Skip to main content
Erschienen in: AI & SOCIETY 2/2019

29.03.2018 | Original Article

Dreyfus on the “Fringe”: information processing, intelligent activity, and the future of thinking machines

verfasst von: Jeffrey White

Erschienen in: AI & SOCIETY | Ausgabe 2/2019

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

From his preliminary analysis in 1965, Hubert Dreyfus projected a future much different than those with which his contemporaries were practically concerned, tempering their optimism in realizing something like human intelligence through conventional methods. At that time, he advised that there was nothing “directly” to be done toward machines with human-like intelligence, and that practical research should aim at a symbiosis between human beings and computers with computers doing what they do best, processing discrete symbols in formally structured problem domains. Fast-forward five decades, and his emphasis on the difference between two essential modes of processing, the unconscious yet purposeful mode fundamental to situated human cognition, and the “minded” sense of conscious processing characterizing symbolic reasoning that seems to lend itself to explicit programming, continues into the famous Dreyfus–McDowell debate. The present memorial reviews Dreyfus’ early projections, asking if the fears that punctuate current popular commentary on AI are warranted, and in light of these if he would deliver similar practical advice to researchers today.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
For a more general review of Dreyfus’ work in philosophy of artificial intelligence with some attention, for example, to the issue of embodiment with which the present paper concludes, see Brey 2001.
 
2
“It’s like claiming that the first monkey that climbed a tree was making progress towards flight to the moon.” (cf. Dreyfus 2007, p. 1142).
 
3
Dreyfus seemed most disappointed that “neither Dennett nor anyone connected with the project has published an account of the failure and asked what mistaken assumptions underlay their absurd optimism” with Dennett pinning the stall-out on a “lack of graduate students” (2007, p. 1141).
 
4
Of the four, he holds pattern recognition to be most fundamental, noting that “resolution of the difficulties which have arrested development” in other fields “all presuppose success” in this one (1965, p. 14).
 
5
Later, he bundles these three forms of information processing into what he calls “perspicuous grouping”, the ability to perceive connections without explicitly counting them out, and to recognize individual examples as “typical” of a class without explicit comparison of every other given example (1965, p. 37–46).
 
6
As the chess player is “zeroing in” on opportune movements, he is effectively “unconsciously counting out” the various alternatives (1965, p. 53).
 
7
Structuring a problem “does not involve merely the given parts and their transformations” but “works in conjunction with the material that is structurally relevant but is selected from past experience.” (Dreyfus 1965, p. 29) This insight bears on prospective agency through backpropagation of perceived error as realized in contemporary dynamic systems models in an interesting way, noteworthy in terms of the neurorobotics research mentioned in the fourth section of this paper.
 
8
He identifies a similar loop arising in the context of gameplay, as the significance of any given piece is partly determined by any single game piece and partly by the position of that piece relative other pieces, with all of this only significant in the context of possible future moves as constrained by the structured goal conditions of the game. For a heuristic chess program, for example, to escape such circularity, the interdependence of such definitions requires that some be fixed, at which point its limits “become a matter of principle rather than simply of practice” (1965, p. 73).
 
9
For an interesting use of this example, see Williams et al. (1974).
 
10
Problems accessible to “associationistic” processes include term-replacement (“mechanical dictionary”), simple memory (associating symbols with patterns), conditioned response (as a means to producing these associations) and trial and error (maze navigation) type problems, all of which are accessible to traditional symbol-pushing AI in the form of decision trees or list searches. The second type is also fully accessible to traditional AI. “Simple formal” type problems are fully governed by explicit rules defining contexts simple enough for meanings to be made completely explicit independent of context, including games whose moves can be explicitly counted out, theorem proofs involving searches for optimal applications of rules under explicit constraints, and pattern recognition given salient features are defined beforehand. The third type, “complex formal” problems, are only partially accessible to traditional AI, including “uncomputable” games whose decision trees cannot be brute-force counted-out including chess and go which require an appreciation of global context to settle on which features are essential and which not before deciding on further moves, and pattern recognition wherein regularities must first be discovered before similarities are recognized. Finally, Dreyfus holds that the fourth type of problem is wholly outside of machine comprehension on principle, consisting in “non-formal” problems with solutions requiring context sensitivity and an ability to distinguish essential from nonessential aspects in patterns which are distorted, the translation of natural language into metaphorical contexts, and the ability to structure otherwise seemingly unstructured problems through what Dreyfus calls “perceptive guess” (see the section headed “Areas of Intelligent Activity Classified with Respect to the Possibility of Artificial Intelligence in Each” beginning on p. 75).
 
11
Alexander VonSchoenborn taught this lesson through the image of an ever-expanding sphere of light around an increasingly bright candle. The greater the light, the larger the unlit fringe.
 
12
By “resistor analogue”, Dreyfus is characterizing a machine that works as do human beings to infer best explanations or to abduce optimal solutions such as we see in contemporary machine learning.
 
13
Whereby AI becomes more intelligent than human beings, human beings are compelled to increasingly integrate themselves with AI to keep up with technological progress, and once bent to the solution of humanity’s most pressing problems, achieve a capacity to deliver humanity from them, cf. Kurzweil, 2005. For a technical argument as to why such an “explosion” of “superintelligence” in self-modifying AI is unlikely, see Benthall (2017).
 
14
It is interesting to contrast these efforts with a related assessment of the “real danger of artificial intelligence”, that increasing automation by way of semi-autonomous machines promises to exacerbate rather than abate an historically unprecedented degree of wealth inequality (cf. Lee 2017) which has proven historically to precede mass violence, social upheaval, and in the twentieth century World War, and of which “autonomous weapons” will surely now play a part.
 
15
Meanwhile, the simple-mindedness of such reasoning has not gone unrecognized by proponents of current research vectors. For example, late in 2015 the Information Technology and Innovation Foundation nominated the “loose coalition of scientists and luminaries who stirred fear and hysteria in 2015 by raising alarms that artificial intelligence (AI) could spell doom for humanity” for its annual Luddite Award, an honor that was finally awarded them in January of the next year (cf. Atkinson 2015; ITIF 2016).
 
16
Noting that the cognizance of the individual of its situation within a social collective is “emergent” in 2001, Sun remarked on research in “bridging” the two (an image also central to da Costa and Pereira 2015) that “It helps to unearth the social unconscious embedded into social institutions and lodged inside individual minds” with the “crucial step in establishing the micro–macro link … between individual agents and society” becoming “how we should understand and characterize the structures of the social unconscious and its ‘‘emergence’’, computationally or otherwise.” (Sun 2001, page 2).
 
17
This is the thesis driving the Bloom et al. (2017), for example.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Armstrong S, Bostrom N, Shulman C (2016) Racing to the precipice: a model of artificial intelligence development. AI Soc 31(2):201–206CrossRef Armstrong S, Bostrom N, Shulman C (2016) Racing to the precipice: a model of artificial intelligence development. AI Soc 31(2):201–206CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bostrom N (2012) The superintelligent will: motivation and instrumental rationality in advanced artificial agents. Mind Mach 22(2):71–85CrossRef Bostrom N (2012) The superintelligent will: motivation and instrumental rationality in advanced artificial agents. Mind Mach 22(2):71–85CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bostrom N (2013) Superintelligence: paths, dangers, strategies. Oxford University Press, Oxford Bostrom N (2013) Superintelligence: paths, dangers, strategies. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Brey P (2001) Hubert Dreyfus—human versus machine. In: Achterhuis H, Crease RP (eds) American philosophy of technology: the empirical turn. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 37–63 Brey P (2001) Hubert Dreyfus—human versus machine. In: Achterhuis H, Crease RP (eds) American philosophy of technology: the empirical turn. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 37–63
Zurück zum Zitat Chalmers DJ (2010) The singularity: a philosophical analysis. J Conscious Stud 17:7–65 Chalmers DJ (2010) The singularity: a philosophical analysis. J Conscious Stud 17:7–65
Zurück zum Zitat da Cardoso CF, Pereira LM (2015) The emergence of artificial autonomy: a view from the foothills of a challenging. In: White J, Searle R (eds) Rethinking machine ethics in the age of ubiquitous technology. IGI Global, Hauppage da Cardoso CF, Pereira LM (2015) The emergence of artificial autonomy: a view from the foothills of a challenging. In: White J, Searle R (eds) Rethinking machine ethics in the age of ubiquitous technology. IGI Global, Hauppage
Zurück zum Zitat Dreyfus HL (1995) Heidegger on gaining a free relation to technology. In: Feenburg A, Hannay A (eds) Technology and the politics of knowledge. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 25–33 Dreyfus HL (1995) Heidegger on gaining a free relation to technology. In: Feenburg A, Hannay A (eds) Technology and the politics of knowledge. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 25–33
Zurück zum Zitat Dreyfus HL (2007) Why heideggerian ai failed and how fixing it would require making it more heideggerian. Artif Intell 171(18):1137–1160CrossRef Dreyfus HL (2007) Why heideggerian ai failed and how fixing it would require making it more heideggerian. Artif Intell 171(18):1137–1160CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dreyfus HL (2012) A history of first step fallacies. Mind Mach 22(2):87–99CrossRef Dreyfus HL (2012) A history of first step fallacies. Mind Mach 22(2):87–99CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kenaw S (2008) Hubert L. Dreyfus’ critique of classical AI and its rationalist assumptions. Mind Mach 18(2):227–238CrossRef Kenaw S (2008) Hubert L. Dreyfus’ critique of classical AI and its rationalist assumptions. Mind Mach 18(2):227–238CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kurzweil R (2005) The singularity is near: when humans transcend biology. Viking, New York, NY Kurzweil R (2005) The singularity is near: when humans transcend biology. Viking, New York, NY
Zurück zum Zitat Pereira LM, Saptawijaya A (2015) Bridging two realms of machine ethics. In: White J, Searle R (eds) Rethinking machine ethics in the age of ubiquitous technology. IGI Global, Hauppage Pereira LM, Saptawijaya A (2015) Bridging two realms of machine ethics. In: White J, Searle R (eds) Rethinking machine ethics in the age of ubiquitous technology. IGI Global, Hauppage
Zurück zum Zitat Pereira LM, Saptawijaya A (2016) Modeling collective morality via evolutionary game theory. In: Magnani L (ed) Programming machine ethics. Studies in applied philosophy, epistemology and rational ethics. Springer, Berlin, pp 26 Pereira LM, Saptawijaya A (2016) Modeling collective morality via evolutionary game theory. In: Magnani L (ed) Programming machine ethics. Studies in applied philosophy, epistemology and rational ethics. Springer, Berlin, pp 26
Zurück zum Zitat Rouse J (2013) What is conceptually articulated understanding? In: Schear JK (ed) Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: the McDowell-Dreyfus debate. Routledge, London, pp 250–271 Rouse J (2013) What is conceptually articulated understanding? In: Schear JK (ed) Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: the McDowell-Dreyfus debate. Routledge, London, pp 250–271
Zurück zum Zitat Russell S, Dewey D, Tegmark M (2015) Research priorities for robust and beneficial artificial intelligence. AI Magaz 36(4):105–114CrossRef Russell S, Dewey D, Tegmark M (2015) Research priorities for robust and beneficial artificial intelligence. AI Magaz 36(4):105–114CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Silver D, Huang A, Maddison CJ, Guez A, Sifre L, Van DDG, Schrittwieser J et al (2016) Mastering the game of Go with deep neural networks and tree search. Nature 529(7587):484–489CrossRef Silver D, Huang A, Maddison CJ, Guez A, Sifre L, Van DDG, Schrittwieser J et al (2016) Mastering the game of Go with deep neural networks and tree search. Nature 529(7587):484–489CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sun R (2001) Individual action and collective function: From sociology to multi-agent learning. Cogn Syst Res 2(1):1–3CrossRef Sun R (2001) Individual action and collective function: From sociology to multi-agent learning. Cogn Syst Res 2(1):1–3CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sun R (2018) Intrinsic motivation for truly autonomous agents. In: Abbass H, Scholz J, Reid D (eds) Foundations of trusted autonomy. Springer, Berlin Sun R (2018) Intrinsic motivation for truly autonomous agents. In: Abbass H, Scholz J, Reid D (eds) Foundations of trusted autonomy. Springer, Berlin
Zurück zum Zitat Sun R, Helie S (2015) Accounting for creativity within a psychologically realistic cognitive architecture. In: Besold T, Schorlemmer M, Smaill A (eds) Computational creativity research: towards creative machines. Atlantis thinking machines, 7th edn. Atlantis Press, Paris Sun R, Helie S (2015) Accounting for creativity within a psychologically realistic cognitive architecture. In: Besold T, Schorlemmer M, Smaill A (eds) Computational creativity research: towards creative machines. Atlantis thinking machines, 7th edn. Atlantis Press, Paris
Zurück zum Zitat Sun R, Wilson N, Lynch M (2016) Emotion: a unified mechanistic interpretation from a cognitive architecture. Cognit Comput 8(1):1–14CrossRef Sun R, Wilson N, Lynch M (2016) Emotion: a unified mechanistic interpretation from a cognitive architecture. Cognit Comput 8(1):1–14CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Tani J (2016) Exploring robotic minds: actions, symbols, and consciousness as self-organizing dynamic phenomena. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRef Tani J (2016) Exploring robotic minds: actions, symbols, and consciousness as self-organizing dynamic phenomena. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat White J (2016) Simulation, self-extinction, and philosophy in the service of human civilization. AI Soc 31(2):171–190CrossRef White J (2016) Simulation, self-extinction, and philosophy in the service of human civilization. AI Soc 31(2):171–190CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat White J, Tani J (2017) From biological to synthetic neurorobotics approaches to understanding the structure essential to consciousness (part 3). APA Newslett Philos Comput 17(1):11–22 White J, Tani J (2017) From biological to synthetic neurorobotics approaches to understanding the structure essential to consciousness (part 3). APA Newslett Philos Comput 17(1):11–22
Metadaten
Titel
Dreyfus on the “Fringe”: information processing, intelligent activity, and the future of thinking machines
verfasst von
Jeffrey White
Publikationsdatum
29.03.2018
Verlag
Springer London
Erschienen in
AI & SOCIETY / Ausgabe 2/2019
Print ISSN: 0951-5666
Elektronische ISSN: 1435-5655
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-018-0837-5

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2019

AI & SOCIETY 2/2019 Zur Ausgabe