Skip to main content

The Democratic Deficit in the (Economic) Governance of the European Union

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Common European Legal Thinking

Abstract

Common European legal thinking reveals itself especially in the existence of a common European constitutional law (Ius Publicum Europaeum Commune). It denotes the ensemble of individual constitutional principles that are – written or unwritten – a common heritage of the various national constitutional states. With regard to the principle of democracy, the Jubilee, when conducting a comparative law study, found there to be a “relatively heterogeneous picture” among national constitutions, even though one can find “core elements of a ‘common European democracy’”. According to Albrecht Weber, these include periodic elections of State institutions, legally ensured responsibility of public decision making with the possibility for parliamentary minorities to gain power as well as representative party democracy. Besides these elements, the equal participation of all governed in the exercise of public authority and constitutional freedoms is a mainstay of European “self-government”. The decision for parliamentary democracy in the European Union (Art. 10.1 TEU) is thus predetermined by the Member States’ forms of government and therefore belongs to the fundamental laws (Grundgesetze), to the “essentials” of the EU’s constitutional compound.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Vari 2013, p. 708, 719 (our translation).

  2. 2.

    This Latin terminology, that connects Hagemeier’s traditional term of “Ius Publicum Europaeum” with the attribute “Commune”, is traced back by von Bogdandy and Hinghofer‐Szalkay 2013, p. 217, to Ch. Starck. In doing so, they refer to Martínez‐Soria 2004.

  3. 3.

    Cf. Weigand 2008; Häberle 1995.

  4. 4.

    Weber 2010, Chap. 7, para 20. Well before the inclusion of the idea of a political union in the Treaties, the ECJ recognised the principle of democracy as a general legal principle; see Case 138/79, Roquette Frères (ECJ 29.10.1980) para 33.

  5. 5.

    Calliess 2005a, p. 283.

  6. 6.

    See the contribution by Cruz Villalón in this volume.

  7. 7.

    Cf. also Sommermann 2005, p. 208 et seq.; with a critical view Nettesheim 2005, p. 188, who opinioned the EU’s constitutional system “designed by an uninspired hand”. Benz 2005, p. 261 holds that a presidential rather than a parliamentary system is more suitable for the EU.

  8. 8.

    Häberle 1991, p. 262, 264.

  9. 9.

    Sommermann 1998, p. 404 et seqq.; Sommermann 2005, p. 192 et seqq.; on the whole see Wendel 2011.

  10. 10.

    Cf. BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 271 – Lisbon.

  11. 11.

    BGBl 2002 II p. 1072.

  12. 12.

    See Art. 14.3 TEU, which does not include the principle of equality of elections. Cf. Schorkopf, in Kahl et al. (2011), Art. 23 GG para 44; Hölscheidt, in Grabitz et al. (2011), Art. 223 AEUV para 47.

  13. 13.

    Cf. Act Concerning the Election of the Members of the European Parliament by Direct Universal Suffrage, Council Decision of 20 September 1976 (Federal Law Gazette 1977 II p. 733); last amended by the Council Decision of 22 June 2002 and 23 September 2002 (Federal Law Gazette 2003 II p. 810; 2004 II p. 520).

  14. 14.

    Cf. BVerfG 2 BvR 2134, 2159/92 (judgment of 12 October 1993), para 97 and 100: “At the same time, with the building‐up of the functions and powers of the Community, it becomes increasingly necessary to allow the democratic legitimation and influence provided by way of the national parliaments to be accompanied by a representation of the peoples of the member‐States through a European Parliament as the source of a supplementary democratic support for the policies of the European Union. […] In the federation of States formed by the European Union, therefore, democratic legitimation necessarily comes about through the feed‐back of the actions of the European institutions into the parliaments of the member‐States; and within the institutional structure of the Union there is the additional factor (increasing to the extent that the European nations grow closer together) of the provision of democratic legitimation by way of the European Parliament elected by the citizens of the States.”; BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 262 – Lisbon: “As long as, and in so far as, the principle of conferral is adhered to in an association of sovereign states with clear elements of executive and governmental cooperation, the legitimation provided by national parliaments and governments complemented and sustained by the directly elected European Parliament is sufficient in principle.”.

  15. 15.

    This has been the appropriate conclusion of the German Federal Constitutional Court (FCC) in its decision on the Treaty of Maastricht (BVerfGE 89, 155 [184 f.]). However, in its judgment on the Treaty of Lisbon as well as in its decisions of 9 November 2011 (BVerfGE 129, 300 – 5 % threshold for EP elections) and of 26 February 2014 (BVerfGE 2 BvE 2/13 et al. – 3 % threshold for EP elections), the FCC has erected high obstacles for the EP to evolve into a “full‐fledged parliament”. Calliess 2005a, p. 300, who already in 2005 concluded that with regard to the grown competences of the EP, the lack of a uniform and equal electoral procedure is no longer justified.

  16. 16.

    Cf. Blanke and Pilz 2014, p. 557.

  17. 17.

    Cf. Ruffert and Walter 2015, para 100; cf. also Rawls 1993, p. 214.

  18. 18.

    Blanke, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Art. 1 para 1, 4; see also Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 14.

  19. 19.

    See the contribution by Luther in this volume.

  20. 20.

    Cf. Schönberger 2004, p. 98 et seqq., 117 et seqq.; Schmidt 2005, p. 772.

  21. 21.

    Cf. e. g. Art. 3.1 and 3.2 French Constitution; Art. 20.2 first sentence German Constitution; Art. 1.2 Italian Constitution; Art. 6.1 Irish Constitution.

  22. 22.

    Schliesky 2004, p. 745; cf. also Oeter 2010, p. 67; Peters 2001, p. 657 et seqq.

  23. 23.

    Thus apparently Isensee 1997; Isensee 2009; along the same line see also Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 43 et seqq.

  24. 24.

    Cf. Schliesky 2004, p. 745; cf. also Oeter 2010, p. 71, Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 16.

  25. 25.

    Cf. Pernice 1993, p. 477 et seq.; Maurer 2013, p. 3 et seq.; in more detail Augustin 2000, especially p. 63 et seqq., 393 et seqq.; Peters 2001, p. 657 et seqq., 700 et seqq.; v. Komorowski 2010, p. 1014 et seqq., who from the perspective of the Basic Law reconstructs the model of dual legitimation as a model of off‐centred, but also territorially uniform (staatsgebietseinheitlich) people’s sovereignty.

  26. 26.

    Habermas 2001, p. 15 et seq.; cf. also Oeter 2010, p. 70.

  27. 27.

    Cf. Schorkopf, in Kahl et al. (2011), Art. 23 GG para 43, Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 14.

  28. 28.

    Scharpf 1970; Scharpf 1999; see also Zürn 1996.

  29. 29.

    See also the contribution by Tomuschat in this volume.

  30. 30.

    Cf. Ruffert and Walter 2015, para 337–338.

  31. 31.

    Cf. Höreth 1999, p. 88 et seq.

  32. 32.

    Cf. in this sense also Maurer 2012 and Maurer 2013, p. 4; see also Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 23.

  33. 33.

    On this element see Eder and Trenz 2007.

  34. 34.

    Cf. also Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 24 et seqq.

  35. 35.

    Cf. Schliesky 2004, p. 599 et seqq.

  36. 36.

    Cf. Ipsen 1972, p. 1045. With regard to the US‐American regulation commissions, G. Majone speaks of a “fourth branch of government”. He holds that also the Community Treaties have established a “fourth branch of government”, namely with the instrument of harmonisation (Art. 114 TFEU), which characterises the Union as a “regulatory State. See Majone 1994, p. 77 et seqq.; Majone 1996, passim; Majone 1998, p. 5 et seqq.; Majone 1999, p. 1 et seqq.; Majone 2001, p. 57 et seqq.; cf. in this respect also Case C‐62/14, OMT (Opinion of AG Cruz Villalón of 14 January 2015) para 109 et seqq. with regard to the European Central Bank.

  37. 37.

    Oeter 2010, p. 73, with reference to Max Weber 1918, p. 39–43, 99–105.

  38. 38.

    Glaser 2013, p. 98; cf. also Scharpf 2006.

  39. 39.

    Ipsen 1972, para 8, 24 et seqq. and 54, 124; Glaser 2013, p. 96; Nettesheim 2005, p. 166 et seq., holds that the Union is steadily on its way from functional integration to statehood.

  40. 40.

    Cf. Nettesheim 2005, p. 154 et seq., who restates the views of authors from the late 1990s, holding that input and control should be given less attention in favour of expectations of results conducive to the common good (output) (p. 181 et seq.); Nettesheim 2014, para 14.

  41. 41.

    Oeter 2010, p. 74; cf. also von Bogdandy 2012, p. 322.

  42. 42.

    See also Art. 2 of the French Constitution: gouvernement du peuple, par le peuple et pour le peuple.

  43. 43.

    Cf. Höreth 1999, p. 81 et seqq.; Schmidt 2005, p. 768.

  44. 44.

    Kohler‐Koch and Rittberger 2007, p. 13.

  45. 45.

    Grzeszick, in Maunz and Dürig (2010), Art. 20 II GG, para 12.

  46. 46.

    Böckenförde 2004, § 24, esp. para 11–25; Grzeszick, in Maunz and Dürig (2010), Art. 20 II GG, para 61; Sommermann 2005, p. 203 et seqq., proves that the doctrine of derivation is not the prevailing model in the constitutional law of the Member States of the Union. With a critical view Nettesheim 2005, p. 178, who rejects this model as “chain‐of‐legitimation fetishism” and who, not without irony, refers to Luhmann 2000, p. 36, when speaking of the inept idea of the people as a sort of overarching entity in which the miracle of the fusion of the individual wills to common will can happen.

  47. 47.

    Nettesheim 2005, p. 178; Nettesheim 2014, para 11.

  48. 48.

    Art. 23.1 GG reads as follows: “With a view to establishing a united Europe, the Federal Republic of Germany shall participate in the development of the European Union that is committed to democratic, social and federal principles, to the rule of law, and to the principle of subsidiarity, and that guarantees a level of protection of basic rights essentially comparable to that afforded by this Basic Law. To this end the Federation may transfer sovereign powers by a law [which] shall be subject to paragraphs (2) and (3) of Article 79”. According to the aforementioned paragraph 3 of Art. 79 GG, amendments to the Basic Law “affecting […] the principles laid down in Articles 1 and 20 shall be inadmissible”. Art. 79.3 GG protects the so‐called “inviolable core content of the Basic Law’s constitutional identity” which is excluded from any transfer of sovereign rights.

  49. 49.

    Di Fabio 1993, 210.

  50. 50.

    Cf. BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 228, 347, 266 et seq. – Lisbon. This view is shared by the European Commission in its letter in response to the Opinion of the House of Lords concerning the role of national Parliaments in the EU, C (2014) 4236 final of 23 June 2014. p. 3: “This general principle goes hand-in-hand with a second general principle, namely that ‘in developing EMU, the level of democratic legitimacy always needs to remain commensurate with the degree of transfer of sovereignty from Member States to the European level’.”

  51. 51.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 351 – Lisbon.

  52. 52.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 235, 239, 255 – Lisbon; see before BVerfG, 2 BvR 2134/92, 2 BvR 2159/92 (12 October 1993) para 101 – Maastricht. In the words of the FCC, in its judgment on the Treaty of Lisbon (para 249), these “essential areas of democratic formative action” include, among others, “citizenship, the civil and the military monopoly on the use of force, revenue and expenditure including external financing and all elements of encroachment that are decisive for the realisation of fundamental rights, above all in major encroachments on fundamental rights such as deprivation of liberty in the administration of criminal law or placement in an institution. These important areas also include cultural issues such as the disposition of language, the shaping of circumstances concerning the family and education, the ordering of the freedom of opinion, press and of association and the dealing with the profession of faith or ideology”.

  53. 53.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 216 – Lisbon.

  54. 54.

    Grzeszick, in Maunz and Dürig (2010), Art. 20 II GG, para 294.

  55. 55.

    Affirmatively Niedobitek 2009, p. 1271; Nettesheim 2013, p. 51 et seqq., holds that this can only be subject to a sector‐specific evaluation. He criticises the FCC for being too undifferentiated when requiring plebiscitary legitimation in every case.

  56. 56.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 113, 277 et seq., 334 – Lisbon.

  57. 57.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 281 – Lisbon; cf. also see also Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 30 et seq.

  58. 58.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 334 – Lisbon.

  59. 59.

    Cf. the wording of the German FCC, BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) – Lisbon and BVerfG, 2 BvR 2134/92, 2 BvR 2159/92 (12 October 1993) – Maastricht.

  60. 60.

    Pernice 1995, p. 261 et seqq. and Pernice 1996, Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 14: “Staaten- und Verfassungsbund”.

  61. 61.

    Cf. Schorkopf, in Kahl et al. (2011), Art. 23 GG para 42.

  62. 62.

    Cf. Calliess 2010a, p. 167 et seq.; on the problems of developing a theory of European democracy in the light of the uncertainty of the Union’s finality see Nettesheim 2005, p. 164 et seqq. (166) with reference from international literature.

  63. 63.

    Cf. Schönberger 2004, p. 87; cf. already Ipsen 1972, Chap. 9 para 63, with reference to Schmitt 1928, p. 379; see also Blanke 1993, p. 420.

  64. 64.

    Cf. Schorkopf, in Kahl et al. (2011), Art. 23 GG para 34.

  65. 65.

    Scharpf 2007, p. 9; Schmidt 2005, p. 772.

  66. 66.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 279 – Lisbon; see also the contribution by Tomuschat in this volume.

  67. 67.

    For the whole panorama of arguments about the democratic quality of the EU and on the question if there is a democratic deficit (G. Majone, R. Dahl, P. Graf Kielmansegg, A. Moravcsik, R.M. Lepsius, A. Follesdahl and S. Hix et al.) see Kohler‐Koch and Rittberger 2007, p. 6 et seqq.

  68. 68.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 265 et seqq. (272) – Lisbon; see also di Fabio 2014, p. 13.

  69. 69.

    Cf. Schorkopf, in Kahl et al. (2011), Art. 23 GG para 42.

  70. 70.

    See BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 284 – Lisbon; von Achenbach 2014, p. 426; Arndt 2008, p. 258.

  71. 71.

    Cf. Schorkopf, in Kahl et al. (2011), Art. 23 GG para 44.

  72. 72.

    The claim of an “objective” democratic deficit, with regard to both public accountability and legitimacy, is rejected by Moravcsik 2008; cf. also Schmidt 2005, p. 767.

  73. 73.

    Cf. von Bogdandy 2012, p. 322.

  74. 74.

    Habermas 2011, p. 62.

  75. 75.

    Pernice 1998, p. 40 (43 et seqq.).

  76. 76.

    Cf. Pernice 2005, p. 759 et seq.; Pernice 2002; Pernice 2009, p. 376; Peters 2001, p. 566; von Achenbach 2014, p. 416 et seq.; Uerpmann‐Wittzack, in von Münch and Kunig (2012), Art. 23 para 14–16, 18; Härtel 2014, para 85; von Bogdandy 2010, p. 48. With a view on these two entities as separate and not coinciding see BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 346 et seqq. – Lisbon.

  77. 77.

    Pernice 1999, p. 717, 720 et seqq.; von Achenbach 2014, p. 420; cf. also Pernice 2009, p. 374 et seqq.

  78. 78.

    Cf. Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 79; Joerges 2014, p. 37 et seq., with a sceptical view of the assumption of Habermas regarding a “convergence” of the European demoi and an “ever-more-Europe” option.

  79. 79.

    See also BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 249, 251 et seqq. – Lisbon.

  80. 80.

    Cf. Art. 3.1 and 3.2 of the French Constitution: “National sovereignty shall vest in the people, who shall exercise it through their representatives and by means of referendum. No section of the people nor any individual may arrogate to itself, or to himself, the exercise thereof.” Art. 1.2 of the Italian Constitution: “Sovereignty belongs to the people and is exercised by the people in the forms and within the limits of the Constitution”. Art. 6.1 of the Irish Constitution: “All powers of government, legislative, executive and judicial, derive, under God, from the people, whose right it is to designate the rulers of the State and, in final appeal, to decide all questions of national policy, according to the requirements of the common good”.

  81. 81.

    “Le principe de toute souveraineté réside essentiellement dans la nation. Nul corps, nul individu ne peut exercer d’autorité qui n’en émane expressément.”.

  82. 82.

    “La Souveraineté est une, indivisible, inaliénable et imprescriptible. Elle appartient à la Nation; aucune section du peuple, ni aucun individu, ne peut s’en attribuer l’exercice.”.

  83. 83.

    In the current Constitution of the Fifth Republic (1958) it says in the preamble: “Le peuple français proclame solennellement son attachement aux Droits de l’Homme et aux principes de la souveraineté nationale tels qu’ils ont été définis par la Déclaration de 1789, confirmée et complétée par le préambule de la Constitution de 1946 […]”. Art. 3 of the French Constitution: “La souveraineté nationale appartient au peuple qui l’exerce par ses représentants et par la voie du référendum. Aucune section du peuple ni aucun individu ne peut s’en attribuer l’exercice.” On the meaning of “nation” as subject of legitimation see Duguit 1921, § 48; Sommermann 1997, p. 86 et seq.

  84. 84.

    von Bogdandy 2010, p. 48.

  85. 85.

    Nettesheim 2005, p. 172.

  86. 86.

    Heller 1963, 176.

  87. 87.

    See Di Fabio 1993, 202 et seqq., who speaks of the European Parliament as a “State convention”; Nettesheim 2005, 170 et seqq. (172 et seq.), and others, see the chance for the formation of a political community in the Union, if it’s action is based on universalistic principles such as freedom, equality, minority protection, neutrality or the commitment to neminem laedere.

  88. 88.

    Cf. Hrbek 2012, p. 131 et seq.

  89. 89.

    Halberstam and Möllers 2009, p. 1248 et seq.; von Achenbach 2014, p. 437.

  90. 90.

    On this see Classen 2009, p. 883; cf. also Scharpf 2007, p. 6; Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 53.

  91. 91.

    Cf. Härtel 2006, § 18 para 12 et seq., who is in favour of a right of initiative for the EP; v. Komorowski 2010, p. 1080.

  92. 92.

    Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 56 et seq.

  93. 93.

    Appl. No. 24833/94, Matthews v. United Kingdom (ECtHR 18 February 1999) para 52 with regard to Art. 3.1 of the Additional Protocol No. to the ECHR.

  94. 94.

    BVerfG, 2 BvR 2134/92, 2 BvR 2159/92 (12 October 1993) para 100 – Maastricht.

  95. 95.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 265 et seqq. (271) – Lisbon. See before BVerfG, 2 BvR 2134/92, 2 BvR 2159/92 (12 October 1993) p. 18 et seq. – Maastricht. In the Maastricht judgment the judges have regarded the European Parliament’s “complementary” function in providing “the basis for democratic support for the policies of the European Union” and thus they have made the national legislative bodies the relevant organs to convey democratic legitimacy in the context of Germany’s participation in the process of European integration; see later on BVerfG, 2 BvR 2236/04 (judgment of 18 July 2005) para 81 – European Arrest Warrant.

  96. 96.

    BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 289, 278 – Lisbon; see Schönberger 2009, p. 1213 et seq.

  97. 97.

    Brosius‐Gersdorf 1999, p. 167 et seq.; Huber 2002, p. 69, para 39; Calliess 2005b, p. 314 et seq.; Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 15.

  98. 98.

    Cf. von Achenbach 2014, p. 19 et seq., 403.

  99. 99.

    von Achenbach 2014, p. 439 et seq.

  100. 100.

    Böckenförde 2004, para 16.

  101. 101.

    Rightly so Doehring 1997, p. 1133 et seq.

  102. 102.

    von Achenbach, p. 405 et seq., 441.

  103. 103.

    Mayer 2012, p. 69 et seq.

  104. 104.

    von Achenbach 2014, p. 445.

  105. 105.

    Ruffert 2004, p. 184.

  106. 106.

    This is probably meant by Weber 2010, Chap. 7, para 54, and Nettesheim 2013, p. 49.

  107. 107.

    In analogy to the criticism voiced by the German FCC with regard to the European Parliament; see BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08 et al. (judgment of 30 June 2009) para 281, 292 – Lisbon.

  108. 108.

    von Achenbach 2014, p. 443 et seq.

  109. 109.

    Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 15.

  110. 110.

    Cf. COM(2006) 211; Pierafita 2013, p. 6 et seqq.

  111. 111.

    Hrbek 2012, p. 130; cf. also Baach 2008, p. 183 et seqq., 191 et seqq.

  112. 112.

    See e. g. Pierafita 2013, p. 4 et seqq.; with a critical view De Wilde 2012.

  113. 113.

    In this respect also De Wilde 2012, p. 12.

  114. 114.

    On the relevance of these two parameters, see Blanke in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Protocol No. 2 TEU para 61 et seqq., 68 et seqq.; Kiiver 2006, p. 162: “and other criteria”.

  115. 115.

    Kiiver 2006, p. 158 et seqq. who speaks in terms of a “COSAC subsidiarity experiment” and the “phantom collective”.

  116. 116.

    Since the entry into force of the Treaty of Lisbon, 318 reasoned opinions have been issued by national Parliaments/chambers under the Article 6 procedure. The Swedish parliament has issued a total of 51, the Dutch House of Representative 20, the Dutch Senate 17 and the French Senate 21. Germany accounts for 13 reasoned opinions, of which 10 originate from the Bundesrat and only 3 from the Bundestag. However, it is difficult to establish whether these reasoned opinions find there to be an infringement of the principle of subsidiarity, as foreseen by Art. 6 of Protocol No. 2 TEU, or if they claim there to be other shortcomings of the draft, such as the material scope, content etc. Conversely, since 2006 a total of 1,174 opinions have been issued under the (informal) “political dialogue” initiated by the Commission (data as of 18 February 2015).; on the latter see Casalena, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Protocol No. 1 TEU para 18.

  117. 117.

    Kiiver 2006, p. 158 et seqq. who speaks in terms of a “COSAC subsidiarity experiment” and the “phantom collective”.

  118. 118.

    Kiiver 2006, p. 168.

  119. 119.

    Cf. Stratulat et al. 2014, p. 6 et seq.

  120. 120.

    UK House of Lords, Evidence taken before the Select Committee on the European Union, Inquiry on “Renegotiation and Referendum on UK Membership of the EU”, 30 June 2015, evidence by Mr David Lidington MP, p. 27.

  121. 121.

    This is a crucial point within the approach by British Prime Minister D. Cameron for the reform of the EU: “…National parliaments able to work together to block unwanted European legislation…”; see The Telegraph (telegraph.co.uk) of 15 March 2014, “The EU is not working and we will change it“. A similar idea had been voiced by then British Foreign Secretary W. Hague at a speech given on 31 March 2013 in Neuhardenberg near Berlin: ″Maybe we should go ahead and think about a red card, granting national Parliaments the right to block EU legislation.”

  122. 122.

    Norton 1984, p. 201 distinguishes the types of parliaments (policy‐making, policy‐influencing and advisory). In recent literature cf. Buzogány and Stuchlik 2012, S. 359 et seq.; on the Danish model see Buche 2013, p. 367 et seqq. and Finke and Melzer 2012; cf. (without an analysis of the Baltic States) Mayer 2012, p. 177 et seqq., 210. Participation rights of the national Parliaments in Finland, Ireland, Malta, the Czech Republic and in some respect in Hungary, Poland and Slovenia are similar to those of the German Bundestag (Sect. 5.3); see Grabenwarter 2011, p. 112.

  123. 123.

    Cf. BVerfG – 2 BvE 2/08 (30 June 2009) para 246, referring to BVerfG – 2 BvR 2134/92 – Maastricht. As a result of this judgment the German Bundestag has enacted the “Act on the Exercise by the Bundestag and by the Bundesrat of their Responsibility for Integration in Matters concerning the European Union” of 22 September 2009 (BGBl. I, p. 3022), amended by Art. 1 of the law of 1 December 2009 (BGBl. I, p. 3822).

  124. 124.

    Fasone and Lupo, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Protocol No. 1 para 179; Kiiver 2005, p. 168, with a negative perspective.

  125. 125.

    Benz and Auel 2007, p. 57; Benz 2005, p. 276, therefore prefers an ex post control by national Parliaments.

  126. 126.

    See Weber 2011, p. 936; Weber 2013, p. 378 et seq.

  127. 127.

    Cf. Deubner 2014, p. 24.

  128. 128.

    Deubner 2014, p. 25.

  129. 129.

    Cf. most recently BVerfG, 2 BvR 1390/12 et al. (judgment of 18 March 2014) – ESM, for example para 163.

  130. 130.

    Cf. Deubner 2014, p. 35: “serious gap in parliamentary attendance”.

  131. 131.

    European Commission, Ex ante coordination of plans for major economic policy reforms, COM(2013) 166 and European Commission, The introduction of a Convergence and Competitiveness Instrument, COM(2013) 165.

  132. 132.

    European Parliament resolution of 23 May 2013 on future legislative proposals on EMU: response to the Commission communications, P7_TA(2013)0222, point 5.

  133. 133.

    P7_TA(2013)0222, point 7.

  134. 134.

    P7_TA(2013)0222, point 16.

  135. 135.

    Bauer 2005, p. 9; Sommermann 2005, p. 216 et seq., also sees parliamentary countermovements in some Member States; for the “increasingly compound and accumulated ‘order’ of executive power in Contemporary Europe”; see also Curtin 2014, p. 206 et seqq.; but in her opinion, “there is no single, comprehensive and unitary European executive institution or body that can in any meaningful way be described as an EU government…” (“fragmentation”).

  136. 136.

    See also Kadelbach 2013, p. 495 et seq.; Pinon 2013.

  137. 137.

    Cf. Mangiameli 2013, sub 3 b, d, e.

  138. 138.

    Cf. Maurer 2013, p. 5 et seqq.

  139. 139.

    The institutional binding effect of a treaty revision would naturally be greater than the durability of a treaty under public international law, notwithstanding Art. 62 VCLT; with the same view apparently Kingreen 2015.

  140. 140.

    Cf. Weber 2013, p. 381 et seqq.; Mangiameli 2013, sub 4 b, c, d; on the political development of the participation of national Parliaments in European policy‐making up to the Constitutional Treaty cf. Maurer 2002.

  141. 141.

    European Parliament resolution of 20 November 2012, P7‐TA‐2012‐430, Recommendation 2.7 on ensuring democratic oversight of the ESM. The Parliament adds, that “key decisions, such as the granting of financial assistance to a Member State and the conclusion of memorandums, should be subject to proper scrutiny by the European Parliament.” See also European Parliament resolution of 12 June 2013 on strengthening European democracy in the future EMU, P7_TA‐PROV(2013)0269, point 11.

  142. 142.

    European Commission, A blueprint for a deep and genuine economic and monetary union. Launching a European debate, COM(2012) 777 final/2, p. 36 et seq.

  143. 143.

    European Parliament resolution of 12 June 2013 on strengthening European democracy in the future EMU, P7_TA‐PROV(2013)0269, point 10; see most recently, European Commision, 5‐Presidents‐Report ‘Completing Europe’s Economic and Monetary Union’, 2015, p. 17.

  144. 144.

    Blanke 2011, p. 402 et seqq.

  145. 145.

    Nettesheim 2013, p. 49.

  146. 146.

    Nettesheim 2013, p. 41 et seq.

  147. 147.

    Nettesheim 2013, p. 47 et seqq.

  148. 148.

    Nettesheim 2005, p. 172, 154; Nettesheim 2013, p. 44.

  149. 149.

    Nettesheim 2005, p. 180 et seqq., p. 184; Nettesheim 2014, para 18; Sommermann 2005, p. 220 et seq.

  150. 150.

    Cf. on the call for stronger participation of the citizens Huber 1999, p. 34, 55; Benz 2005, p. 274.

  151. 151.

    Cf. in the case of Germany BVerfG, 2 BvR 1390/12 et al. (judgment of 18 March 2014) para 162 – ESM.

  152. 152.

    Deubner 2014, p. 33 et seq.; Stratulat et al. 2014, p. 7 et seq.; Kreilinger 2013, p. 21.

  153. 153.

    Similarly De Wilde 2012, p. 4, 8 et seq. and Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 52.

  154. 154.

    Corbett 2013.

  155. 155.

    Kiiver 2006, p. 162 who emphasises the right of the national Parliaments to scrutinise “proportionality and other criteria” notwithstanding the fact that in his opinion there is “no protocol or treaty provision authorizing […] to do so”.

  156. 156.

    Cf. Sects. 5–9 EUZBBG on the broad range of matters that activate the Bundestag’s right to early notification and involvement by the federal government as well as to deliver opinions to the federal government. A sign of the mainly weak role of national Parliaments beyond matters concerning the European Union stricto sensu is the fact that only four national Parliaments (Finland, Estonia, Germany and The Netherlands) had to consent to the bilateral financial aid for Greece (international treaty).

  157. 157.

    See the instructive study conducted by Auel and Tacea 2014.

  158. 158.

    Cf. Denza, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Art. 48 para 51; Casalena, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Protocol No. 1 TEU para 96.

  159. 159.

    Olivetti, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Art. 12 para 72.

  160. 160.

    Cf. Grabenwarter 2011, p. 110.

  161. 161.

    Raunio 2005, p. 322 et seq.

  162. 162.

    Cf. Mayer 2012, p. 191.

  163. 163.

    Cf. Møller Sousa 2008, p. 432.

  164. 164.

    Cf. Mayer 2012, p. 197 et seq.

  165. 165.

    Cf. Baach 2008, p. 183 et seqq.; von Achenbach 2014, p. 442 et seq.; see also Dann 2004, p. 254 et seqq., who regards the collision of the logic of negotiation and decision making in the Council with effective parliamentary participation on the basis of the model of executive federalism (p. 269), which is founded on efficient, flexible negotiation and compromise (p. 95 et seqq.); on structural problems of control of international organisations or institutions by national Parliaments see Krajewski 2008, para 14.

  166. 166.

    Finke and Melzer 2012, p. 10.

  167. 167.

    Auel and Benz 2005, p. 373; cf. also Møller Sousa 2008, p. 434 et seq.; Mayer 2012, p. 207 et seqq.

  168. 168.

    Act on the Exercise by the Bundestag and by the Bundesrat of their Responsibility for Integration in Matters concerning the European Union (Integrationsverantwortungsgesetz – BGBl. I p. 3022) as amended by Art. 1 of the Act of 1 December 2009 (BGBl. I p. 3822); cf. Casalena, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Protocol No. 1 TEU para 100; on the whole see also Calliess 2014, Part 3, C, para 32 et seqq.

  169. 169.

    Section 8 (4) EUZBBG (emphasis added): “If the Bundestag avails itself of the opportunity to deliver an opinion […], the Federal Government shall invoke the requirement of prior parliamentary approval in the negotiations if the main interests expressed in the decision of the Bundestag cannot be asserted. The Federal Government shall notify the Bundestag thereof without delay in a special report. In its form and content, this report must lend itself to discussion by the bodies of the Bundestag. Before the final decision, the Federal Government shall endeavour to reach agreement with the Bundestag. […] The foregoing provisions shall not prejudice the right of the Federal Government, in awareness of the Bundestag’s opinion, to take divergent decisions for good reasons of foreign or integration policy.”.

  170. 170.

    Section 5 (2) EUZBLG (emphasis added): “To the extent that a project primarily affects the legislative powers of the Länder and the Federation has no legislative power, or a project primarily affects the structure of Land authorities, or the Land administrative procedures, the position of the Bundesrat shall be given the greatest possible respect in determining the Federation’s position […]. This is without prejudice to the responsibility of the Federation for the nation as a whole, including matters of foreign, defence and integration policy. […] If agreement with the Federal Government is not reached and the Bundesrat confirms its opinion by a majority of two thirds, the Bundesrat’s opinion is decisive. In matters that may result in increased expenditures or reduced revenues for the Federation, the consent of the Federal Government shall be required.”.

  171. 171.

    Cf. Saberzadeh, in von Arnauld and Hufeld (2011), Chap. 11 para 34 et seq.

  172. 172.

    Cf. Saberzadeh, in von Arnauld and Hufeld (2011), Chap. 11 para 42 with further reference.

  173. 173.

    Calliess 2010b, p. 23.

  174. 174.

    Cf. U. Guérot and R. Menasse, Es lebe die europäische Republik, F.A.Z. of 24 March 2013, p. 24; M. Roth, Der Euro braucht ein Parlament, 17 November 2011.

  175. 175.

    Cf. See The Spinelli Group/Bertelsmann Stiftung, A Fundamental Law of the European Union, 2013; cf. also Andrew Duff (who was a member of the Federalists project group), A Fundamental Law of the European Union, Speech to the Federal Trust in London on 10 January 2012, http://www.fedtrust.co.uk/filepool/Andrew_Duff_Speech_10thJanuary2013.pdf

  176. 176.

    See for example Future of Europe Group of the Foreign Ministers of Austria, Belgium, Denmark, France, Italy, Germany, Luxembourg, the Netherlands, Poland, Portugal and Spain, Final Report of 17 September 2012; cf. also Deubner 2014, p. 41.

  177. 177.

    Emphasis added. Cf. also Maurer 2013, p. 6.

  178. 178.

    See Parliamentary Resolution on a proposal for a modification of the Act concerning the election of the members of the European Parliament by direct universal suffrage of 20 September 1976 (2009/2134(INI)), A7‐0027/2012. For genuine European (transnational) elections see Franzius and Preuß 2012, p. 118 et seqq.

  179. 179.

    Cf. J. Fischer, Die ZEIT of 10 November 2011; see also Deubner 2014, p. 42.

  180. 180.

    See with a similar idea Kadelbach 2013, p. 499 et seqq.

  181. 181.

    This is the criticism with regard to the general idea of a national chamber at EU level voiced by Corbett 2013.

  182. 182.

    Cf. Mangiameli 2013, sub 4 b, c, d.

  183. 183.

    Cf. the speech delivered by J. Fischer 2000 and by T. Blair, Rede vor der Warschauer Börse v. 6.10.2000, http://www.europa-digital.de/aktuell/dossier/reden/blair.shtml

  184. 184.

    L. Jospin, L’Avenir de l’Europe, 28.5.2001.

  185. 185.

    Cf. Mayer 2012, p. 554 et seq.

  186. 186.

    Cf. however the position of Valéry Giscard d’Estaing, who declared already in June 2011: “Or, le Parlement européen n’est pas directement en contact avec le milieu politique des Etats : c’est un milieu européen en fait. Il faudrait donc faire un congrès une fois par an – je crois que je suis raisonnable – avec les députés européens et deux fois plus de députés nationaux choisis selon les mêmes critères de représentation.” (http://www.euractiv.fr/avenir-europe/valery-giscard-destaing-leurope-interview-506089).

  187. 187.

    Cf. Blanke 2013, sub 4; already before the Constitutional Convention Blanke 2002; the idea of a Euro‐Chamber is also rejected by Maurer 2013, p. 8.

  188. 188.

    Cf. also Fasone, in Blanke and Mangiameli (2013), Protocol No. 1 TEU para 159.

  189. 189.

    Cf. Becker 2013.

  190. 190.

    See Kreilinger 2013, p. 4 et seqq.

  191. 191.

    Cf. Maurer 2013, p. 11 et seqq.; See Kreilinger 2013, p. 6 et seq.

  192. 192.

    Decision 13.

  193. 193.

    Cf. Mayer 2012, p. 170 with further reference in footnote 110.

  194. 194.

    In that sense Mayer 2012, p. 173.

  195. 195.

    Cf. Maurer 2013, p. 10 et seqq.; see also Kreilinger 2013, p. 8 et seqq.

  196. 196.

    Maurer 2013, p. 11.

  197. 197.

    Norman 2003, p. 98.

  198. 198.

    European Commission, A blueprint for a deep and genuine economic and monetary union. Launching a European debate, COM(2012) 777 final/2, p. 36.

  199. 199.

    Cf. Deubner 2014, p. 37 et seqq.

  200. 200.

    With this proposal Maurer 2013, p. 13.

  201. 201.

    Cf. See Kreilinger 2013, p. 17.

  202. 202.

    Peidrafita 2013, p. 8.

  203. 203.

    Cf. Kiiver 2006, p. 185 et seqq.

  204. 204.

    Danish Folketing, Twenty-three Recommendations – to strengthen the role of national parliaments in a changing European governance, January 2014, p. 2–3; UK House of Lords, European Union Committee, Report on “The Role of National Parliaments in the European Union” of 24 March 2014, para 55; Dutch Tweede Kamer, “Ahead in Europe. On the role of the Dutch House of Representatives and national parliaments in the European Union” see the final report on “democratic legitimacy” of 9 May 2014, p. 29; Lord Boswell of Aynho (Chairperson of the UK House of Lords European Union Committee), letter of 28 January 2015 to the national parliaments’ European Affairs Committees, “Towards a ‘green card’”.

  205. 205.

    COSAC, Twenty-second Bi-annual Report, 4 November 2014, p. 33 et seqq.; Twenty-third Bi-annual Report, 6 May 2015, p. 31 et seqq.

  206. 206.

    European Commission, letter in response to the Opinion of the House of Lords concerning the role of national Parliaments in the EU, C(2014) 4236 final of 23 June 2014. p. 2.

  207. 207.

    Kiiver 2006, p. 187.

  208. 208.

    On the term see Cooper 2006, p. 283; Cooper 2012, p. 441 et seq.; Joerges 2014, p. 40 et seq., with a similar account.

  209. 209.

    See for example the speech delivered by the Italian President Napolitano in October 2012: http://www.italianieuropei.it/italianieuropei-9-2012/item/2806-unione-politica-ed-europeizzazione-della-politica.html

  210. 210.

    European Parliament resolution of 20 November 2012, P7‐TA‐2012‐430, Decision 13.

  211. 211.

    Cf. Wagener and Eger 2014, Chap. 11.

  212. 212.

    With the same result Maurer 2013, p. 6.

  213. 213.

    Cf. European Parliament resolution of 20 November 2012, P7‐TA‐2012‐430, Decisions no. 1 and 13. Cf. also Decision no. 9: “The European Parliament [c]onsiders a substantial improvement of the democratic legitimacy and accountability at Union level of the EMU governance by an increased role of Parliament as an absolute necessity and a precondition for any further step toward a banking union, a fiscal union and an economic union” See most recently, European Commission, 5-Presidents-Report ‘Completing Europe’s Economic and Monetary Union’, 2015, p. 17.

  214. 214.

    Benz 2005, p. 276.

  215. 215.

    Cf. Lord 2007, p. 150 who adds, that “the representative qualities of parliamentary policies can be achieved by filtering bottom‐up initiatives”.

References

  • von Achenbach, J. (2014). Demokratische Gesetzgebung in der Europäischen Union. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Arnauld, A., & Hufeld, U. (Eds.). (2011). Systematischer Kommentar zu den Lissabon-Begleitgesetzen. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arndt, F. (2008). Ausrechnen statt aushandeln: Rationalitätsgewinne durch ein formalisiertes Modell für die Bestimmung der Zusammensetzung des Europäischen Parlaments. ZaöRV, 247–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustin, A. (2000). Das Volk der Europäischen Union. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Auel, K., & Tacea, A. (2014). Fighting Back? And if yes, how? Measuring Parliamentary Strength and Activity in EU Affairs. In C. Hefftler, C. Neuhold, O. Rozenberg, J. Smith, & W. Wessels (Eds.), Palgrave handbook on national parliaments and the European Union. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baach, F. (2008). Parlamentarische Mitwirkung in Angelegenheiten der Europäischen Union. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, H. (2005). Demokratie in Europa – Einführende Problemskizze. In H. Bauer, P. M. Huber, & K.-P. Sommermann (Eds.), Demokratie in Europa (pp. 1–20). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, P. (2013). Die Subsidiaritätsprüfung in Bundestag und Bundesrat – ein rechtliches oder ein politisches Instrument? ZPol, 5–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benz, A. (2005). Politikwissenschaftliche Diskurse über demokratisches Regieren. In H. Bauer, P. M. Huber, & K.-P. Sommermann (Eds.), Demokratie in Europa (pp. 253–280). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benz, A., & Auel, K. (2007). Expanding National Parliamentary Control: Does it Enhance European Democracy?. In B. Kohler-Koch, & B. Rittberger (Eds.), Debating the democratic legitimacy of the European Union (pp. 57–74). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J. (1993). Der Unionsvertrag von Maastricht – Ein Schritt auf dem Weg zu einem europäischen Bundesstaat. DÖV, 412–423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J. (2002). Essentialia einer europäischen Verfassungsurkunde. ThürVBl, 197–203, 224–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J. (2011). The European Economic and Monetary Union – between vulnerability and reform. International Journal of Public Law and Policy, 402–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J. (2013). The Role of national Parliaments in the European Union, Evidence given to the House of Lords (September 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J., & Mangiameli, S. (Eds.). (2013). The Treaty on European Union (TEU) – A Commentary. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J., & Pilz, S. (2014). Solidarische Finanzhilfen als Lackmustest föderaler Balance in der Europäischen Union. EuR 541–566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Böckenförde, E.-W. (2004). § 24, Demokratie als Verfassungsprinzip. In J. Isensee, & P. Kirchhof (Eds.), Handbuch des Staatsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland 3rd edn. vol. II Heidelberg: Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy, A. (2010). Founding Principles. In A.von Bogdandy, & J. Bast (Eds.), Principles of European Constitutional Law (2nd edn., pp. 11–54). Oxford, Munich, Baden-Baden: Hart, C.H.Beck, Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy, A. (2012). The European Lesson for International Democracy. EJIL, 315–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy, A., & Hinghofer-Szalkay, S. (2013). Das etwas unheimliche Ius Publicum Europaeum. ZaöRV, 209–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brosius-Gersdorf, F. (1999). Die doppelte Legitimationsbasis der Europäischen Union. EuR, 133–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buche, J. (2013). Europäisierung parlamentarischer Kontrolle im Norden Europas: Dänemark, Finnland und Schweden im Vergleich. In B. Eberbach-Born, S. Kropp, A. Stuchlik, & W. Zeh (Eds.), Parlamentarische Kontrolle und Europäische Union (pp. 367–395). Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzogány, A., & Stuchlik, A. (2012). Subsidiarität und Mitsprache. Nationale Parlamente nach Lissabon. ZParl, 356–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calliess, C. (2005a). Optionen zur Demokratisierung der Europäischen Union. In H. Bauer, P. M. Huber, & K.-P. Sommermann (Eds.), Demokratie in Europa (pp. 281–318). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calliess, C. (2005b). Das Demokratieprinzip im Europäischen Staaten- und Verfassungsverbund. In J. Bröhmer, & R. Bieber (Eds.), Internationale Gemeinschaft und Menschenrechte. Festschrift für Georg Ress (pp. 399–421). Cologne: Heymanns.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calliess, C. (2010a). Die neue Europäische Union nach dem Vertrag von Lissabon. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calliess, C. (2010b). Nach dem Lissabon-Urteil des Bundesverfassungsgerichts: Parlamentarische Integrationsverantwortung auf europäischer und nationaler Ebene. ZG, 25(1), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calliess, C. (2014). Staatsrecht III. Bezüge zum Völker- und Europarecht. Munich: C.H.Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Classen, C. D. (2009). Legitime Stärkung des Bundestages oder verfassungsrechtliches Prokrustesbett? JZ, 881–889.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, I. (2006). The Watchdogs of Subsidiarity: National Parliaments and the Logic of Arguing in the EU. JCMS, 281–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, I. (2012). A ‘Virtual Third Chamber’ for the European Union? National Parliaments after the Treaty of Lisbon. West European Politics, 441–465.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbett, R. (2013). The Role of national Parliaments in the European Union, Evidence given to the House of Lords (September 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  • Curtin, D. (2014). Challenging Executive Dominance in European Democracy. In C. Joerges, & C. Glinski (Eds.). The European Crisis and the Transformation of Transnational Governance. Authoritarian Managerialism versus Democratic Governance (pp. 203–226). Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dann, P. (2004). Parlamente im Exekutivföderalismus. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deubner, C. (2014). Stärkere Parlamente in der neuen WWU-Gouvernanz? integration, 21–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Wilde, P. (2012). Why the Early Warning Mechanism does not Alleviate the Democratic Deficit. OPAL Online Paper (6/2012).

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Fabio, U. (1993). Der neue Art. 23 des Grundgesetzes. Der Staat, 191–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Fabio, U. (2014). Entwicklungsperspektiven für das Europäische Parlament. ZSE, 9–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doehring, K. (1997). Demokratiedefizit in der Europäischen Union? DVBl, 1133–1137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duguit, L. (1921). Traité de droit constitutionnel (2nd edn.). vol. I. Paris: Ancienne Libr. Fontemoing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, K., & Trenz, H.-J. (2007). Prerequisites of Transnational Democracy and Mechanisms for Sustaining it: The Case of the European Union. In B. Kohler-Koch, & B. Rittberger (Eds.), Debating the democratic legitimacy of the European Union (pp. 165–181). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finke, D., & Melzer, M. (2012). Parliamentary Scrutiny of EU Law Proposals in Denmark: Why do Governments request a Negotiation Mandate? Reihe Politikwissenschaft, vol. 127. Vienna: Institut für Höhere Studien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. (2000). Vom Staatenverbund zur Föderation – Gedanken über die Finalität der europäischen Integration. integration, 149–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franzius, C., & Preuß, U. K. (2012). Die Zukunft der europäischen Demokratie. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glaser, K. (2013). Über legitime Herrschaft. Grundlagen der Legitimitätstheorie. Wiesbaden: Springer VS.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grabenwarter, C. (2011). National Constitutional Law Relating to the European Union. In A. von Bogdandy, & J. Bast (Eds.), Principles of European Constitutional Law (2nd edn., pp. 11–54). Oxford, Munich, Baden-Baden: Hart, C.H.Beck, Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häberle, P. (1991). Gemeineuropäisches Verfassungsrecht. EuGRZ, 261–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häberle, P. (1995). Gemeineuropäisches Verfassungsrecht. In R. Bieber, & P. Widmer (Eds.), L’espace constitutionnel européen (pp. 361–389). Zurich: Schulthess.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2001). Why Europe needs a Constitution. New Left Review, 5–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2011). Zur Verfassung Europas. Berlin: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halberstam, D., & Möllers, C. (2009). The German Constitutional Court says “Ja zu Deutschland!” GLJ, 1241–1258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Härtel, I. (2006). Handbuch Europäische Rechtsetzung. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Härtel, I. (2014). § 11, Gesetzgebungsordnung der Europäischen Union. In A. Hatje, & P.-C. Müller-Graff (Eds.), Enzyklopädie Europarecht vol. I Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, H. (1963). Staatslehre (3rd edn.). Leiden: Sijthoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höreth, M. (1999). Die Europäische Union im Legitimitätstrilemma. Zur Rechtfertigung des Regierens jenseits der Staatlichkeit. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hrbek, R. (2012). The Role of National Parliaments in the EU. In H.-J. Blanke, & S. Mangiameli (Eds.), The European Union after Lisbon (pp. 129–158). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, P. M. (1999). Demokratie ohne Volk oder Demokratie der Völker? Zur Demokratiefähigkeit der Europäischen Union. In J. Drexl, K. F. Kreuzer, D. H. Scheuing, & U. Sieber (Eds.), Europäische Demokratie (pp. 27–57). Baden Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, P. M. (2002). Recht der europäischen Integration. Munich: Vahlen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ipsen, H. P. (1972). Europäisches Gemeinschaftsrecht. Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isensee, J. (1997). Nationalstaat und Verfassungsstaat – wechselseitige Bedingtheit. In R. Stober (Ed.), Recht und Recht. Festschrift für Gerd Roellecke (pp. 137–163). Stuttgart et al.: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isensee, J. (2009). Europa der Nationen oder europäische Nation – Von Grund und Ziel kontinentaler Organisation. In M. Herdegen, H.-H. Klein, H.-J. Papier, & R. Scholz (Eds.), Staatsrecht und Politik. Festschrift für Roman Herzog (pp. 131–153). Munich: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joerges, C. (2014). Three Transformations of Europe and the Search for a Way Out of its crisis. In C. Joerges, & C. Glinski (Eds.), The European Crisis and the Transformation of Transnational Governance. Authoritarian Managerialism versus Democratic Governance. (pp. 25–46) Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadelbach, S. (2013). Lehren aus der Finanzkrise – Ein Vorschlag zur Reform der Politischen Institutionen der Europäischen Union. EuR, 489–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahl, W., Waldhoff, C., & Walter, C. (Eds.). (2011). Bonner Kommentar zum Grundgesetz. Loose-leaf. Heidelberg: C.F. Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiiver, P. (2006). The National Parliaments in the European Union: A Critical View on EU Constitution-Building. The Hague: Kluwer Law International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingreen, T. (2015). Die Stunde der europäischen Legislative. Legal Tribune Online (19.2.2015).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohler-Koch, B., & Rittberger, B. (2007). Charting Crowded Territory: Debating the Democratic Legitimacy of the European Union. In B. Kohler-Koch, & B. Rittberger (Eds.), Debating the democratic legitimacy of the European Union (pp. 1–29). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Komorowski, A. (2010). Demokratieprinzip und Europäische Union. Berlin: Duncker & Humblodt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krajewski, M. (2008). International Organizations or Institutions, Democratic Legitimacy. In R. Wolfrum (Ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreilinger, V. (2013). The New Inter-Parliamentary Conference For Economic and Financial Governance. Notre Europe Policy Paper No. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C. (2007). Parliamentary Representation in a Decentered Polity. In B. Kohler-Koch, & B. Rittberger (Eds.), Debating the democratic legitimacy of the European Union (pp. 139–156). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (2000). Die Politik der Gesellschaft. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majone, G. (1994). The Rise of the Regulatory State in Europe. West European Politics, 77–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majone, G. (Ed.). (1996). Regulating Europe. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majone, G. (1998). Europe’s ‘Democratic Deficit’: The Question of Standards. ELJ, 5–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majone, G. (1999). The Regulatory State and Its Legitimacy Problems. West European Politics, 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majone, G. (2001). Non majoritarian Institutions and the Limits of Democratic Governance: A Political Transaction-Cost Approach. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 57–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mangiameli, S. (2013). The role of National Parliaments in the European Union. Evidence given to the House of Lords (September 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  • Martínez-Soria, J. (2004). Die Neue Europäische Union – Erste Tagung der Societas Iuris Publici Europaei (SIPE). JZ, 1164–1165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, A. (2002). Nationale Parlamente in der Europäischen Union – Herausforderung für den Konvent. integration, 20–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, A. (2012). Parlamente in der EU. Vienna: Facultas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, A. (2013). From EMU to DEMU: The Democratic Legitimacy of the EU and the European Parliament. IAI Working Papers 13/11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, M. (2012). Die Europafunktion der nationalen Parlamente in der Europäischen Union. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Møller Sousa, M. (2008). Learning in Denmark? The Case of Danish Parliamentary Control over European Union Policy. Scandinavian Political Studies, 428–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, A. (2008). The Myth of Europe’s Democratic Deficit. Intereconomics, 331–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Münch, & Kunig (Eds.). (2012). Grundgesetz-Kommentar (6th edn.). Munich: C.H.Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nettesheim, M. (2005). Demokratisierung der Europäischen Union und Europäisierung der Demokratietheorie – Wechselwirkungen bei der Herausbildung eines europäischen Demokratieprinzips. In H. Bauer, P. M. Huber, & K.-P. Sommermann (Eds.), Demokratie in Europa (pp. 143–190). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nettesheim, M. (2013). Demokratische Legitimation und Vertrauenskultur: zu den Grenzen majoritären Entscheidens in der EU. In M. Niedobitek, & K.-P. Sommermann (Eds.), Die Europäische Union als Wertegemeinschaft (pp. 39–56). Berlin: Duncker & Humblodt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nettesheim, M. (2014). § 15. Rechtsstaatliche Demokratie in der EU. In T. Oppermann, C. D. Classen, & M. Nettesheim (Eds.), Europarecht 6th edn. Munich: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niedobitek, M. (2009). The Lisbon Case of 30 June 2009 – A Comment from the European Law Perspective. GLJ, 1267–1276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, P. (2003). The Accidental Constitution: The Story of the European Constitution. Brussels: EuroComment.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, P. (1984). Parliament and policy in Britain: the House of Commons as a policy influencer. Teaching Politics, 13(2), 198–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oeter, S. (2010). Federalism and Democracy. In A.von Bogdandy, & J. Bast (Eds.), Principles of European Constitutional Law (2nd edn., pp. 55–82). Oxford, Munich, Baden-Baden: Hart, C.H.Beck, Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piedrafita, S. (2013). EU Democratic Legitimacy and National Parliaments. CEPS Essay No. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (1993). Maastricht, Staat und Demokratie. Die Verwaltung, 449–488.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (1995). Bestandssicherung der Verfassungen: Verfassungsrechtliche Mechanismen zur Wahrung der Verfassungsordnung. In R. Bieber, & P. Widmer (Eds.), L’espace constitutionnel européen (pp. 225–264). Zurich: Schulthess.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (1996). Die Dritte Gewalt im Europäischen Verfassungsverbund. EuR, 26–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (1998). Constitutional Law Implications for a State Participating in a Process of Regional Integration. In E. Riedel (Ed.), German Reports on Public Law Presented to the XV. International Congress on Comparative Law (pp. 40–64). Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (1999). Multilevel Constitutionalism and the Treaty of Amsterdam: European Constitution-Making Revisited? CMLR, 703–750.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (2002). Multilevel Constitutionalism in the European Union. ELRev, 511–529.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (2005). Zur Finalität Europas. In G. F. Schuppert, I. Pernice, & U. Haltern (Eds.), Europawissenschaft (pp. 743–792). Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pernice, I. (2009). The Treaty of Lisbon: Multilevel Constitutionalism in Action. Columbia Journal of European Law, 349–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, A. (2001). Elemente einer Theorie der Verfassung Europas. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pierafita, S. (2013). EU Democratic Legitimacy and National Parliaments. CEPS Essay 7/2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinon, S. (2013). Crise économique européenne et crise institutionelle à tous les étages. Revue de l’Union Européenne, 218–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruffert, M. (2004). Schlüsselfragen der Europäischen Verfassung der Zukunft: Grundrechte Institutionen – Kompetenzen – Ratifizierung. EuR, 165–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruffert, M., & Walter, C. (2015). Institutionalisiertes Völkerrecht (2nd edn.). Munich: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raunio, T. (2005). Holding Governments Accountable in European Affairs: Explaining Cross-national Variation. The Journal of Legislative Studies, 319–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, F. W. (1970). Demokratietheorie zwischen Utopie und Anpassung. Konstanz: Univ. Verl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, F. W. (1999). Regieren in Europa. Effektiv und demokratisch? Frankfurt: Campus-Verl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, F. W. (2006). Problem Solving Effectiveness and Democratic Accountability in the EU. Reihe Politikwissenschaft, vol. 107. Vienna: Institut für Höhere Studien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, F. W. (2007). Reflections on Multilevel Legitimacy. MPIfG Working Paper No. 07/3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesky, U. (2004). Souveränität und Legitimität von Herrschaftsgewalt. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, V. (2005). Democracy in Europe: The Impact of European Integration. Perspectives on Politics, 3(4), 761–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. (1928). Verfassungslehre. Munich: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitz, T. (2012). § 84 Staatsvolk und Unionsvolk in der föderalen Supranationalen Union. In I. Härtel (Ed.), Handbuch Föderalismus (vol. IV, pp. 261–289). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schönberger, C. (2004). Die Europäische Union als Bund. AöR, 81–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schönberger, C. (2009). Lisbon in Karlsruhe: Maastricht’s Epigones At Sea. GLJ,1201–1218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommermann, K.-P. (1997). Staatsziele und Staatszielbestimmungen. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommermann, K.-P. (1998). Der entgrenzte Verfassungsstaat. Kritische Vierteljahresschrift für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft, 81, 404–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommermann, K.-P. (2005). Demokratiekonzepte im Vergleich. In H. Bauer, P. M. Huber, & K.-P. Sommermann (Eds.), Demokratie in Europa (pp. 191–221). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stratulat, C., Emmanouilidis, J. A., Fischer, T., & Piedrafita, S. (2014). Legitimising EU Policymaking: What Role for National Parliaments. Brussels Thinks Tank Dialogue 2014. Discussion paper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streinz, R. (2012). Europarecht (9th edn.). Heidelberg: Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vari, M., & Istituto per la documentazione e gli studi legislativi (2012). Presentazione del volume “The European Union after Lisbon. Constitutional Basis, Economic Order and External Action” di Hermann-Josef Blanke e Stelio Mangiameli (pp. 703–728). Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Presented by G. Amato, P. De Ioanna & M. Vari.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagener, H.-J., & Eger, T. (2014). Europäische Integration: Wirtschaft und Recht, Geschichte und Politik (3rd edn.). Munich: Vahlen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A. (2010). Europäische Verfassungsvergleichung. Munich: C.H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A. (2011). Die Reform der Wirtschafts- und Währungsunion in der Finanzkrise. EuZW, 935–940.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A. (2013). Europa- und völkerrechtliche Elemente der Gewährleistung von Haushaltsdisziplin in der Währungsunion. EuR, 375–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1918). Parlament und Regierung im neugeordneten Deutschland. Munich: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weigand, E. (2008). Towards a common European legal thinking: a dialogic challenge. In H. Petersen, A. L. Kjær, H. Krunke, & M. Rask Madsen (Eds.), Paradoxes of European Legal Integration (pp. 235–251). Aldershot, Hampshire: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendel, M. (2011). Permeabilität im europäischen Verfassungsrecht. Verfassungsrechtliche Integrationsnormen auf Staats- und Unionsebene im Vergleich. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zürn, M. (1996). Über den Staat und die Demokratie im europäischen Mehrebenensystem. Politische Vierteljahresschrift, 37(1), 27–55.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Blanke, HJ., Böttner, R. (2015). The Democratic Deficit in the (Economic) Governance of the European Union. In: Blanke, HJ., Cruz Villalón, P., Klein, T., Ziller, J. (eds) Common European Legal Thinking. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19300-7_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics