Skip to main content

Contraction, Revision, Expansion: Representing Belief Change Operations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Krister Segerberg on Logic of Actions

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 1))

Abstract

The underlying idealizations in Krister Segerberg’s Dynamic Doxastic Logic (DDL) are investigated in comparison with other belief revision models. It is argued that the doxastic voluntarism of the proposed interpretation is problematic but can be discarded. The treatment of conditional operators in DDL is discussed, and it is proposed that the use of conditional operators not satisfying the Ramsey test should be further investigated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Or more precisely: the sentences I was committed to believe to be true (Cf. [18]).

  2. 2.

    If belief change is interpreted as referring to other belief-holders than individual persons, then the sentential format may be less problematic. One example of this is database management. The contents of databases are more readily representable by sentences than human beliefs or memories. Another example is changes in collectively created and maintained stocks of information or knowledge, such as the corpus of scientific beliefs. Collective processes are usually based on sentential representations since these are needed for interindividual communication.

  3. 3.

    Or set of sentences [9].

  4. 4.

    These are the most elementary demands of conservatism. In addition the following, somewhat less precise, demands are common: (iii) In incorporation, no sentences are added unless this is needed to incorporate the input. (ii) In contraction, no sentences are removed unless this is needed to remove the input.

  5. 5.

    An alternative approach takes as primitive an operation that both removes some sentence(s) and adds some other sentence(s). It is then possible to develop a model of belief change on the basis of one single primitive operation instead of two as in Levi’s model [13].

  6. 6.

    For arbitrary \(K_1\) and \(K_2\), this recipe only works if the language is finite. In a framework with an infinite language, two operations on sentences are not sufficient to take us from a belief set \(K_1\) to any other belief set \(K_2\). If there is a countably infinite number of logical atoms, then the number of belief sets expressible in the language is uncountable. (This can be shown with a standard diagonalization argument.) On the other hand, there is only a countable number of sequences \(\div p + q\) of a contraction by one sentence (\(p\)) followed by an expansion by another (\(q\)). This problem can be solved by introducing multiple contraction and expansion.

  7. 7.

    This refers to the modelling of human beliefs. Pure contraction of databases is unproblematic.

  8. 8.

    Heinrich Wansing is another prominent proponent of this view. He has proposed that developing the semantics of belief ascriptions from the viewpoint of doxastic voluntarism can be a way to avoid closure of belief under logical consequence. In his view, a variant of seeing-to-it-that (stit) logic of agency can be used to represent voluntary acquisition and abandonment of belief. [41] In later work he has further specified this as dstit-theory, where dstit stands for “deliberately sees to it that” [42]. He proposes the introduction of a belief formation operator to be read “\(\alpha \) sees to it that \(\alpha \) believes that \(p\)” (p. 212).

  9. 9.

    Issac Levi [19] avoids most of the common difficulties with Ramsey test conditionals by accepting (4) but not (5).

  10. 10.

    However, it is trivially unproblematic in an approach where it holds for all potential belief sets \(K_1\) and \(K_2\) that \(K_1 \nsubseteq K_2\). In such a framework there cannot be any pure contraction, or any other operation that takes us from a belief set to one of its proper subsets. Furthermore, there cannot be any pure expansion, or any other operation that takes us from a belief set to one of its proper supersets. Cf. [11].

  11. 11.

    The notation in the quoted formulas has been slightly modified.

  12. 12.

    This conflation is perhaps stimulated by the standard theory of probabilities, in which two notions of degree of belief are merged: the current strength of a belief and the propensity to retain it when it is challenged are represented by the same number. However, this is a limitation that should not necessarily be transferred to other frameworks.

References

  1. Alchourrón, C., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Audi, R. (2001). Doxastic voluntarism and the ethics of belief. In M. Setup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty. Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue (pp. 93–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Aucher, G. (2003). A combined system for update logic and belief revision, ILLC report MoL-2003-03. Amsterdam: ILLC, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Baltag, A., Moss, L., & Solecki, S. (1998). The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions. In I. Gilboa (Ed.), Proceedings of the 7th conference on theoretical aspects of rationality and knowledge (TARK 98) (pp. 43–56). San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2008). A Qualitative Theory of dynamic interactive belief revision. In G. Bonanno, W. van der Hoek, M. Wooldridge (Eds.) Logic and the Foundations of Game and Decision Theory (LOFT 7), Texts in Logic and Games 3 (pp. 11–58). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cantwell, J. (1997). On the logic of small changes in hypertheories. Theoria, 63, 54–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Fermé, E., & Hansson, S. O. (2011). AGM 25 years. Twenty-five years of research in belief change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 40, 295–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Fuhrmann, A. (1991). Theory contraction through base contraction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 20, 175–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Fuhrmann, A., & Hansson, S. O. (1994). A survey of multiple contraction. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 3, 39–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Gärdenfors, P. (1986). Belief revisions and the Ramsey test for conditionals. Philosophical Review, 95, 81–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Hansson, S. O. (1992). In defense of the Ramsey test. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 522–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Hansson, S. O. (2000). Formalization in philosophy. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 6, 162–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Hansson, S. O. (2009). Replacement—a Sheffer stroke for belief revision. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38, 127–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Hansson, S. O. (2010). Methodological pluralism in philosophy. Theoria, 76, 189–191.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Hansson, S. O. (2011). Logic of belief revision. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-belief-revision)

  16. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Leitgeb, H., & Segerberg, K. (2007). Dynamic doxastic logic: Why, how, and where to? Synthese, 155, 167–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Levi, I. (1977). Subjunctives, dispositions and chances. Synthese, 34, 423–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Levi, I. (1988). Iteration of conditionals and the Ramsey test. Synthese, 76, 49–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Levi, I. (1991). The fixation of belief and its undoing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Lindström, S., & Rabinowicz, W. (1991). Epistemic entrenchment with incomparabilities and relational belief revision. In A. Fuhrmann & M. Morreau (Eds.), The logic of theory change (pp. 208–228). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Lindström, S., & Rabinowicz, W. (1999). DDL unlimited. Dynamic doxastic logic for introspective agents. Erkenntnis, 51, 353–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Montmarquet, J. (2008). Virtue and voluntarism. Synthese, 161, 393–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Mourad, R. (2008). Choosing to believe. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 63, 55–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Nickel, P. J. (2010). Voluntary belief on a reasonable basis. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 312–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Nottelmann, N. (2006). The analogy argument for doxastic voluntarism. Philosophical Studies, 131, 559–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Plaza, J. (1989). Logics of public communications. In M. L. Emrich, M. S. Pfeifer, M. Hadzikadic, & Z. W. Ras (Eds.), Proceedings of the 4th International Symposium on Methodologies for Intelligent Systems, (pp. 201–216). Oak Ridge, Tennessee: Oak Ridge National Laboratory.

    Google Scholar 

  28. de Rijke, M. (1994). Meeting some neighbours. In J. van Eijck, & A. Visser (Eds.), Logic and information flow, (pp. 170–195). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Rott, H. (1989). Conditionals and theory change: Revisions expansions, and additions. Synthese, 81, 91–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Scott-Kakures, D. (1994). On belief and the captivity of the will. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 77–103. [p. 83, to be checked.].

    Google Scholar 

  31. Segerberg, K. (1989). A note on an impossibility theorem of Gärdenfors. Noûs, 23, 351–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Segerberg, K. (1995). Belief revision from the point of view of doxastic logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 3, 535–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Segerberg, K. (1996). Three recipes for revision. Theoria, 62, 62–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Segerberg, K. (1997). Proposal for a theory of belief revision along the lines of Lindström and Rabinowicz. Fundamenta Informaticae, 32, 183–191.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Segerberg, K. (1999). Two traditions in the logic of belief: Bringing them together. In H. J. Ohlbach & U. Reyle (Eds.), Logic, language and reasoning: Essays in honour of Dov Gabbay (pp. 135–147). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  36. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory. American philosophical quarterly monograph series (Vol. 2). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  37. van Benthem, J. (1989). Semantic parallels in natural language and computation. In H.-D. Ebbinghaus, J. Fernandez-Prida, M. Garrido, D. Lascar, M. Rodrigues Artalejo Logic Colloquium’87 (pp. 331–375). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  38. van Benthem, J. (1995). Logic and the flow of information. In Proceedings of the 9th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics (Vol. 134, pp. 693–724).

    Google Scholar 

  39. van Ditmarsch, H. (2005). Prolegomena to dynamic logic for belief revision, Synthese (Knowledge, Rationality & Action), 147, 229–275.

    Google Scholar 

  40. van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (2007). Dynamic epistemic logic. Synthese Library. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Wansing, H. (2000). A reduction of doxastic logic to action logic. Erkenntnis, 53, 267–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Wansing, H. (2006). Doxastic decisions, epistemic justification, and the logic of agency. Philosophical Studies, 128, 201–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sven Ove Hansson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hansson, S.O. (2014). Contraction, Revision, Expansion: Representing Belief Change Operations. In: Trypuz, R. (eds) Krister Segerberg on Logic of Actions. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7046-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics