Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Theory and Decision 2/2018

26.01.2018

Behavioral patterns and reduction of sub-optimality: an experimental choice analysis

verfasst von: Daniela Di Cagno, Arianna Galliera, Werner Güth, Noemi Pace

Erschienen in: Theory and Decision | Ausgabe 2/2018

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper attempts to identify behavioral patterns and compare their average success considering several criteria of bounded rationality. Experimentally observed choice behavior in various decision tasks is used to assess heterogeneity in how individual participants respond to 15 randomly ordered portfolio choices, each of which is experienced twice. Treatments differ in (not) granting probability information and in (not) eliciting aspirations. Since in our setting neither other regarding concerns nor risk attitude matter and probability of the binary chance move is (optimal) choice irrelevant, categorizing decision types relies on parameter dependence and choice adaptations. We find that most participants reduce systematically sub-optimality when following the identified criteria.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
For an analysis of the concepts of aspiration and satisficing, see the seminal contributions of Simon (1955), Siegel (1957) and Manski (2017) Sauermann and Selten (1962) and Selten (1998) for the adaptation theory (AAT). For experimental analyses, see Selten et al. (2012) and Hey et al. (2017).
 
2
To avoid other relevant concerns, see Harrison and Johnson (2006).
 
3
This induces risk neutrality in decision-making (see Roth and Malouf 1979, for an early use in bargaining).
 
4
For a critical assessment, see Selten et al. (1999) which, however, questions expected utility theory, not binary lottery incentives. Rejecting binary lottery incentives but maintaining expected utility theory is impossible.
 
5
Di Cagno et al. (2017) also analyze three control cases with \(c=0\).
 
6
The probability information is the only difference between T1 and T2.
 
7
In the experimental setting of T3 and T4 the aspiration level is set on the €14 bar probabilities and we avoid confusion with the second (complementary) bar.
 
8
Paying participants only for a random round is required by binary-lottery incentives and avoids past-earnings effects.
 
9
In a similar manner, one could check slider positions for \(i_{t^*-\tau }\le {i^*}\) with \(\tau =1,2\) to determine whether they return to the range \([0,i^*]\) via \(i_{t^*}\le {i^*}\); however, such an analysis is omitted because only too few data are available.
 
10
We adopt the \(60\%\) individual level of compliance per phase.
 
11
The reason for distinguishing phases 1 and 2 in Table 10 is that the categorization of the eight behavioral categories is independently performed for phase 1 and phase 2 data, i.e., an individual participant may belong in phase 2 to a different class than in phase 1.
 
12
Table 14 (in the Appendix A) additionally controls for whether participants switch categories from phase 1 to 2. Again, the dominant categories are those with (yes, yes, yes)-participants in both phases (41 in T1 and 31 in T2), whose average non-improving score in phase 2 is 2.68 in T1 and 2.74 in T2, i.e. slightly lower than the respective phase 2-score in Table  10.
 
13
An exception is phase 1 of T2 and the case (no, yes, yes), whose non-improving frequency score is 3.30 and thus smaller than the score of 3.46 for (yes, yes, yes).
 
14
Exceptions exist is phase 1 of T4, e.g. case (no, yes, yes) with only 7 participants whose non-improving score is 5.43, less than 6.00 for (yes, yes, yes).
 
15
Thus, we obviously cannot refer separately to phases 1 and 2 and note the greater success in phase 2 than in phase 1.
 
16
In the following analysis, as in the previous, compliance with a selected criterion is calculated based on 60% average compliance.
 
17
We admit that our method of incentivizing aspiration formation by letting participants lose all chances of earning more €14, rather than only €4 is partly responsible for the striking confirmation of satisficing, at least in phase 2 of treatments T3 and T4.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Conlisk, J. (1996). Why bounded rationality? Journal of Economic Literature, 34(2), 669–700. Conlisk, J. (1996). Why bounded rationality? Journal of Economic Literature, 34(2), 669–700.
Zurück zum Zitat Conte, A., Di Cagno, D. T., & Sciubba, E. (2015). Behavioral patterns in social networks. Economic Inquiry, 53(2), 1331–1349.CrossRef Conte, A., Di Cagno, D. T., & Sciubba, E. (2015). Behavioral patterns in social networks. Economic Inquiry, 53(2), 1331–1349.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Di Cagno, D. T., Galliera, A., Güth, W., Marzo, F., & Pace, N. (2017). (Sub) Optimality and (non) optimal satisficing in risky decision experiments. Theory and Decision, 83(2), 195–243.CrossRef Di Cagno, D. T., Galliera, A., Güth, W., Marzo, F., & Pace, N. (2017). (Sub) Optimality and (non) optimal satisficing in risky decision experiments. Theory and Decision, 83(2), 195–243.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Erev, I., & Haruvy, E. (2013). Learning and the economics of small decisions. In J. H. Kagel & A. E. Roth (Eds.), The handbook of experimental economics. Princeton University Press. Erev, I., & Haruvy, E. (2013). Learning and the economics of small decisions. In J. H. Kagel & A. E. Roth (Eds.), The handbook of experimental economics. Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fischbacher, U. (2007). z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 10(2), 171–178.CrossRef Fischbacher, U. (2007). z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 10(2), 171–178.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gigerenzer, G. (2006). Bounded and rational. In R. J. Stainton (Ed.), Contemporary debates in cognitive science Oxford. UK: Blackwell. Gigerenzer, G. (2006). Bounded and rational. In R. J. Stainton (Ed.), Contemporary debates in cognitive science Oxford. UK: Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Greiner, B. (2004). An online recruitment system for economic experiments. Published. In: Forschung und Wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003. GWDG Bericht, 63, 79–93. Greiner, B. (2004). An online recruitment system for economic experiments. Published. In: Forschung und Wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003. GWDG Bericht, 63, 79–93.
Zurück zum Zitat Harrison, G.W., & Johnson, L.T. (2006). Identifying altruismin the laboratory. In RM. Isaac, & D.D. Davis (Eds.) Experiments investigating fundraising and charitable contributors (Research in Experimental Economics, Volume 11). Emerald Group Publishing Limited. Harrison, G.W., & Johnson, L.T. (2006). Identifying altruismin the laboratory. In RM. Isaac, & D.D. Davis (Eds.) Experiments investigating fundraising and charitable contributors (Research in Experimental Economics, Volume 11). Emerald Group Publishing Limited.
Zurück zum Zitat Hey, J. D., Permana, Y., & Rochanahastin, N. (2017). When and how to satisfice: an experimental investigation. Theory and Decision, 83(3), 1–17.CrossRef Hey, J. D., Permana, Y., & Rochanahastin, N. (2017). When and how to satisfice: an experimental investigation. Theory and Decision, 83(3), 1–17.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica: Journal of the econometric society, 47(2), 263–291.CrossRef Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica: Journal of the econometric society, 47(2), 263–291.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Manski, C. F. (2017). Optimize, satisfice, or choose without deliberation? A simple minimax-regret assessment. Theory and Decision, 82(2), 1–19. Manski, C. F. (2017). Optimize, satisfice, or choose without deliberation? A simple minimax-regret assessment. Theory and Decision, 82(2), 1–19.
Zurück zum Zitat Prelec, D. (1998). The probability weighting function. Econometrica, 66(3), 497–527.CrossRef Prelec, D. (1998). The probability weighting function. Econometrica, 66(3), 497–527.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Roth, A. E., & Malouf, M. W. (1979). Game-theoretic models and the role of information in bargaining. Psychological Review, 86(6), 574–594.CrossRef Roth, A. E., & Malouf, M. W. (1979). Game-theoretic models and the role of information in bargaining. Psychological Review, 86(6), 574–594.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sauermann, H. and Selten, R., (1962). Anspruchsanpassungstheorie der unternehmung. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Staatswissenschaft/Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, (H. 4), 577–597. Sauermann, H. and Selten, R., (1962). Anspruchsanpassungstheorie der unternehmung. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Staatswissenschaft/Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, (H. 4), 577–597.
Zurück zum Zitat Selten, R. (1998). Aspiration adaptation theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 42(2–3), 191–214. Selten, R. (1998). Aspiration adaptation theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 42(2–3), 191–214.
Zurück zum Zitat Selten, R. (2001). What is bounded rationality. In G. Gigerenzer & R. Selten (Eds.), Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox. The MIT Press. Selten, R. (2001). What is bounded rationality. In G. Gigerenzer & R. Selten (Eds.), Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox. The MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Selten, R., Pittnauer, S., & Hohnisch, M. (2012). Dealing with dynamic decision problems when knowledge of the environment is limited: an approach based on goal systems. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 25(5), 443–457.CrossRef Selten, R., Pittnauer, S., & Hohnisch, M. (2012). Dealing with dynamic decision problems when knowledge of the environment is limited: an approach based on goal systems. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 25(5), 443–457.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Selten, R., Sadrieh, A., & Abbink, K. (1999). Money does not induce risk neutral behavior, but binary lotteries do even worse. Theory and Decision, 46(3), 213–252.CrossRef Selten, R., Sadrieh, A., & Abbink, K. (1999). Money does not induce risk neutral behavior, but binary lotteries do even worse. Theory and Decision, 46(3), 213–252.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Siegel, S. (1957). Level of aspiration and decision making. Psychological Review, 64(4), 253–262.CrossRef Siegel, S. (1957). Level of aspiration and decision making. Psychological Review, 64(4), 253–262.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69(1), 99–118.CrossRef Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69(1), 99–118.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Behavioral patterns and reduction of sub-optimality: an experimental choice analysis
verfasst von
Daniela Di Cagno
Arianna Galliera
Werner Güth
Noemi Pace
Publikationsdatum
26.01.2018
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Theory and Decision / Ausgabe 2/2018
Print ISSN: 0040-5833
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7187
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-018-9653-0

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2018

Theory and Decision 2/2018 Zur Ausgabe