Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Science and Philosophy ((SCPH,volume 5))

  • 145 Accesses

Abstract

It is inevitable that language has, as Ian Hacking put it, mattered to philosophy.1 It is not inevitable that practices — especially extra-linguistic practices — have mattered so little. Philosophy has not yet addressed an issue that is central to any theory of the language of observation and therefore, to any theory of science: how do observers ascend from the world to talk, thought and argument about that world? The importance of practice is sometimes noticed by philosophers and historians of science.2 The more historically minded have persued it into the experimental coal-face where new experience is mined.3 One reason for neglect of observational practice is that scientists’ own accounts of experimental work support the disembodied view that philosophers tacitly endorse. Human agency is written out of these accounts; at best it appears in an appropriately deliberative and methodical role. This would seem to justify the philosophical practice of rendering observation in the passive form ‘X was observed in order to …’, as if observers have eyes, minds and theories but never hands in the matter. A second reason is that concepts and theories are found in texts: they are easy to write and talk about. The literary view of scientific concepts suits the linguistic turn in philosophy and conforms to wider cultural assumptions about the priority of head over hands. Yet many scientists spend most of their time solving problems of a different order, in a manner that is procedural and involves manipulations in the material world as well as the world of concepts.

‘Now he’s seeing it like this’, ‘now like that’ would only be said of someone capable of making certain applications of the figure quite freely.

The substratum of this experience is the mastery of a technique.

Wittgenstein

Logic itself has now entered a stage where ‘anthropological’ considerations (finitism) play an important role. Altogether the scientific enterprise seems to be much closer to the arts than older logicians and philosophers of science (myself among them) once thought …

Feyerabend

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Giere (1988), pp. 109–10.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Sachs (1986), ch. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Gregory (1986), pp. 28–30.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Arber (1985) describes thought processes as reticular, that is, convoluted and folded (like the brain).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Giere [1989] levels this criticism at the examples used by Thagard (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  6. See R. Tweney, “Five questions for computationalists”, forthcoming in Schrager, J. and Langley, P, Computational models of discovery and theory formation, [in press], and R. Fjelland, “Can computers make scientific discoveries: A critique of Langley, Simon, Bradshaw and Zytkow: Scientific Discovery”, read to the 14th Conference on the Philosophy of Science, Inter-University Centre for Postgraduate Studies, April 1989. For a critique of philosophies of discovery, see Nickles (1985, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Nickles (1988), p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Holmes (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Franklin (1986), 140–162.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Medawar (1963) and (1969), p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Naylor (1989), p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Postscript to Kuhn (1970), p. 189. Fleck’s discussion of “vademecum” science addresses the function of exemplary practices, Fleck (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  13. For a discussion of verbalization in relation to protocol analysis see Tweney (1989a, 1989b) and Tweney and Hoffner (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Collins (1985), pp. 100–106 on calibration and Laverdière (1989) on carbon dating.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Perez-Ramos, A. (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Hesse (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Latour and Woolgar (1979) and Collins (1981b) favour idealist explanations. Knorr-Cetina argues that the ethologists’ emphasis on how objects are produced favours a materialist explanation (1983), p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  18. One of the most thorough surveys of contemporary philosophy of science makes only a couple of references to experiment (other than to theory-testing). Neither is about experiment: the first deals with theories of data and experimental design (which form the base of Patrick Suppes’ hierarchy of theories); the second discusses Feyerabend’s pragmatic theory of observation sentences: Suppe (1974), pp. 106–8, 178–9. See also van Fraasen (1980), chapter 4.

    Google Scholar 

  19. For examples of learning how to see with bubble chambers see Galison (1985) and Galison and Asmuss (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  20. R. Tweney, On doing Science, MS in preparation.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Hacking (1983); on realizing see also Radder (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Tweney has mapped Faraday’s experiments on electromagnetic induction: Tweney (1989b, c).

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Shapin (1988) and Shapin and Schaffer (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Latour (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Gooding (1990a).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Swenson (1972) on the aether-drift experiments and Worrall (1989) on Poisson’s white-spot prediction.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Lakatos (1980b), v. 2, p. 211.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Hacking (1983), p. 249–54.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Hofmann (1987b) and Holmes (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Exceptions are Hesse (1988) and Bloor (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Rudwick (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Porter (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Knorr-Cetina (1981), Lynch (1985b), Latour and Woolgar (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  34. See Laudan, R. (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  35. See R. Tweney, “The use of external memory in science”, unpublished Ms.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Gruber (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  38. On the sensorium as mirror see Hacking (1976) and Rorty (1979); on the craft basis of constructing representations that mirror the world see Shapin and Schaffer (1985), chapter 1, esp. p. 17 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Goodman (1973), p. 94 and ff.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Influential discussions of introducing novices to descriptive language are Quine (1960), pp. 26–57, (1974), p. 33 ff., and Wittgenstein (1953), pp. 1e-21e.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See Feyerabend (1965) and Hacking (1983), ch. 5. The problem of incommensurability of meaning diverted attention from the procedural and extra-linguistic aspects of scientific practice which features in Kuhn’s earlier work (Kuhn, 1961, 1962a); see Schuster (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Putnam (1973), p. 203. This view is an explicitly social one. In Putnam (1975), he argues that this establishes the stereotypical part of the meaning of terms; see also Putnam (1978), p. 115–6.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Quine (1969), p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Nersessian (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  45. Nickles (1989) and Hesse (1980) argue the compatibility of philosophical and naturalistic accounts of science; both maintain that philosophical and historical analyses are distinct practices (see Nickles, on realizability requirements (1989), p. 317 ff. and Hesse (1980), p. 163).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gooding, D. (1990). The procedural turn. In: Experiment and the Making of Meaning. Science and Philosophy, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-0707-2_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-0707-2_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-3253-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-0707-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics