Skip to main content

Psychological Methods of Observing Consciousness

  • Chapter
An Ontology of Consciousness

Part of the book series: Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library ((MNPL,volume 18))

  • 120 Accesses

Abstract

Some contemporary philosophers, such as Feyerabend,1 Armstrong,2 and Rorty,3 speak as though any distinction between subjective processes and their objective manifestations depended upon the supposed ‘incorrigibility’ of the subjective processes, i.e., the thesis that I cannot think that I experience a pain and be mistaken. Actually, it is not necessary for this purpose that the subjective knowledge of mental states yield any such incorrigible information, but only that it yield different —though perhaps equally corrigible—information about the mental states. We shall attempt to demonstrate in this first chapter that direct phenomenological reflection upon mental states does yield different information from objective observation methods, and that the objectifying methods are incapable in principle of observing consciousness without being supplemented by and correlated with phenomenological data. This is true, we shall argue, in spite of the fact that phenomenological data are by no means incorrigible. In fact, many phenomenologists cheerfully grant that the notion of incorrigible access to one’s own subjective consciousness by means of a complete phenomenological reduction went out of style long ago, when the phenomenologists Merleau-Ponty and Sartre (and many say Husserl himself in the Crisis and other posthumous papers) pronounced the idea of a complete phenomenological reduction impossible in principle. There are certain items of information about the nature of consciousness which even phenomenological psychology (not to mention objectivistic psychology) cannot ascertain, but for which it must have recourse to philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Paul Feyerabend, “Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem,” Review of Metaphysics, 17, 49–66.

    Google Scholar 

  2. D.M. Armstrong, “Is Introspective Knowledge Incorrigible?,” Philosophical Review, 72, 418–19.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Richard Rorty, “Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. For example, Guy Lafrancois, Psychological Theories and Human Learning (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1972); F. Kanfer and A. Goldstein, Helping People Change (New York: Pergamon, 1980); Kiesler; it is also noteworthy that Melvin Marx, writing in Encyclopedia Britannica’s 1980 Science and the Future yearbook, cites the resurgence of introspective investigations as the year’s most important event in the field of psychology (382–85).

    Google Scholar 

  5. J.B. Watson, Behaviorism (2nd ed.) (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1930); “Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It,” Psychological Review (1913), 20, 157–158.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Husserl, Phänomenologische Psychologie (Den Haag: Nijhoff, 1962), passim., see especially pp. 35–41; Amedeo Giorgi, “Phenomenology and Experimental Psychology,” Duquesne Studies in Phenomenological Psychology (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1971), I, 6–29; H. Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1960); Needleman; D.P. Schultz, “The Human Subject in Psychological Research,” Psychological Bulletin,63, 358–72; Merleau-Ponty, The Phenomenology of Perception; The Primacy of Perception; The Structure of Behavior.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Carl Rogers, “A Theory of Therapy, Personality, and Interpersonal Relationships as Developed in Client-centered Framework,” in S. Koch, ed., Psychology: A Study of a Science, III (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959); Abraham Maslow, Motivation and Personality ( New York: Harper and Row, 1954 ).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Husserl, Phänomenologische Psychologie,35–41.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception,vii-xxi; Sartre, Transcendence of the Ego; see also infra., Chapter III.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception,434–456; A. Manser, Sartre: A Philosophic Study (New York: Oxford University Press, 1966), 164, D. Tulloch, “Sartrian Existentialism,” Philosophical Quarterly,2, 31–52; M. Kaye, Morals and Commitment (London: Covent Garden, 1971), to mention only a few.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions ( Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962 ).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Kuhn.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Needleman, 9–46.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Hans J. Eysenck, The Dynamics of Anxiety and Hysteria ( New York: Praeger, 1957 ).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Henri Poincare, Mathematics and Science ( New York: Dover, 1963 ).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Merleau-Ponty, The Structure of Behavior, 10–93 and passim; Kurt Goldstein, The Organism (New York: American Books, 1938); Aron Gurwitsch, The Field of Consciousness ( Pittsburgh; Duquesne University Press, 1964 ).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Maslow, 27–30, 35–38.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Carl Hempel, Philosophy of Natural Science ( Princeton: Englewood Cliffs, 1966 ), 40–45.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Eysenck.

    Google Scholar 

  20. K.W. and J.T. Spence, “Relation of Eyelid Conditioning to Manifest Anxiety, Extraversion and Rigidity,” Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology (1964), 68, 144–49.

    Google Scholar 

  21. R.B. Catell, The 16 Personality Factor Questionnaire, Inst. Pers. and Abil. Test, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cattell.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Eysenck.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Spence.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Giorgi, 13–15.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Giorgi, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Giorgi, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Schultz, 227.

    Google Scholar 

  29. R.D. Laing, Self and Others ( New York: Pantheon, 1969 ).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Jean-Paul Sartre, Psychology of the Imagination ( New York: Washington Square Press, 1966 ).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Merleau-Ponty, “The Child’s Relations With Others,” The Primacy of Perception,96–155.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Sartre, Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions ( London: Metheun, 1971 ).

    Google Scholar 

  33. See note 6.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Merleau-Ponty, The Primacy of Perception, 75.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Laing, 32.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Eric Berne, Games People Play ( New York: Grove Press, 1967 ).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Georg Lukacs, “Existentialism or Marxism,” G. Novack, ed., Existentialism versus Marxism ( New York: Delta Press, 1966 ).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1986 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ellis, R. (1986). Psychological Methods of Observing Consciousness. In: An Ontology of Consciousness. Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library, vol 18. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0715-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0715-2_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8298-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0715-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics