtue ethics and Aristotle. Review of Metaphysics 45: 503–524. Simpson, Peter. 1992. Contemporary virtue ethics and Aristotle. Review of Metaphysics 45: 503–524.
Zurück zum Zitat Sorabji, Richard. 1980. Aristotle on the role of intellect in virtue. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty, 201–219. Berkeley: University of California Press. Sorabji, Richard. 1980. Aristotle on the role of intellect in virtue. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty, 201–219. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Telfer, Elizabeth. 1989/1990. The unity of moral virtues in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90: 35–48. Telfer, Elizabeth. 1989/1990. The unity of moral virtues in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90: 35–48.
Zurück zum Zitat Tessitore, Aristide. 1996. Reading Aristotle’s ethics. Virtue, rhetoric, and political philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press. Tessitore, Aristide. 1996. Reading Aristotle’s ethics. Virtue, rhetoric, and political philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Urmson, J. O. 1973. Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 223–230. Urmson, J. O. 1973. Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 223–230.
Zurück zum Zitat Vasiliou, Iakovos. 1996. The role of good upbringing in Aristotle’s ethics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56: 771–797.CrossRef Vasiliou, Iakovos. 1996. The role of good upbringing in Aristotle’s ethics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56: 771–797.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Whiting, Jennifer. 2002. Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 270–290.CrossRef Whiting, Jennifer. 2002. Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 270–290.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Becoming a Good Human Being: Aristotle on Virtue and Its Cultivation
verfasst von
Jörn Müller
Copyright-Jahr
2021
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-24466-8_10