Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare 3/2022

07.05.2022 | Original Paper

Electoral Institutions with impressionable voters

verfasst von: Costel Andonie, Daniel Diermeier

Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare | Ausgabe 3/2022

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We use a model of impressionable voters to study multi-candidate elections under different electoral rules. Instead of maximizing expected utility, voters cast their ballots based on impressions. We show that, under each rule, there is a monotone relationship between voter preferences and vote measures. The nature of this relationship, however, varies by electoral rule. Vote measures are biased upwards for socially preferred candidates under plurality rule, but biased downwards under negative plurality. There is no such bias under approval voting or Borda count. Voters always elect the socially preferred candidate in two-way races for any electoral rule. In multi-candidate elections, however, the ability to elect a Condorcet winner varies by rule. The results show that multi-candidate elections can perform well even if voters follow simple behavioral rules. The relative performance of specific electoral institutions, however, depends on the assumed behavioral model of voting.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
The nature of the ballot depends on the electoral rule. It corresponds to a “vote” under plurality rule, or in run-off elections, an “approval” under approval voting, a “negative vote” under negative plurality, and a ranking over candidates under the Borda rule.
 
2
See Bendor 2010 and Bendor et al. 2011 for detailed discussions.
 
3
Recent research (e.g., Spenkuch 2018) has argued that real electorates are best understood as heterogeneous, where some voters are rational, others impressionable or sincere. Modeling such electorates is valuable but very challenging. It also goes beyond the purpose of our paper.
 
4
The two remaining rules, Borda and runoff, are discussed later in Sect. 6.
 
5
For examples of such factors see (Gasper and Reeves 2011; Cole et al. 2012; Achen and Bartels 2002) and Wolfers (2002).
 
6
Casting a “favorable ballot for candidate i” corresponds to voting for i under plurality rule, approving of i under approval voting, or not voting in opposition to i under negative plurality.
 
7
The propensity to abstain \(p_{\theta }^{t}(A)\) can be computed from the vote propensities \(p_{\theta }^{t}\) and so does not need to be tracked explicitly. We will show how to compute \(p_{\theta }^{t}(A)\) from \(p_{\theta }^{t}\) when we analyse the stationary distributions.
 
8
This disadvantage is present only under approval voting. To see this, suppose that, under approval voting, there are three candidates and only one type of voters. Consider the following two distributions over the set B: (1) a distribution where ballots (1, 1, 0) and (0, 1, 1) each have probability \(\frac{1}{2}\) of being cast; (2) a distribution where ballots (1, 1, 1) and (0, 1, 0) each have probability \(\frac{1}{2}\) of being cast. Both of these distributions yield vote propensities \((p(1),p(2),p(3))=(\frac{ 1}{2},1,\frac{1}{2})\), i.e., an outcome where candidate 2 gets a measure of 1 of approval votes, while candidates 1 and 3 get a measure of \(\frac{1}{2}\). If we were to work directly with the probability distribution \(\{r_{\theta }^{t}(b)\}_{b\in B}\), we would be able to differentiate between the two cases, while the distribution of vote propensities \(\{p_{\theta }^{t}(i)\}_{i\in N}\) is not able to do so.
 
9
Alternatively, we could consider a more complex updating rule where updating varies with the magnitude of the voter’s impressions. That is, a voter with a “very negative” impression of a candidate may decrease that candidate’s propensity more heavily compared to the case of “moderately negative” impressions, etc. Adding such complexity, however, does not change the qualitative results of the analysis.
 
10
As under plurality rule, we could allow an updating process where the increase or decrease of propensities depends also on the magnitude of impressions. But again, this will not change the qualitative results.
 
11
It is easy to see that if \(v_{\theta }^{i}>v_{\theta }^{j}\), then \(q_{\theta }(i)>q_{\theta }(j)\), \(E[\frac{1}{1+I_{\theta }(-i)}]>E[\frac{1}{1+I_{\theta }(-j)}]\) and \(E[\frac{1}{1+J_{\theta }(-i)}]<E[\frac{1}{1+J_{\theta }(-j)}]\), and therefore \(S_{\theta }(i)>S_{\theta }(j)\) under each rule.
 
12
Similar implications hold when comparing differences in vote measures across groups. Under plurality rule, controlling for the differences \(q_{\theta }(i)-q_{\theta }(j)\) between two groups, the difference in vote measures \(S_{\theta }(i)-S_{\theta }(j)\) will be larger for the group for which, on average, the number of candidates, excluding candidates i and j, that voters of that group like is lower. Under negative plurality, in contrast, the difference in vote measures \(S_{\theta }(i)-S_{\theta }(j)\) will be larger for the group for which, on average, the number of candidates, other than i and j, that voters of that group like is larger.
 
13
A Condorcet winner beats all other candidates in pair-wise comparison. A Condorcet loser is beaten by all other candidates in pair-wise competition.
 
14
Different aspirations may shift all probabilities of positive impressions \(\{q_{\theta }(i)\}_{i\in N}\) either up or down, possibly in a non-linear fashion. However, this does not change the qualitative results of Propositions 1, and 2.
 
15
See Andonie and Diermeier (2019) for the details under plurality rule. The same holds for the other rules.
 
16
Two-candidate elections under plurality rule with impressionable voters have been analysed in detail in Andonie and Diermeier (2019). Here, we focus on the comparison among the three rules. We omit the proof of Proposition 3. The proof follows immediately by noting that the difference in the measures of votes of the two candidates, by Proposition 2, is \(S(1)-S(2)=\sum _{\theta }s_{\theta }(q_{\theta }(1)-q_{\theta }(2))\) in all three rules, and then using the same argument as in plurality rule.
 
17
Under approval voting, a voter that decides to vote will never vote for (or approve) both candidates, therefore (1, 1) can be eliminated from the set \(B^{a}\). In the negative rule, choosing action (1, 1) (i.e., abstention) is the same as choosing action (0, 0) in the other rules. Therefore, all sets B are the same in the three rules, and so their equilibria and associated behavior of voters will also be the same.
 
18
Under plurality rule, in the rational voter model there may be equilibria where voters vote for two of the candidates that excludes the uniformly preferred candidate. See, e.g., Proposition 1 in Myerson (2002).
 
19
Under negative plurality, in the rational voter model there may be equilibria where all candidates have a positive probability of winning. See, e.g., Proposition 2 in Myerson (2002).
 
20
Under approval voting, the concept of sincere voting is ambiguous. See, e.g., Myerson and Weber (1993) (footnote 11, p. 113), or Nunez (2014), for possible definitions of “sincere” voting under approval voting.
 
21
The assumptions that the measures of groups 1 and 2 of voters are the same, and that the component of impressions voters of groups 1 and 2 associate with candidate 3, i.e., parameter v, is the same for the two groups, are made for simplicity. The ordering of the three rules characterized in Lemma 1 does not change if, e.g., the parameters v of the two groups differ, but are close to one another.
 
22
Other cases that may be interesting are as follows. (1) If \(v>1\) and \(w>0\) then candidate 3 is “ranked” first by all voters. The analysis of this case is similar to that of \(v>1\) from the previous section, with similar conclusions. (2) If \(v<0\) and \(w<0\) then candidate 3 is “ranked” last by all voters. Again, the analysis of this case is similar to that of \(v<0\) from the previous section. (3) If \(v>1\) and \(w<0\) then voters of groups 1 and 2 “rank” candidate 3 first, while voters of group 3 “rank” candidate 3 last. The analysis and insights are similar to the case we discuss in this section.
 
23
The threshold \(w^{\phi }\) depends on various parameters such as v, F(.), \(\alpha\), etc. To simplify notation, we will write \(w^{\phi }\). It is possible that a value of w with this property does not exist. For example, if \(s\in (\frac{1}{4},\frac{1}{3})\), then in the plurality rule, a \(w^{p}\) with this property exists for any \(v<0\); in the approval rule, a \(w^{a}\) exists only for v with \(v^{a}<v<0\); while in the negative rule, a \(w^{n}\) exists only for v with \(v^{n}<v<0\). Moreover, the two cutoffs of v for the existence in the approval and negative rules are such that \(v^{a}<v^{n}<0\).
 
24
Specifically, the probabilities of positive impression of candidate 2 are such that: \(q_{1}(2),q_{2}(2)>\frac{1}{2}\) and \(q_{3}(2)<\frac{1}{2}\). This follows because v is large (in absolute value), and therefore the probabilities of positive impression of candidate 2 for groups 1, and 2 are: \(q_{1}(2),q_{2}(2)>\frac{1}{2}\). At the same time, the corresponding probability for group 3 is \(q_{3}(2)<\frac{1}{2}\) because group 3 of voters rank candidate 2 last.
 
25
Indeed, Lemma 1 implies that, if, for a given set of values of the model’s parameters (e.g., fixed components v, or w, distribution F(.), weight \(\alpha\), etc.), candidate 3 wins under negative plurality, or approval voting, then he must also win under plurality rule. However, this allows the possibility that candidate 3 wins under plurality rule, but loses under negative plurality, or approval voting, for some values of the parameters that fall under the case considered. In other words, the set of parameters’ values under which candidate 3 wins is largest under plurality rule, followed by approval voting, and is smallest under negative plurality.
 
26
In the election considered by Myerson and Weber (1993), the utilities (which correspond to the vectors of fixed components in the impressionable voter model) of the three groups of voters are: \(u_{1}=\{10,9,0\}\), \(u_{2}=\{9,10,0\}\) and \(u_{3}=\{0,0,10\}\). As the differences over candidates 1 and 2 of voters in groups 1 and 2 are small relative to their strong opposition of candidate 3, we consider the division between groups 1 and 2 to be “small”.
 
27
If \(\alpha \rightarrow 0\), then it can be shown that \(S(1)-S(3)\rightarrow -0.1\) under plurality rule, and \(S(1)-S(3)\rightarrow 0.2\) under approval voting. On the other hand, if \(\alpha \rightarrow +\infty\) then \(S(1)-S(3)\) converges to zero, from above, under both plurality and approval rules. Therefore, if the distribution function F() is continuous, then, e.g., if \(\alpha\) is sufficiently small, then \(S(1)-S(3)<0\) under plurality rule, and \(S(1)-S(3)>0\) under approval voting.
 
28
In a recent paper, Bouton and Ogden (2021) consider a model of ethical voting under plurality, and runoff rules, and find that the set of equilibria of their model depends on the magnitude of voters’ preferences as well. We discuss the runoff rule in the next section.
 
29
The analysis can be obtained from the authors upon request.
 
30
The most common threshold is \(h=0.5\), but other thresholds are also used, typically below 0.5 (Bouton 2013).
 
31
If \(n=2\) then there is no difference between the runoff and plurality rule.
 
32
We are assuming that the socially preferred candidate wins when confronting a less preferred candidate in the second round. However, under some particular cases this may not hold, e.g., a Condorcet winner can lose to a less preferred candidate in the second round, if the preferences of voters preferring the Condorcet winner are substantially “weaker” than those of voters preferring the opponent candidate (this can be seen by writing the difference of measures of votes in the second round, \(S^{II}(1)-S^{II}(2)\) from above, in terms of the distribution function F(.), and impression components \(v_{\theta }^{1}\) and \(v_{\theta }^{2}\).).
 
33
We note that differences in impression probabilities \(q_{\theta }(1)-q_{\theta }(i)\) also influence the sign of \(S^{I}(1)-S^{I}(i)\). However, they are relevant only when the differences in impression components \(v_{\theta }^{1}-v_{\theta }^{i}\) differ substantially across types of voters, and the socially preferred candidate corresponds to the Condorcet winner. In all other cases e.g., when the differences in impression components \(v_{\theta }^{1}-v_{\theta }^{i}\) are the same magnitude across types, or the socially preferred candidate corresponds to the utilitarian welfare maximizing candidate, the influence of the differences \(q_{\theta }(1)-q_{\theta }(i)\) is irrelevant.
 
34
To break the tie between candidates 2 and 3, we can assume, for example, that voters of group 2 marginally prefer candidate 2 to candidate 3, i.e., their vector of fixed components is \(u_{2}=\{0,1+\eta ,1\}\), where \(\eta >0\) and small. The qualitative results of Proposition 6 will be the same.
 
35
They also apply to the election with four candidates, and three groups of voters we discuss below.
 
36
For voters of group 1: \(v_{1}^{3}=0\) and \(a_{1}=\frac{1}{3}\), while for voters of group 2: \(v_{2}^{3}=1\) and \(a_{2}=\frac{2}{3}\).
 
37
As in the previous example, to break the tie between candidates 3 and 4, we can assume, for example, that a majority of voters marginally prefers candidate 3 to candidate 4. Again, the qualitative results will be the same as in Proposition 7.
 
38
For some common distributions, e.g., \(U[-1,+1]\), \(\alpha ^{*}=+\infty\). So they do not require restrictions on the values of \(\alpha\).
 
39
For voters of group 1: \(v_{1}^{2}=0\), \(v_{1}^{4}=0\) and \(a_{1}=\frac{1}{4}\), while for voters of group 3: \(v_{3}^{2}=0\), \(v_{3}^{4}=1\) and \(a_{3}=\frac{1 }{2}\).
 
40
For voters of group 2 we have that \(q_{3}(1)=q_{3}(3)\), and therefore their votes do not influence the difference \(S^{I}(1)-S^{I}(3)\).
 
41
We discuss laboratory experiments in the Conclusion. Here we focus on multi-candidate elections. The absence of studies of two candidate elections under different electoral rules may be due to the fact that in a rational voter model all voting rules lead to equivalent outcomes.
 
42
See Andonie and Diermeier (2017) for details.
 
43
In the run-off elections we studied previously only two candidates can run in the second round. However, it is straightforward to modify the model and its analysis so that three candidates can run in the second round, like in the French elections.
 
44
See e.g., Forsythe et al. (1993), Forsythe et al. (1996), Levine and Palfrey (2007), Bouton et al. (2016), Bouton et al. (2017), among others.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Achen CH, Bartels LM (2002) Blind Retrospection: Electoral Responses to Droughts, Flu, and Shark Attacks. In: Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Boston, September, 2002 Achen CH, Bartels LM (2002) Blind Retrospection: Electoral Responses to Droughts, Flu, and Shark Attacks. In: Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Boston, September, 2002
Zurück zum Zitat Achen CH, Bartels LM (2004) Musical Chairs: Pocketbook Voting and the Limits of Democratic Accountability. In: Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Chicago, September, 2004 Achen CH, Bartels LM (2004) Musical Chairs: Pocketbook Voting and the Limits of Democratic Accountability. In: Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Chicago, September, 2004
Zurück zum Zitat Achen CH, Bartels LM (2016) Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do Not Produce Responsive Government. and Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press Achen CH, Bartels LM (2016) Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do Not Produce Responsive Government. and Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Andonie C, Diermeier D (2017) Path-Dependency and Coordination in Multi-Candidate Elections with Behavioral Voters. J Theor Polit 29(4):520–545CrossRef Andonie C, Diermeier D (2017) Path-Dependency and Coordination in Multi-Candidate Elections with Behavioral Voters. J Theor Polit 29(4):520–545CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Andonie C, Diermeier D (2019) Impressionable voters. Am Econ J Microecon 11(1):79–104CrossRef Andonie C, Diermeier D (2019) Impressionable voters. Am Econ J Microecon 11(1):79–104CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ashworth S (2012) Electoral accountability: recent theoretical and empirical work. Annu Rev Polit Sci 15:183–201CrossRef Ashworth S (2012) Electoral accountability: recent theoretical and empirical work. Annu Rev Polit Sci 15:183–201CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ashworth S, Bueno E, de Mesquita (2014) Is Voter Competence Good for Voters?: Information, Rationality, and Democratic Performance. Am Polit Sci Rev 108(3):565–587 Ashworth S, Bueno E, de Mesquita (2014) Is Voter Competence Good for Voters?: Information, Rationality, and Democratic Performance. Am Polit Sci Rev 108(3):565–587
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor J (2010) Bounded Rationality and Politics. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press Bendor J (2010) Bounded Rationality and Politics. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor J, Diermeier D, Ting M (2003) A behavioral model of turnout. Am Polit Sci Rev 97:261–280CrossRef Bendor J, Diermeier D, Ting M (2003) A behavioral model of turnout. Am Polit Sci Rev 97:261–280CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor J, Kumar S, Siegel DA (2010) Adaptively rational retrospective voting. J Theor Polit 22(1):26–63CrossRef Bendor J, Kumar S, Siegel DA (2010) Adaptively rational retrospective voting. J Theor Polit 22(1):26–63CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor J, Diermeier D, Siegel D, Ting M (2011) A Behavioral Theory of Elections. Princeton University Press, PrincetonCrossRef Bendor J, Diermeier D, Siegel D, Ting M (2011) A Behavioral Theory of Elections. Princeton University Press, PrincetonCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bordignon M, Nannicini T, Tabellini G (2016) Moderating political extremism: single round versus runoff elections under plurality rule. Am Econ Rev 106(8):2349–2370CrossRef Bordignon M, Nannicini T, Tabellini G (2016) Moderating political extremism: single round versus runoff elections under plurality rule. Am Econ Rev 106(8):2349–2370CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Borgers T, Sarin R (2000) Naive reinforcement learning with endogenous aspirations. Int Econ Rev 41:921–950CrossRef Borgers T, Sarin R (2000) Naive reinforcement learning with endogenous aspirations. Int Econ Rev 41:921–950CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton L (2013) A theory of strategic voting in runoff elections. Am Econ Rev 103:1248–1288CrossRef Bouton L (2013) A theory of strategic voting in runoff elections. Am Econ Rev 103:1248–1288CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton L, Castanheira M (2012) One person, many votes: divided majority and information aggregation. Econometrica 80(1):43–87CrossRef Bouton L, Castanheira M (2012) One person, many votes: divided majority and information aggregation. Econometrica 80(1):43–87CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton L, Gratton G (2015) Majority runoff elections: Strategic voting and Duverger’s hypothesis. Theor Econ 10:283–314CrossRef Bouton L, Gratton G (2015) Majority runoff elections: Strategic voting and Duverger’s hypothesis. Theor Econ 10:283–314CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton L, Castanheira M, Llorente-Saguer A (2016) Divided majority and information aggregation: theory and experiment. J Public Econ 134:114–128CrossRef Bouton L, Castanheira M, Llorente-Saguer A (2016) Divided majority and information aggregation: theory and experiment. J Public Econ 134:114–128CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton L, Castanheira M, Llorente-Saguer A (2017) Multicandidate elections: aggregate uncertainty in the laboratory. Games Econom Behav 101:132–150CrossRef Bouton L, Castanheira M, Llorente-Saguer A (2017) Multicandidate elections: aggregate uncertainty in the laboratory. Games Econom Behav 101:132–150CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton L, Ogden BG (2021) Group-based voting in multicandidate elections. J Politics 83(2):468–482CrossRef Bouton L, Ogden BG (2021) Group-based voting in multicandidate elections. J Politics 83(2):468–482CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brams S, Fishburn P (2005) Going from theory to practice: the mixed success of approval voting. Soc Choice Welf 25:457–74CrossRef Brams S, Fishburn P (2005) Going from theory to practice: the mixed success of approval voting. Soc Choice Welf 25:457–74CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brams S, Nagel J (1991) Approval voting in practice. Public Choice 71(1/2):1–17CrossRef Brams S, Nagel J (1991) Approval voting in practice. Public Choice 71(1/2):1–17CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bush R, Mosteller F (1955) Stochastic Models of Learning. Wiley, New YorkCrossRef Bush R, Mosteller F (1955) Stochastic Models of Learning. Wiley, New YorkCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cho I-K, Matsui A (2005) Learning aspiration in repeated games. J Econ Theory 124:171–2001CrossRef Cho I-K, Matsui A (2005) Learning aspiration in repeated games. J Econ Theory 124:171–2001CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cole S, Healy A, Werker E (2012) Do voters demand responsive governments? evidence from Indian disaster relief. J Dev Econ 97:167–181CrossRef Cole S, Healy A, Werker E (2012) Do voters demand responsive governments? evidence from Indian disaster relief. J Dev Econ 97:167–181CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cox Gary W (1997) Making Votes Count. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Cox Gary W (1997) Making Votes Count. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Cox GW (1994) Strategic voting equilibria under the single non-transferable vote. Am Polit Sci Rev 88:608–621CrossRef Cox GW (1994) Strategic voting equilibria under the single non-transferable vote. Am Polit Sci Rev 88:608–621CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Diermeier D, Krehbiel K (2003) Institutionalism as a Methodology. J Theor Polit 15(2):123–144CrossRef Diermeier D, Krehbiel K (2003) Institutionalism as a Methodology. J Theor Polit 15(2):123–144CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Diermeier D, Li C (2017) Electoral control with behavioral voters. J Polit 79(3):890–902CrossRef Diermeier D, Li C (2017) Electoral control with behavioral voters. J Polit 79(3):890–902CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fey M (1997) Stability and coordination in Duverger’s law: a formal model of pre-election polls and strategic voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 91:135–147CrossRef Fey M (1997) Stability and coordination in Duverger’s law: a formal model of pre-election polls and strategic voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 91:135–147CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn P, Little J (1988) An experiment in approval voting. Manag Sci 34(5):555–68CrossRef Fishburn P, Little J (1988) An experiment in approval voting. Manag Sci 34(5):555–68CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Forsythe R, Myerson RB, Rietz TA, Weber RJ (1993) An experiment on coordination in multicandidate elections: the importance of polls and election histories. Soc Choice Welf 10:223–247CrossRef Forsythe R, Myerson RB, Rietz TA, Weber RJ (1993) An experiment on coordination in multicandidate elections: the importance of polls and election histories. Soc Choice Welf 10:223–247CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Forsythe R, Myerson R, Rietz T, Weber R (1996) An experimental study of voting rules and polls in three-candidate elections. Int J Game Theory 25:355–383CrossRef Forsythe R, Myerson R, Rietz T, Weber R (1996) An experimental study of voting rules and polls in three-candidate elections. Int J Game Theory 25:355–383CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fujiwara T (2011) A regression discontinuity test of strategic voting and Duverger’s law. Q J Polit Sci 6:197–233CrossRef Fujiwara T (2011) A regression discontinuity test of strategic voting and Duverger’s law. Q J Polit Sci 6:197–233CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gasper JT, Reeves A (2011) Make it rain? retrospection and the attentive electorate in the context of natural disasters. Am J Polit Sci 55(2):340–355CrossRef Gasper JT, Reeves A (2011) Make it rain? retrospection and the attentive electorate in the context of natural disasters. Am J Polit Sci 55(2):340–355CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Healy A, Mo C, Malhotra N (2010) Irrelevant events affect voters’ evaluations of Government performance. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(28):12506–12511 Healy A, Mo C, Malhotra N (2010) Irrelevant events affect voters’ evaluations of Government performance. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(28):12506–12511
Zurück zum Zitat Hilgard ER, Bower GH (1966) Theories of learning. Appleton-Century-Crofts, New York Hilgard ER, Bower GH (1966) Theories of learning. Appleton-Century-Crofts, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Karandikar R, Mookherjee D, Ray D, Vega-Redondo F (1998) Evolving aspirations and cooperation. J Econ Theory 80:292–331CrossRef Karandikar R, Mookherjee D, Ray D, Vega-Redondo F (1998) Evolving aspirations and cooperation. J Econ Theory 80:292–331CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kinder DR (1998) Opinion and Action in the Realm of Politics. In: The Handbook of Social Psychology, ed. D. Gilbert, S. Fiske and G. Lindzey. 4 ed. Boston: McGraw-Hill pp 778–867 Kinder DR (1998) Opinion and Action in the Realm of Politics. In: The Handbook of Social Psychology, ed. D. Gilbert, S. Fiske and G. Lindzey. 4 ed. Boston: McGraw-Hill pp 778–867
Zurück zum Zitat Krishna V, Morgan J (2015) Majority Rule and Utilitarian Welfare. Am Econ J Microecon 7(4):339–75CrossRef Krishna V, Morgan J (2015) Majority Rule and Utilitarian Welfare. Am Econ J Microecon 7(4):339–75CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Levine DK, Palfrey TR (2007) The Paradox of voter participation? A Laboratory study. Am Polit Sci Rev 101(1):143–158CrossRef Levine DK, Palfrey TR (2007) The Paradox of voter participation? A Laboratory study. Am Polit Sci Rev 101(1):143–158CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myatt DP, Fisher SD (2002a) Everything is Uncertain and Uncertainty is Everything: Strategic Voting in Simple Plurality Elections. University of Oxford, Discussion Paper Series, Number 115 Myatt DP, Fisher SD (2002a) Everything is Uncertain and Uncertainty is Everything: Strategic Voting in Simple Plurality Elections. University of Oxford, Discussion Paper Series, Number 115
Zurück zum Zitat Myatt DP (2007) On the theory of strategic voting. Rev Econ Stud 74:255–281CrossRef Myatt DP (2007) On the theory of strategic voting. Rev Econ Stud 74:255–281CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myatt DP, Fisher SD (2002) Tactical coordination in plurality electoral systems. Oxford Rev Econ Policy 18(4):504–522CrossRef Myatt DP, Fisher SD (2002) Tactical coordination in plurality electoral systems. Oxford Rev Econ Policy 18(4):504–522CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myerson RB (1999) Theoretical comparisons of electoral systems. Eur Econ Rev 43:671–697CrossRef Myerson RB (1999) Theoretical comparisons of electoral systems. Eur Econ Rev 43:671–697CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myerson RB (2002) Comparison of Scoring Rules in Poisson Voting Games. J Econ Theory 103:219–251CrossRef Myerson RB (2002) Comparison of Scoring Rules in Poisson Voting Games. J Econ Theory 103:219–251CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myerson RB, Weber RJ (1993) A theory of voting equilibria. Am Polit Sci Rev 87:102–114CrossRef Myerson RB, Weber RJ (1993) A theory of voting equilibria. Am Polit Sci Rev 87:102–114CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nunez M (2014) The strategic sincerity of approval voting. Econ Theor 56:157–189CrossRef Nunez M (2014) The strategic sincerity of approval voting. Econ Theor 56:157–189CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Palfrey TR (1989) A mathematical proof of Duverger’s Law. In: Peter CO (ed) Models of strategic choice in politics. University of Michigan Press, pp 69–92 Palfrey TR (1989) A mathematical proof of Duverger’s Law. In: Peter CO (ed) Models of strategic choice in politics. University of Michigan Press, pp 69–92
Zurück zum Zitat Palfrey T, Rosenthal H (1983) A strategic calculus of voting. Public Choice 41:7–53CrossRef Palfrey T, Rosenthal H (1983) A strategic calculus of voting. Public Choice 41:7–53CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Palfrey T, Rosenthal H (1985) Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. Am Polit Sci Rev 79:62–78CrossRef Palfrey T, Rosenthal H (1985) Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. Am Polit Sci Rev 79:62–78CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Palomino F, Vega-Redondo F (1999) Convergence of Aspirations and (partial) Cooperation in the Prisoner’s Dilemma. Int J Game Theory 28:465–488CrossRef Palomino F, Vega-Redondo F (1999) Convergence of Aspirations and (partial) Cooperation in the Prisoner’s Dilemma. Int J Game Theory 28:465–488CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pons V, Tricaud C (2018) Expressive voting and its cost: evidence from runoffs with two or three candidates. Econometrica 86(5):1621–1649CrossRef Pons V, Tricaud C (2018) Expressive voting and its cost: evidence from runoffs with two or three candidates. Econometrica 86(5):1621–1649CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Richard C, James M (1963) A Behavioral Theory of the Firm. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs Richard C, James M (1963) A Behavioral Theory of the Firm. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs
Zurück zum Zitat Simon H (1955) A behavioral model of rational choice. Q J Econ 69(1):99–118CrossRef Simon H (1955) A behavioral model of rational choice. Q J Econ 69(1):99–118CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Spenkuch JL (2018) Expressive vs. strategic voters: an empirical assessment. J Public Econ 165:73–81CrossRef Spenkuch JL (2018) Expressive vs. strategic voters: an empirical assessment. J Public Econ 165:73–81CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Thorndike EL (1898) Animal intelligence: an experimental study of the associative processes in animals. Psychol Rev (Monograph Supplement) 2(8) Thorndike EL (1898) Animal intelligence: an experimental study of the associative processes in animals. Psychol Rev (Monograph Supplement) 2(8)
Zurück zum Zitat Wolfers J (2002) Are Voters Rational? Evidence from Gubernatorial Elections. Stanford GSB Working Paper no. 1730 Wolfers J (2002) Are Voters Rational? Evidence from Gubernatorial Elections. Stanford GSB Working Paper no. 1730
Metadaten
Titel
Electoral Institutions with impressionable voters
verfasst von
Costel Andonie
Daniel Diermeier
Publikationsdatum
07.05.2022
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Erschienen in
Social Choice and Welfare / Ausgabe 3/2022
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Elektronische ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-022-01406-6

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3/2022

Social Choice and Welfare 3/2022 Zur Ausgabe