Skip to main content
Top
Published in: The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2019

08-05-2018

Adult Children’s Obligations Towards Their Parents: A Contractualist Explanation

Author: William Sin

Published in: The Journal of Value Inquiry | Issue 1/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Excerpt

How should we understand the moral relation between adult children and their parents? What obligations do adult children have when their parents become sick and frail in their old age? These are the questions I attempt to answer in this paper. More specifically, since adult children have both impersonal and personal reasons to care for their parents, I use Scanlon’s theory of contractualism to answer the questions. Scanlon’s contractualism can consider the respective obligations from a personal point of view. The characteristic motivation of his theory is to identify the moral principles which are suitable to “serve as the basis of mutual recognition and accommodation.”1 Agents can take others’ interests into account and can act from principles which the other party, as well as the agent himself, have reason to accept. …

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), p. 194.
 
2
Shelley Kagan, The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989).
 
3
Adult children’s obligation to help their parents will be affected by the quality of parenting which they received from their parents. In my discussion, I assume that the aging parents have been responsible parents, who didn’t seriously neglect or abuse their children in the past.
 
4
The Moderate Principle covers a wide spectrum. We will need further explanation to determine the exact level of demand of this principle. See William Sin, “Trivial Sacrifices, Great Demands,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (2010): 3–15.
 
5
United Nations, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Population Division (2017). World Population Prospects: The 2017 Revision; United Nations Development Programme, Human Development Report 2013. The Rise of the South: Human Progress in a Diverse World (New York, NY: United Nation Development Programme, 2013).
 
6
Christine Vogeli, Alexandra E. Shields, Todd A. Lee, Teresa B. Gibson, William D. Marder, Kevin B. Weiss & David Blumenthal “Multiple Chronic Conditions: Prevalence, Health Consequences, and Implications for Quality, Care Management, and Costs,” Journal of General Internal Medicine 22 (Suppl. 3), (2007): 391–395; Jennifer L. Wolff, Barbara Starfield, and Gerard Anderson “Prevalence, Expenditures, and Complications of Multiple Chronic Conditions in the Elderly,” Archives of Internal Medicine 162 (20) (2002): 2269–2276. See also Center for Disease Control. Chronic Disease Prevention and Promotion. Retrieved from https://​www.​cdc.​gov/​chronicdisease/​index.​htm.
 
7
United Nations, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Population Division (2010). World Population Prospects: The 2010 Revision; Dominic Bailey, Mick Ruddy, and Marina Shchukina, “Ageing China: Changes and Challenges.” BBC News Asia, September 20, 2012. Retrieved from http://​www.​bbc.​com/​news/​world-asia-19630110.
 
8
Confucians believe that adult children have strong obligations to reciprocate, and that filial obligations trump other moral concerns. See Confucius: The Analects (D. C. Lau, Trans.). (New York: Penguin Books, 1979), 13.18 and Mencius (D. C. Lau, Trans.). (New York: Penguin Books, 1970), 7A35. On a moderate interpretation of the Confucian demands, see Philip J. Ivanhoe “Filial Piety as a Virtue,” In Rebecca L. Walker and Philip J. Ivanhoe (eds.), Working Virtue: Virtue Ethics and Contemporary Moral Problems (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 297–311.
 
9
Some writers hold that adult children are not morally responsible for supporting their parents’ lives at all, and that filial obligations are by their nature oppressive or parochial. See A. John Simmons Moral Principles and Political Obligations (New Jersey, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), pp. 157–190; Michael Slote, “Obedience and Illusions,” In Onora O’Neill and William Ruddick (eds.), Having Children (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 319–326.
 
10
This story, together with the remarks made by Mrs. Fischer, is taken from John Leland, “For Families of the Ailing, a Brief Chance to Relax.” New York Times, August 18, 2008. Retrieved from http://​www.​nytimes.​com/​2008/​08/​19/​health/​19aging.​html. I am grateful to Daniel Wikler who drew my attention to this case.
 
11
Social Welfare Department, the Government of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region. Overview of Residential Care Services for Elders, 2012. http://​www.​swd.​gov.​hk/​en/​index/​site_​pubsvc/​page_​elderly/​ sub_residentia/id_overviewon. Accessed 24 March 2018.
 
12
Elisabeth J. Croll, “The Intergenerational Contract in the Changing Asian Family,” Oxford Development Studies 34 (2006): 473–491. Chau-Kiu Cheung and Alex Yui-Huen Kwan, “The Erosion of Filial Piety by Modernization in Chinese Cities,” Ageing and Society 29 (2009): 179–198.
 
13
Cecilia. L. W. Chan, Andy H. Y. Ho, Pamela P. Y. Leung, Harvey M. Chochinov, Robert A. Neimeyer, Samantha M. C. Pang & Doris M. W. Tse “The blessings and the curses of filial piety on dignity at the end of life: Lived experience of Hong Kong Chinese adult children caregivers,” Journal of Ethnic and Cultural Diversity in Social Work 21 (2012): 277–296, p. 281.
 
14
Ibid., p. 288.
 
15
Ibid.
 
16
That a family is regarded as a family because when some members of which suffer a loss, the rest may feel the same. Scanlon, op. cit., p. 129: “[W]e would not be good friends or family members or loyal members of our institutions if we did not feel a loss to them as a loss to us.”
 
17
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Revised Edition) (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 111.
 
18
Scanlon, op. cit., pp. 191–192, 194.
 
19
Ibid., pp. 4, 153.
 
20
Scanlon, ibid., p. 214 stresses that contractualism involves “a holism about moral justification.”
 
21
Ibid., pp. 195, 208, 211.
 
22
Elizabeth Ashford, “The Demandingness of Scanlon’s Contractualism,” Ethics 113 (2003): 273–302.
 
23
Scanlon, op. cit., p. 196.
 
24
Ashford, op. cit., p. 279. For Scanlon, a person’s level of welfare (or the considerations of cost alone) is not the sole criterion of reasonable rejection; it also matters how those costs will be imposed on the agent (op. cit., p. 196) and how the “framework of entitlements” (op. cit., p. 214) is structured in the circumstance.
 
25
Ashford, op. cit., p. 281.
 
26
Ibid.
 
27
The case of Shipwreck is discussed in Sin, op. cit., p. 13. I owed this case to Daniel Wikler.
 
28
As a thought experiment, Shipwreck has involved abstractions from certain particularities in real life. One may wonder, for example, if Joan’s life contains only the basic activities necessary to survive and have leisure. People will follow different long-term projects and commitments, and will maintain relations with others in reality. I have not entered into discussions concerning the potential conflicts between an agent’s need to support his parents and to maintain some of these projects. The reason is that I want to focus the discussion on the conflict between the agent’s need to live his own life and his need to respond to the moral demands of filial duties. My thought is that if people’s pure freedom to live their own lives can be warranted against the claim of morality to assist the needy, this argument will reinforce the agent’s claim for the legitimacy of his maintaining other projects and commitments too.
 
29
Without the attachment of the threshold view, the Moderate Principle may require agents to make significant contributions indefinitely, which will give rise to extreme moral demands.
 
30
Needless to say, the same argument can apply to the threshold version of the Extreme Principle.
 
31
It is possible to adopt either an iterative reading or an aggregate reading to understand the threshold view. The iterative reading asks from time to time when Joan will acquire the supererogation as she keeps riding the bike (or when she will restart the obligation as she takes the break). Such a reading may make the threshold view nonsensical. The threshold view makes sense if we interpret it in terms of qualitative changes in the situation or in terms of the overall balance when one compares different long-term alternatives (which is the aggregate reading). It is worth noting that Scanlon, op. cit., p. 224 also endorses the aggregate reading when he introduces the Rescue Principle. But I worry that the aggregate reading will ultimately be replaced by the iterative reading as we apply the pairwise comparison time and again in either the case of famine relief or that of long-term caregiving. The crux of the matter will depend on how often we need to consult the pairwise comparison in a circumstance.
 
32
This point is noted by Liam Murphy, Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 67–70 when he says that we lack a criterion “for setting the right balance between demands and the amount of good to be done.” Confronting a situation like the present state of the world, we do not know what the “appropriate level of demands would be.”
 
33
In reality, many parents are not willing to impose extreme burdens on their children. They want their children to live their own lives too. However, in the present context, we are considering, at a critical level, what amount of sacrifice is reasonable for adult children to bear on behalf of their parents. The parents’ such psychological propensities may not fall within the scope of our investigation here.
 
34
There have been different ways to categorize the various explanations of filial obligations. Michael Collingridge and Seumas Miller, “Filial Responsibility and the Care of the Aged,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 14 (1997): 119–128 distinguish between “reciprocity model”, “needs-based model”, “friendship model,” and “conventionalist model”. Li Chenyang, “Shifting Perspectives: Filial Morality Revisited,” Philosophy East and West 47 (1997), 211–232 proposes the following way of categorizing explanations of filial obligations: “English’s Friendship Model”, “Belliotti’s Contribution to Self Principle”, “Narveson’s Prudent Investor Thesis”, “Sommers’ Conventional Expectation Thesis”, “Blustein’s Gratitude Theory” and “The Confucian Alternative.” Simon Keller, “Four Theories of Filial Duty,” The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 56 (223) (2006): 254–274 suggests “the debt theory,” “the gratitude theory,” “the friendship theory,” and his own “special goods theory.” Most recently, Anders Schinkel, “Filial Obligations: A Contextual, Pluralist Model,” The Journal of Ethics 16, (2012): 395–420 distinguishes the “past parental sacrifices model”, “the special relationship model,” and “the conventionalist model”. In this paper, I use Keller’s categories due to their simplicity and usefulness.
 
35
Christina Hoff Sommers, “Filial Morality” The Journal of Philosophy 83, (1986): 439–456; Stephen Post, “What Children Owe Parents: Ethics in an Aging Society” Thought Vol. 64 (255) (1989): 315–325; Ivanhoe, op. cit.
 
36
Fred R. Berger, “Gratitude” Ethics 85 (1975): 298–309; Nancy S. Jecker, “Are Filial Duties Unfounded?” American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (1989), pp. 73–80; Ivanhoe, op. cit.; Mark R. Wicclair, “Caring for Frail Elderly Parents: Past Parental Sacrifices and the Obligations of Adult Children,” Social Theory and Practice 16 (2) (1990): 163–189.
 
37
Jane English, “What Do Grown Children Owe Their Parents?” In Onora O’Neill and William Ruddick, op. cit., pp. 351–356; Jeffrey Blustein, Parents and Children: The Ethics of the Family (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982); Nicholas Dixon, “The Friendship Model of Filial Obligations,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 12 (1995), 77–87.
 
38
Keller, op. cit. and The Limits of Loyalty (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
 
39
Keller, op. cit., p. 273 states: “I think that it should at least be clear that when you are uniquely placed to provide someone with an important good, you have a moral reason to do so, at least in some sense and other things being equal.”
 
40
On the idea of “sacrifice,” a reviewer comments that “being a parent is part of a person’s identity, and the ‘sacrifices’ it entails are simply part of who one is and what one does, and are therefore as little to be described as ‘sacrifices’ as most other things one does in order to live a good life.” Scanlon, op. cit., p. 129 will agree with this view. Of course, even if a person can fully internalize the costs of a project, such as raising a child, into his life plan, it will not refute the fact that in an alternative course of life, had he not made the sacrifices for this child, the person could pursue his other goals and commitments with more resources and with more concentration than he can in his present life. Thus, the idea of “sacrifice” can be understood from the perspective of a whole-life comparison. On this point, see William Sin, “Internalization and Moral Demands,” Philosophical Studies 157 (2012): 163–175, pp. 171–173.
 
41
The debt theory may have presupposed a special sense of sacrifice. When parents bear sacrifices to bring up their children, they can be doing it willingly. Nonetheless it remains possible that the parents could have lived certain alternative lives with a richer amount of resource endowment if they decided not to bring up any children in those lives. We may understand the idea of sacrifice here by drawing reference to the whole-life conception of comparison (see footnote 40). For other interpretations of the debt theory, such as the Confucian one, see Cecilia Wee, “Filial Obligations: A Comparative Study,” Dao 13.1 (2014): 83–97 and Ivanhoe, op. cit.
 
42
It is possible that even if two parties are inclined to make a sacrifice on behalf of one another, this does not affect the objective existence of a certain principle of action which no one can reasonably reject. The fact that there is no practical need for each of the parties to enter into moral deliberation does not refute the claim that a nonrejectable principle between them may nevertheless exist. It is a further question whether an agent can engage in both kinds of thinking at the same time. But compare Bernard Williams’s remark that normative theories can sometimes be too “ambitious.” See his Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 17–19.
 
43
It is pertinent that Scanlon, op. cit., p. 172 has stated explicitly, in the context of a discussion of filial obligations, that “the contractualist view I am presenting does not account either for the content or the motivational basis of all that the term ‘morality,’ as it is used by many if not most people, is commonly taken to cover.”
 
Metadata
Title
Adult Children’s Obligations Towards Their Parents: A Contractualist Explanation
Author
William Sin
Publication date
08-05-2018
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
The Journal of Value Inquiry / Issue 1/2019
Print ISSN: 0022-5363
Electronic ISSN: 1573-0492
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-018-9634-0

Other articles of this Issue 1/2019

The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2019 Go to the issue