Skip to main content
Top

2018 | OriginalPaper | Chapter

Conventions of Unamendability: Covert Constitutional Unamendability in (Two) Politically Enforced Constitutions

Authors : Gert Jan Geertjes, Jerfi Uzman

Published in: An Unamendable Constitution?

Publisher: Springer International Publishing

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Legal scholarship on the unamendability of constitutional provisions tends to focus on legal systems with a strong tradition of judicial review of legislation. Legal systems such as the United Kingdom and The Netherlands, where the constitutionality of laws is a matter for the political branches and not for the courts, are routinely ignored. They do not fit existing perceptions of constitutional unamendability and arguably fall well outside the categories of either explicit or implicit constitutional unamendability. Nonetheless, these ‘politically enforced constitutions’ still contain mechanisms of unamendability, be it of an informal nature. These take the shape of judicial or institutional disobedience. The doctrine of unconstitutional constitutional amendments thus becomes relevant to a broader range of constitutional systems. However, this type of unamendability requires a more subtle approach. It does not emerge from constitutional provisions, whether explicit or not, but rather occurs in the form of a constitutional convention of unamendability. The question whether parts of the constitution should be regarded as unamendable thus cannot be solely couched in the all-or-nothing terminology of legal rules. Instead, conventions of unamendability, due to their principle-based character, may be subject to changing circumstances and exceptions. Existing literature on constitutional conventions may be used as a model in order to build a framework of analysis for the concept of constitutional unamendability in politically enforced constitutions.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
See art. 72–3 of the Swiss Constitution. More generally Peters (2009) and Green (2010), p. 619.
 
2
See articles 15 and 8, respectively, of the Swiss Constitution, and articles 9 en 14 of the ECHR.
 
3
For instance from Geert Wilders who, at the time lent vital support to the ruling coalition in The Netherlands. See Green (2010), p. 642.
 
4
Garlicki and Garlicka (2011), p. 343.
 
5
See s 112 of the Norwegian Constitution; Smith (2011), p. 369.
 
6
See generally Roznai (2013), pp. 657, 662.
 
7
Ibid., p. 665.
 
8
See e.g., Wright (1991), p. 741, O’Connell (1999), p. 48, Mazzone (2005), p. 1747, Jacobsohn (2006), p. 460, Gözler (2008), Albert (2009, 2010, p. 663), Barak (2011), p. 321, Bezemek (2011), p. 517, Cariás (2011), Roznai and Yolcu (2012), p. 175, Halmai (2012), p. 182, Roznai (2013), Colón-Ríos (2013), p. 521, (2014), p. 143) and Albert (2014a), p. 181.
 
9
Roznai (2013).
 
10
See the contributions of Roznai, Hoque, Olcay, Yegen and Masri.
 
11
See e.g., the ‘Three Musketeers’ of Indian constitutional litigation: the Supreme Court judgments in I.C. Golaknath & Ors v. State of Punjab, AIR 1967 SC 1643 (27 February 1967); Kesavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala, AIR 1973 SC 1461 (24 April 1973); Minerva Mills Ltd. v. Union of India, AIR 1980 SC 1789 (31 July 1980). For a compelling accounts, see the contribution to this volume by Satya Prateek; Jacobsohn (2006), p. 470, Albert (2014a), p. 22, and Halmai (2012), p. 186.
 
12
Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 [1996] ZACC 26, 1996 (4) SA 744 (6 September 1996). See Albert (2009), p. 26, and Halmai (2012), p. 190.
 
13
Compare e.g.: Constitutional Court of Turkey, E.2008/18, K.2008/116 (5 June 2008); Czech Constitutional Court, Pl. ÚS 27/09 (10 September 2009); Constitutional Court of Hungary, no. 61/2011 (VII. 13) (13 June 2011). For commentary, see: Özbudun (2009), p. 533, Roznai and Yolcu (2012), p. 175, Roznai (2014), p. 29, and Halmai (2012), p. 182. The Turkish example is particularly informative. See on that subject, the contributions in this volume by Tarık Olcay and Oya Yegen.
 
14
See Colón-Riós (2013), p. 521, (2014), p. 143, and Bernal (2013), p. 339.
 
15
See Otto (2007), p. 137.
 
16
Still worse: as we will see, the Dutch Constitution even prohibits the courts to engage in procedural review of the amendment. See article 120 of the Constitution and the Van den Bergh v. The State judgment of the Dutch Supreme Court, NJ 1963/248 (27 January 1961).
 
17
We took a leaf here from Voermans (2009), p. 84.
 
18
The term judicial deafness was used before, see e.g., Patterson (2007), pp. 279, 280.
 
19
Yaniv Roznai, ‘Necrocracy or Democracy? Assessing Objections to Formal Unamendability’; Stephan Michel and Ignacio Cofone, ‘Credible Commitment or Paternalism? The Case of Unamendability’; Konstantinos Pilpilidis, ‘A Constitution for Eternity: An Economic Theory of Explicit Unamendability’.
 
20
See e.g., Albert (2008), p. 37.
 
21
Voermans (2009), p. 86.
 
22
Albert (2009), p. 16.
 
23
Schwartzberg (2007), pp. 3–8.
 
24
At the time of finalizing this article, the European Communities Act 1972 is still in force in the UK legal order as a ‘constitutional’ statute, since the exit of the UK out of the EU has not yet taken place in a legal sense. The Act will only lose its constitutional status as soon as Parliament repeals it.
 
25
Compare the chapter of Yaniv Roznai, ‘Necrocracy or Democracy? Assessing Objections to Formal Unamendability’ (n 19), para 5A.
 
26
We use the recently proposed classification by Albert (2014a) 188–189.
 
27
See e.g., Garlicki and Garlicka (2011), p. 347.
 
28
See for two such examples in Canada and the US, Albert (2014a), p. 181.
 
29
See Schwartzberg (2007), p. 13.
 
30
Albert (2014a), p. 191.
 
31
van den Berg (2006), Andeweg and Irwin (2014), p. 167.
 
32
Albert (2014a), p. 191.
 
33
See articles 193(4) and 194(2) of the Swiss Federal Constitution.
 
34
See article 112(1) of the Norwegian Grundlov.
 
35
See Garlicki and Garlicka (2011).
 
36
Smith (2011), pp. 384–386.
 
37
As Eivind Smith has conveniently shown, the way in which the role of the monarchy in Norway has developed, is probably not in line with the spirit of the Constitution as perceived in 1814. None of the political actors (including the monarchy itself) raised the issue however. The most likely scenario is that the position of the King in Norwegian constitutional law, although initially clearly part of the ‘principles embodied by the Constitution’, has—by virtue of the changing political landscape—lost this status along the way of history. See Smith (2011).
 
38
See e.g., Barak (2011).
 
39
Take for instance the case of Bangladesh, where unamendability was a judicially declared norm until 2011, when an eternal clause was added to the Constitution. See the chapter of Ridwanul Hoque, ‘Eternal Provisions in the Constitution of Bangladesh: A Constitution Once and for All?’.
 
40
Kesavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala, AIR 1973 SC 1461 (24 April 1973). See also: I.C. Golaknath & Ors v. State of Punjab, AIR 1967 SC 1643 (27 February 1967); Indira Nehru Gandhi v. Raj Narain, AIR 1975 SC 2299 (19 December 1975); Minerva Mills Ltd. v. Union of India, AIR 1980 SC 1789 (31 July 1980).
 
41
Samanta and Basu (2008), pp. 499, 501.
 
42
See Roznai (2013).
 
43
Ibid., p. 698.
 
44
See on the weak/strong-form review axis: Tushnet (2006), pp. 1225, 1242. Recently in the context of amendment: Colón-Ríos (2014).
 
45
See e.g., Gözler (2008).
 
46
Barak (2011), p. 321.
 
47
Although he does not use this kind of terminology, Colón Ríos seems to depart from a similar line of reasoning. See Colón Ríos (2014).
 
48
Jacobsohn (2009), p. 82.
 
49
Roznai (2013), p. 661.
 
50
See e.g., Kavanagh (2009) and Uzman et al. (2011).
 
51
On this trend see e.g., Hirschl (2008), p. 93.
 
52
See on this distinction e.g., Tushnet (2006), p. 1242 and Colón-Ríos (2014), p. 143.
 
53
See e.g., in the Japanese context Matsui (2011), pp. 1375, 1413 and Albert (2015a), p. 655.
 
54
The concept may thus be antithetical to the idea of judicial supremacy as for instance defined by Whittington (2009), p. 7.
 
55
See e.g., Cooper v Aaron, 358 US 1 (12 September 1958); City of Boerne v Flores, 521 US 507 (25 June 1997); Tushnet (1998), p. 945.
 
56
See e.g., BverfGE 96, 260 (15 July 1997), para 12.
 
57
European Union law provides a possible exception in this regard: see the remarkable case of John Dalli, a European Commissioner who was forced to resign but challenged his resignation in the European Court of Justice. See Case T-562/12 (12 May 2015).
 
58
BverfGE 106, 310 (18 December 2002).
 
59
BverfGE 114, 121 (25 August 2005).
 
60
395 US 486 (16 June 1969).
 
61
Sandalow (1969) 164, 168.
 
62
See e.g., Albert (2014b), pp. 1029, 1073, drawing attention to Coleman v Miller, 307 US 433, 454 (1939), in which the Court suggested that disputes concerning Article V of the US Constitution are non-justiciable political questions.
 
63
Compare the so-called National Prohibition Cases, 253 US 350 (7 June 1920); Leser v Garnett, 258 US 130 (27 February 1922). See also Gözler (2008), pp. 79–80.
 
64
Albert (2015b).
 
65
Albert (2009), pp. 44–46, (2015b) fn 150.
 
66
Dicey (1959), pp. 3–4.
 
67
Ellen Street Estates Ltd v Minister of Health [1934] 1 KB 590 (25 January 1934).
 
68
Goldsworthy (1999), p. 243.
 
69
Ibid., p. 242–243.
 
70
If the sovereignty of Parliament should be qualified as a matter of law or as political fact is subject to debate. See Wade (1955), pp. 172, 189 and Goldsworthy (2010) 123–126.
 
71
Griffith (1979), p. 15.
 
72
Bellamy (2011), pp. 86, 92.
 
73
See also below, para 6.1.
 
74
Goldsworthy (1999), p. 266. See for a critique on his distinction on legal and extra-legal constraints on Parliament’s law-making power, Allan (2013), pp. 156–161.
 
75
X v Morgan-Grampian Publishers Ltd [1991] 1 AC 1 HL (4 April 1990) (Lord Bridge).
 
76
See: Allan (1985).
 
77
See Human Rights Act 1998, s 3.
 
78
Allan (2001).
 
79
See e.g., Anisminic v FCC [1969] 2 AC 147, HL (17 December 1968) (pre-HRA) and R v A [2001] UKHL 25, HL (17 May 2001) (under the HRA).
 
80
Allan (1993), p. 267.
 
81
See for a critique e.g., Goldsworthy (2008), pp. 277, 302.
 
82
See e.g., Barber (2011), p. 144 and Bogdanor (2009), pp. 271–290.
 
83
See e.g., Kavanagh (2009), pp. 305–307 and Elliott (2002), p. 340.
 
84
These global factors have been frequently described by Hirschl (2006), p. 721.
 
85
[2005] UKHL 56 (13 October 2005), para 104, 107.
 
86
See Young (2009), pp. 10–11.
 
87
This is what Aruna Sathanapally calls, the ‘dual review model’ of dialogue. Interestingly, Sathanapally argues that s. 4 of the HRA did not achieve the true ‘dual review’ version of dialogue. Sathanapally (2012), pp. 48, 224.
 
88
See e.g., Campbell (2001). Admittedly, a different view is quite as influential. See e.g., Feldman (2007).
 
89
Pickin v British Railways Board [1974] AC 765 HL (30 January 1974).
 
90
R (Jackson) v Attorney General (2005), para 27 (Lord Bingham). Another, more recent, instance of a case in which a UK court decided on a largely political matter may be R (Miller) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [2017] UKSC 5 (24 January 2017). In the Miller case, the UK Supreme Court ruled that the UK Government was not allowed to invoke the procedure for withdrawal from the European Union (the so-called Article 50 procedure) without an Act of Parliament allowing the Government to do so. This case could also be seen as a clear example of court interference with the political process. It could be argued that this was a non-justiciable issue, since Parliament itself could also have claimed decision authority on the UK’s withdrawal from the EU through political means.
 
91
One of the cornerstones of the constitution at large, the unwritten rule that the government depends parliamentary support is exemplary in this regard.
 
92
Uzman et al. (2011), p. 671.
 
93
Dicey (1959), pp. 39–40.
 
94
Uzman et al. (2011).
 
95
See the Court’s Harmonization Act Judgment, NJ 1989/469 (14 April 1989).
 
96
Van den Bergh v. The State 1963/248.
 
97
Tegelen v. Limburg, NJ 2000/160 (19 November 1999).
 
98
Waterpakt v. The State, NJ 2003/691 (21 March 2003) para 3.5; The State v. Clara Wichmann Foundation, NJ 2010/388 (9 April 2010) para 4.6.2.
 
99
See the proposal of Liberal MP Joost Taverne to limit the reviewing power of the courts to subordinate legislation (Parliamentary Papers II 2011/12, 33 359, nr 1–3).
 
100
See e.g., the European Court’s judgment in James & Ors v United Kingdom, [1986] ECHR 2, Series A no 98 (21 February 1986): ‘Article 13 does not go so far as to guarantee a remedy allowing a Contracting State’s laws as such to be challenged before a national authority on the ground of being contrary to the Convention’.
 
101
The phenomenon of judicial disobedience is not exclusive to politically enforced constitutions. It may apply also to ‘judicial supremacy systems’ too. See, in the context of the United States, for instance the Slaughter-house cases, 83 US 36 (14 April 1873), in which the Supreme Court arguably exacerbated the privileges and immunities clause of the 14th Amendment. Relatedly, the enactment of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act in 1993 could be seen as a reaction to Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective Association, 485 US 439 (19 April 1988) and Employment Division v. Smith, 494 US 872 (17 April 1990), in which the Supreme Court upheld legislation that prohibited activities which were religiously prescribed.
 
