Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Science and Philosophy ((SCPH,volume 5))

  • 144 Accesses

Abstract

Arguments meant to justify a discovery by ‘grounding’ it in theory rely on the operations and experiments that enabled it to be represented. This generative aspect of justification has been unfashionable since it was displaced in the early nineteenth century by the deductive style of a new, unified mathematical physics.1 As a result, an important problem for a theory of representation, has been neglected: how do observers represent experience that is new to all of them in a communicable form? This question is inseparable from another: how do observers tell when they have successfully communicated what, in their own experience, they intend others to see? Satisfactory answers to these questions would show how observational assent reflects similarity of semantic ascent, and vice versa. A further question is how novel, anomalous information retains enough of its anomalous character to promote changes in a theoretical system that has apparently assimilated it. These questions remain unanswered.

All knowledge must be recognition, on pain of being mere delusion …

Bertrand Russell

I made a number of experiments of the same kind, but the results were never precisely alike …

Humphry Davy

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. An accessible account of the use of these two images is Wise (1979b).

    Google Scholar 

  2. For Maxwell’s assessment of Faraday’s synthesis see his (1890), vol. 2, pp. 359.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Faraday described his “rough geometrical” method in a referee’s report on a paper submitted by Joule to the Royal Society (Royal Society MS, RR3, 154). For the mathematization of Faraday, see Heimann (1970) and Smith and Wise (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Oersted (1820), p. 274. Oersted sent copies of his report (in latin) to the editors of a number of European journals, who published translations. My account is based on a translation published by David Brewster.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., p. 215.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Oersted (1821). This account did not appear until November 1821, by which time his explanations had been superceded by others based on other observers repetitions of his results.

    Google Scholar 

  8. For an analysis of direct and indirect observation see Shapere (1982, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Wittgenstein (1953), para. 231.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., para. 262.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Biot (1821), p. 281.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For electromagnetic science on the continent see Caneva (1978) and (1980) and for the traditions into which it erupted, Heilbron (1981, 1982).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Most of their experiments sought a temporally extended effect, i.e. a continuous current. These non-discoveries are described in Ross (1965), Williams (1983, 1985a, 1985b), Hofmann (1987a).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Faraday (1821–1822), p. 199.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  16. These and several related experiments were repeated with final year physics students at Bristol University, in 1983–84. They are described in J. E. Leigh and S. Perrett, “A reproduction of Michael Faraday’s experiments on electromagnetism”, Physics Stage III Project Reports, Bristol University, May 1985 (unpublished), and in Gooding (1989c). Historians who recognize the need to augment textual interpretation with experimental repetition include Belloni (1970), James (1985), Shaffer (1989) and Settle (1961, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Faraday (1821–22), p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Davy (1821a), p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Biot (1821), p. 283.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., pp. 282–283.

    Google Scholar 

  21. I rely on a published account which incorporates a degree of reconstruction. Comparing laboratory records of contemporary work with published versions of it and with know-how acquired in recent repetitions narrows the distance between exploration itself and reports which incorporate reconstruction and hindsight.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Biot (1821), p. 282.

    Google Scholar 

  23. S. Shapin (1984) and Shapin and Schaffer (1985), p. 60 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Biot (1821), p. 282–3.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., p. 283.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Here demonstrative reconstruction generates a narrative in which cognitive reconstruction is implicit (see table 1.1). Note that the “chaotic” behaviours are real. Subduing them requires a great deal of practice. For more on this see Gooding, op. cit. note 17 and part 2, below.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Biot (1821), p. 283.

    Google Scholar 

  28. According to a report of a sitting of the Académie of 30 October, ‘M.M. Biot et Savart ont été conduits au résultat suivant qui exprime rigoureusement l’action éprouvée par une molécule de magnétism austral ou boréal placée à une distance quelconque d’un fil cylindrique très-fin et indéfini, rendue magnétique par le courant voltaïque. Par le point où réside cette molécule, menez une perpendiculare à l’axe du fil: la force qui sollicite la molecule est perpendiculare à cette ligne et à l’axe de fil,’ Biot and Savart (1820), p. 223, my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Biot, loc. cit n. 28. That light and magnetism shared this peculiarity suggested other interactions between them. For example, in 1823 John Herschel tried to detect the influence of electromagnetism on a polarized ray passing through a helix; see Gooding (1985b).

    Google Scholar 

  30. On the significance of Laplacian physics (especially the contributions of Poisson, whom Biot cites here), see Hofmann (1987a), and for the institutional contex see Fox (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Biot (1821), p. 286.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  33. These precepts included a commitment to inverse square forces, whose importance was established when Coulomb showed through meticulous experiments that electrostatic and magnetic forces obey the same law as gravitation. Laplace took up Coulomb’s example, making Newton’s law the exemplar for any rigourous physical theory in which a precise mathematical formulation should be coupled with accurate quantitative experimentation.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Both acknowledge the theory-embeddeness of observation. Falsification tries to restore a degree of independence by restricting what experiment can be used to show; sociological deconstruction argues that what experiments show is always, ultimately a matter of theoretical and other socially validated judgements.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See Caneva (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  36. See Hofmann (1987b) and Ampère (1820, 1827).

    Google Scholar 

  37. The 1825 memoir (published 1827) is the usual source for Ampère’s route to discovery. For a philosophical analysis based on Ampère’s (1827) reconstruction see Dorling (1973). Ampère’s account does not relate how the initial experimentation actually led to the force law. For a critique of empirical scrutiny of scientific method based on such accounts, see Gooding (1989d).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Hofmann (1987b).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Hofmann (1987a). Caneva also draws attention to the unpremeditated character of Ampère’s earliest experimental problem solving, in ‘Andre-Marie Ampère and the development of electrodynamics: a case study in the dynamics of problem solving and theory building in science”, presented to the October 1980 Four Societies meeting at Toronto (unpublished).

    Google Scholar 

  40. On rivalry and ambition see Williams (1985b), p. 91 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. For the construction and significance of this hypothesis see Hofmann (1987b).

    Google Scholar 

  42. For Thomson and Faraday see Gooding (1982b) and below, chapter 10.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Williams (1985b) identifies the methodological differences that fuelled this controversy, which can be traced in their correspondence, see Williams et al., eds., (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Hofmann and Williams argue that Ampère produced electromagnetic induction effects as early as 1822. He suppressed them in favour of an emerging conviction that magnetism is just electricity in motion. Faraday’s discovery of electromagnetic induction in 1831 proved this to be an error of judgement: see Thompson (1895).

    Google Scholar 

  45. Davy (1821a), p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Arago (1820), p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Davy (1821a), p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Davy had probably investigated the latter effects first. Faraday’s development of this work is discussed below.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid., p. 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., p. 14. In his report Biot claimed that his filings formed a cylyndrical mass.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Davy’s next experiments sought a relationship between the quantity of iron filings lifted and the “quantity of electricity passing”. It is typical of Davy’s and Faraday’s investigations of these phenomena, that they expressed these results qualitatively.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Davy (1821a), p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., for Brande’s account of Wollaston’s idea see Brande (1820).

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid., pp. 14–15.

    Google Scholar 

  56. See Faraday (1827), pp. 449–451.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Davy (1821a), p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Williams (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., p. 18. According to Faraday he was was present at this experiment, see Faraday (1839–1855), vol. 2, p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  62. It is hard to say how soon Davy and others in London learned of Ampère’s results, which were announced regularly to the Académie whose sittings were reported in the Annales de Chimie. This journal appears to have been Davy and Faraday’s main source of information.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Davy (1821a), p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Davy (1821b), p. 427. This was performed at the London Institution which posessed an even larger battery of cells than the one at the Royal Institution. W. H. Pepys later built another “intensity” or high-current cell with two plates of enormous surface area. This too attracted a number of experimental “contacts”: see Gooding (1985b, 1989c), and for Pepys’ large batteries, Hackmann (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  65. Faraday (1821–22).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ibid., 197.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  68. See the studies cited in note 17.

    Google Scholar 

  69. On operationalism see Bridgeman (1952), Hempel (1952) and Beller (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  70. Faraday (1821–22), p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ibid., p. 199, my emphasis

    Google Scholar 

  72. This develops a notion of construals introduced in Gooding (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  73. Lynch (1985a).

    Google Scholar 

  74. Observability is often worked out as a response to novel observations. For a study of changing degrees of theory-dependence or “externality” see Pinch (1985b) and below, chapters 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  75. The relevant background is summarized in chapter 4; further details can be found in Gooding (1985c) and (1989a).

    Google Scholar 

  76. In the 18th and 19th centuries the the identity of laboratory and natural phenomena was sometimes contended: see Hackmann (1989) and Galison and Assmus (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  77. See Gooding (1989a). pp. 208–12.

    Google Scholar 

  78. On display see Hackmann (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  79. Watts (1811); see also Watts (1745) and Williams (1965), pp. 12–14.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Faraday (1821–22), p. 195, my emphasis. The phrase “clear idea” occurs often in Faraday’s writing: see chapters 9 and 10.

    Google Scholar 

  81. The mimetic tradition of observational science was an influence, reinforced by Faraday’s conversion to a religious doctrine that demanded as literal a reading of nature as possible (by analogy to a literal reading of the scriptures). See Cantor (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  82. Faraday (1827). Tweney has shown how, in the Chemical Manipulations Faraday introduces complex operations by constructing them from elementary techniques (or scripts). See Tweney (1985, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  83. Faraday (1821–22), p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  84. The Faraday Museum at the Royal Institution contains one of these. We know of the prototype from the anecdote that Faraday carried an ordinary bottle cork about with him, with its ends marked “P” and “N”. He could demonstrate the direction of magnetic action of the current by sticking a pin into the cork.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Faraday probably assisted with the experiment. He wrote: “On arranging numerous wires in circles, and other directions around and about the discharging wire, it was found after the discharge, that all were magnetic,… so that the north pole of one needle was towards the south pole of the next, and in a constant relation to the course of the discharge …”, (1821–22), p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gooding, D. (1990). Action and interpretation. In: Experiment and the Making of Meaning. Science and Philosophy, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-0707-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-0707-2_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-3253-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-0707-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics