Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Minds and Machines 4/2019

19-10-2019

A Common Frame for Formal Imagination

Authors: Joan Casas-Roma, M. Elena Rodríguez, Antonia Huertas

Published in: Minds and Machines | Issue 4/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

In this paper, we review three influential theories of imagination in order to understand how the dynamics of imagination acts could be modeled using formal languages. While reviewing them, we notice that they are not detailed enough to account for all the mechanisms involved in creating and developing imaginary worlds. We claim those theories could be further refined into what we call the Common Frame for Imagination Acts, which defines a framework that can be used to study the dynamics of imagination using formal languages, and we support our claim by showing how the framework allows to model certain imagination acts step by step. Then, we introduce the Rhombus of Imagination, which is a visual tool that can be used in conjunction with our framework to study the procedural structure of different kinds of imagination acts and identify their dynamic properties.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
In relation to Van Leeuwen (2013), we can say that our interest lies in constructive imagining.
 
2
It is worth noting how, on page 127, the authors explain that, without taking action into account, their theory of pretense can be understood as a theory of imagination, which is in fact where our interest lies in this work.
 
3
It is worth noting that, as argued in Spaulding (2016), Williamson uses the term “imagination” in a broad sense, which includes supposition, the evaluation of conjunctive conditionals, and so on.
 
4
As the author points out in Balcerak-Jackson (2016), succeeding in such voluntary action may vary depending on whether we are supposing, imagining or conceiving.
 
5
Note that, if possible worlds are used as formal models, imaginary worlds will then be required to be formally consistent. Nevertheless, different authors, such as Priest (2016), Berto (2017), or even Nichols and Stich in Nichols and Stich (2003) argue that one can also imagine impossible scenarios. If we wanted to allow for paraconsistent imaginings, our approach could be adapted to accommodate the use of impossible worlds in the way they are used, for instance, in Berto (2017).
 
6
In the formal definition, we use the expression “\(p_{j}\) is accounted for in \(\varphi\)” to express the fact that the truth conditions for the formula \(\varphi\) determine the truth-value of the atomic formula \(p_{j}\) by requiring it to be either true or false in the state of affairs described by \(\varphi\).
 
7
For a comprehensive introduction to propositional logic, see Hodges (2001), for instance.
 
8
Particularly, on page 118 of Nichols and Stich (2000), they identify both processes as the inferential elaboration, without distinguishing between their static or dynamic character.
 
9
It is important to note that Fig. 5 is not meant to be a Kripke model, but rather just a schematic representation of the process. As such, and in order to stress out the fact that this process elaborates on the details of the same imaginary world, we represent believed factual rules using standard propositional logic and without any kind of modal operator. Figure 5, then, aims to represent how the world on the left changes into the world on the right, rather than representing that both worlds are different, in terms of possible-worlds semantics. For more details on modal logic, see Blackburn et al. (2010).
 
10
Note that, although this kind of expressions can be mapped into Lewis’ account of counterfactuals in Lewis (1973), the way they are used in our approach is different. Whereas Lewis’ approach of such expression would “move” the point of evaluation to a different world where both antecedent and consequent are the case, our approach “breaks down” the evaluation in two different steps. First, it checks whether the antecedent is already the case in the current world and, if so, then creates a new world, which represents a refinement of the current one, and in which the consequent also holds. The notion of “refinement” can be, in fact, a bit controversial when thinking about possible worlds; after all, possible worlds are maximally consistent sets of formulas in which each and every atomic formula is already assigned a truth-value. We use the term “refinement” is a more informal or intuitive way. Even if the truth-value of all atomic formulas needs to be set in our imaginary worlds, their truth-value may be the result of importing it from the world of reference, instead of determining what is should be by looking at how the imagining develops. In this sense, and even if the technical apparatus behind a classical approach requires all atomic formulas to have a truth-value, by “refining” the world we mean that, by pulling onto certain factual beliefs, the agent “realizes” that the truth-value of certain atomic formulas should change in the imagining, with respect to what they were before. In this sense, “refining” a world could be understood as “updating” the truth-values of certain atomic formulas step-by-step, given the factual rules believed by the agent. Those “refinement” steps could be seen as specific executions of some of the broader sets of inferential mechanisms identified by previous authors.
 
11
In Funkhouser and Spaulding (2009), the authors use the term “script” to refer to something that can be imitated or enacted, and that can guide action without the need of being backed up by beliefs or knowledge. Our use of the term differs from theirs in the sense that, in our account, scripts are not meant to guide an actual action, but rather to set, according to the current state of the imaginary scenario, which actions or events could take place in there. In particular, our scripts encode something like “in a situation in which such and such was the case, executing action \(\alpha\) could lead to this set of outcomes”. Scripts, then, are neither guides to enact an action, nor a way to assign a tendency to certain actions to happen in an imaginary scenario, but rather a way of determining what an action could bring about, given the conditions of such scenario. Therefore, although both our and their use of the term “script” has some similarities, as in both cases it concerns actions that could happen in an imaginary scenario, in our setting scripts are just meant to open new modal paths opened up by certain actions or events.
 
12
It could be argued that, in fact, scripts do provide some information regarding what actions are most likely to occur in a certain scenario. Nevertheless, the structures we use to define our approach do not allow to capture, at least not explicitly, this notion of “typicality”, or “likeliness” for an action to happen in a given scenario. Instead, our approach assumes that the agent already has scripts about every possible action available; what makes an action “executable” in a certain scenario, then, is determined by the conditions that the script should fulfill in order to bring about its consequences. More intuitively, the action “pour tea into a cup” would only have an actual effect in those scenarios in which, for instance, there is a cup and a tea pot, but it will not affect, say, a scenario where there are only apples and oranges on a table. Even though our approach, as it is, cannot yet account for updating the likeliness of certain actions to be imagined in particular scenarios, it could be extended by including a kind of “sorted preference list” over scripts for the imagining being entertained. The list would have to be ordered in such a way that, the closer the current imagining is to the preconditions of a particular script, the more relevant this script becomes in the list, and thus the more likely it is to be selected by the agent.
 
13
In Fact, Langland-Hassan argues that these kind of additions, which Nichols and Stich attribute to their opaque Script Elaborator, are nothing more than new premises that the agent clamps to the imaginary scenario.
 
14
It is only fair to note how, considering the way the Description algorithm works, it still creates a new state of affairs related via an accessibility relation. Nevertheless, and conversely to what happens with the Default Evolution, this transition is purely meant to capture a refinement of a static scenario, rather than an actual event occurring in the scenario being represented. In other words, these refinements can be interpreted as small “reasoning steps” similar to those that appear in Velazquez Quesada (2011). If a formal layer for time was to be added to our approach, only those transitions labeled with an action would represent an actual change in time, whereas those transitions resulting from an execution of the Description would still represent a scenario at the same time instant.
 
15
When considering other, more specific kinds of imagination acts, it could be necessary to add additional vertex to the rhombus. For instance, a vertex accounting for actions, in the case of pretense, or another one accounting for emotions, in the case of empathy.
 
16
In paradigmatic cases of fiction, such as medieval fantasy stories, this set of reality-oriented rules and facts is not only formed by those rules the agent believes about the real, actual world, but also by those rules that usually apply to the fictional setting being depicted. This latter kinds of rules correspond to Genre Truths, as identified in Funkhouser and Spaulding (2009). Additionally, but still related to this kind of paradigmatic rules, Lewis (1978) offers an account on how to assess truth in fiction.
 
Literature
go back to reference Balcerak-Jackson, M. (2016). On the epistemic value of imagining, supposing and conceiving. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 41–60). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef Balcerak-Jackson, M. (2016). On the epistemic value of imagining, supposing and conceiving. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 41–60). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef
go back to reference Berto, F. (2014). On conceiving the inconsistent. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Hardback), Wiley Online Library, vol. 114, 1.1, pp. 103–121. Berto, F. (2014). On conceiving the inconsistent. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Hardback), Wiley Online Library, vol. 114, 1.1, pp. 103–121.
go back to reference Blackburn, P., De Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2010). Modal Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.MATH Blackburn, P., De Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2010). Modal Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.MATH
go back to reference Costa-Leite, A. (2011). Logical properties of imagination. Abstracta, 6(1), 103–116. Costa-Leite, A. (2011). Logical properties of imagination. Abstracta, 6(1), 103–116.
go back to reference Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Funkhouser, E., & Spaulding, S. (2009). Imagination and other scripts. Philosophical Studies, 143(3), 291–314.CrossRef Funkhouser, E., & Spaulding, S. (2009). Imagination and other scripts. Philosophical Studies, 143(3), 291–314.CrossRef
go back to reference Harel, D. (1984). Dynamic logic. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, volume II: Extensions of Classical Logic (pp. 497–604). Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company.CrossRef Harel, D. (1984). Dynamic logic. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, volume II: Extensions of Classical Logic (pp. 497–604). Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company.CrossRef
go back to reference Hodges, W. (2001). Logic: An introduction to elementary logic. London: Penguin Books.MATH Hodges, W. (2001). Logic: An introduction to elementary logic. London: Penguin Books.MATH
go back to reference Kind, A. (2016a). Desire-like imagination. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 163–176). New York: Routledge. Kind, A. (2016a). Desire-like imagination. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 163–176). New York: Routledge.
go back to reference Kind, A. (2016b). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination. Taylor & Francis Group: Routledge. Kind, A. (2016b). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination. Taylor & Francis Group: Routledge.
go back to reference Langland-Hassan, P. (2016). On choosing what to imagine. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 61–84). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef Langland-Hassan, P. (2016). On choosing what to imagine. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 61–84). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef
go back to reference Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. New Jersey: Blackwell Publishing.MATH Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. New Jersey: Blackwell Publishing.MATH
go back to reference Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1), 37–46. Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1), 37–46.
go back to reference Nanay, B. (2016). The role of imagination in decision-making. Mind and Language, 31(1), 126–142.CrossRef Nanay, B. (2016). The role of imagination in decision-making. Mind and Language, 31(1), 126–142.CrossRef
go back to reference Nichols, S. (2006). The architecture of the imagination: New essays on pretence, possibility, and fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Nichols, S. (2006). The architecture of the imagination: New essays on pretence, possibility, and fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74(2), 115–147.CrossRef Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74(2), 115–147.CrossRef
go back to reference Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.CrossRef Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Niiniluoto, I. (1985). Imagination and fiction. Journal of Semantics, 4(3), 209–222.CrossRef Niiniluoto, I. (1985). Imagination and fiction. Journal of Semantics, 4(3), 209–222.CrossRef
go back to reference Rucińska, Z. (2016). What guides pretence? towards the interactive and the narrative approaches. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(1), 117–133.CrossRef Rucińska, Z. (2016). What guides pretence? towards the interactive and the narrative approaches. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(1), 117–133.CrossRef
go back to reference Shirazi, A., & Amir, E. (2007). Probabilistic modal logic. In R. Holte, A. Howe, (Eds.), Proceedings of the 22nd AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp. 489–495. Shirazi, A., & Amir, E. (2007). Probabilistic modal logic. In R. Holte, A. Howe, (Eds.), Proceedings of the 22nd AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp. 489–495.
go back to reference Sinhababu, N. (2016). Imagination and belief. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 111–123). New York: Routledge. Sinhababu, N. (2016). Imagination and belief. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 111–123). New York: Routledge.
go back to reference Sorensen, R. A. (1992). Thought experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sorensen, R. A. (1992). Thought experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Spaulding, S. (2016). Imagination through knowledge. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 207–226). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef Spaulding, S. (2016). Imagination through knowledge. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 207–226). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef
go back to reference Van Leeuwen, N. (2013). The meanings of “imagine” part i: Constructive imagination. Philosophy Compass, 8(3), 220–230.CrossRef Van Leeuwen, N. (2013). The meanings of “imagine” part i: Constructive imagination. Philosophy Compass, 8(3), 220–230.CrossRef
go back to reference Velazquez Quesada, F. R. (2011). Small steps in dynamics of information. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation. Velazquez Quesada, F. R. (2011). Small steps in dynamics of information. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation.
go back to reference Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Wansing, H. (2017). Remarks on the logic of imagination. A step towards understanding doxastic control through imagination. Synthese, 194(8), 2843–2861.MathSciNetCrossRef Wansing, H. (2017). Remarks on the logic of imagination. A step towards understanding doxastic control through imagination. Synthese, 194(8), 2843–2861.MathSciNetCrossRef
go back to reference Weinberg, J. M., & Meskin, A. (2006). Puzzling over the imagination: Philosophical problems, architectural solutions. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination: New essays on pretence, possibility, and fiction (pp. 175–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Weinberg, J. M., & Meskin, A. (2006). Puzzling over the imagination: Philosophical problems, architectural solutions. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination: New essays on pretence, possibility, and fiction (pp. 175–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Williamson, T. (2016). Knowing by imagining. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 113–123). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef Williamson, T. (2016). Knowing by imagining. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 113–123). Oxford: OUP.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
A Common Frame for Formal Imagination
Authors
Joan Casas-Roma
M. Elena Rodríguez
Antonia Huertas
Publication date
19-10-2019
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Minds and Machines / Issue 4/2019
Print ISSN: 0924-6495
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8641
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-019-09510-w

Other articles of this Issue 4/2019

Minds and Machines 4/2019 Go to the issue

Premium Partner