102
See e.g., Elliott (2001), p. 197.
 
103
Feldman (2002), pp. 70–74.
 
104
Ewing and Gearty (1990), p. 255.
 
105
See e.g., R. v. Home Secretary Ex p Brind [1991] 1 AC 696 (HL).
 
106
Besson (2008), p. 40.
 
107
See e.g., Laws (1995), p. 72 and Feldman (2009), p. 544.
 
108
See Elliott (2001), p. 233 and Kavanagh (2004), p. 259, Kavanagh (2009), pp. 144–164.
 
109
See e.g., Hoffmann (2009).
 
110
See e.g., Fredman (2013), p. 292.
 
111
Arnot (2009).
 
112
Palmer (2009).
 
113
See Bates (2015).
 
114
See e.g., Elliott (2013), p. 137.
 
115
See e.g., Elliott (2015), p. 1.
 
116
Porter and Hirsch (2010). More recently: ‘The question is, can we go back? Can we tear up the Human Rights Convention and go back? …I don’t think we can’, Lord Phillips of Worth Matravers in a panel discussion at King’s College London, 24 March 2015, report at <http://​ukhumanrightsblo​g.​com/​2015/​05/​15/​we-cannot-go-back-debating-the-human-rights-act-eva-pils/​#more-25964> accessed on 14 July 2017.
 
117
Elliott (2015).
 
118
Ibid.
 
119
See: Osborn v. Parole Board [2013] UKSC 61, [2014] AC 1115; Kennedy v. Charity Commission [2014] UKSC 20, [2014] 2 WLR 808; R (Evans) v. Attorney General [2015] UKSC 21.
 
120
UKSC 20, [2014] 2 WLR 808, para 46.
 
121
Hale (2014).
 
122
Elliott (2014).
 
123
See his recent remarks at a conference at King’s College London (24 March 2015).
 
124
European law, both in the framework of the EU and the Council of Europe, might pose some obstacles, but they do not concern us here.
 
125
See Elliott (2015).
 
126
Meerenberg, W 4330 (13 January 1879).
 
127
This follows from the current Article 89(1) and (2) of the Constitution of the Netherlands, which stipulates: ‘Orders in council shall be established by Royal Decree.’ A Royal Decree is a decree of the government.
 
128
Fluoridering, NJ 1973/386 (22 June 1973).
 
129
Methadonbrief, NJ 1987/898 (27 June 1986).
 
130
Ibid. para 3.3.
 
131
Parliamentary Proceeding of the Second Chamber (Kamerstukken II) 1977/78, 15 047 (R 1099), nr 3, 15.
 
132
However, some authors still believe that the government may, and perhaps should, make more use of the competence to autonomously issue Orders-in-Council. See, notably, Donner (2013).
 
133
Albert (2014a).
 
134
Goldsworthy (1999), pp. 302–303.
 
135
Dicey (1959), p. 24.
 
136
Jennings (1959), p. 136.
 
137
Ibid.
 
138
Jaconelli (2005), pp. 149, 168–176.
 
139
One precedent may however be enough to constitute a convention, see Jennings (1959), p. 136.
 
140
Compare the distinction between ‘positive’ and ‘critical morality’. Those who advance the positive morality view consider conventions as a description of the applicable moral values in the arena of politics, whereas those who promote the critical morality argue that a more critical stance is needed. Only the conventions which ought to be considered as binding should be properly termed so. See Marshall (1986).
 
141
Marshall (1986), p. 7.
 
142
Stephen (1882), p. 137 and Dicey (1959), p. 81.
 
143
Morton (199192), p. 114, 157–158. See also Feldman (2005), pp. 329, 334, (2011), pp. 117, 123.
 
144
Morton (199192), pp. 165–166.
 
145
Ibid., p. 165.
 
146
This is particularly peculiar to political constitutions, see Griffith (1979), p. 20.
 
147
Dicey (1959) 422–423.
 
148
Morton (199192), p. 171.
 
149
Ibid., p. 169.
 
150
Ibid., pp. 173–174.
 
151
Ibid., p. 142.
 
152
The definition of principle here is drawn from Dworkin (1977), 22–28.
 
153
Jaconelli (2005), p. 176. See also Jaconelli (2015).
 
154
Allan (2013), p. 65.
 
155
Munro (1975).
 
156
Feldman (2013).
 
157
Jaconelli (2005), p. 167.
 
158
Feldman (2005).
 
Literature
go back to reference Albert R (2008) Counterconstitutionalism. Dalhousie Law J 31:37 Albert R (2008) Counterconstitutionalism. Dalhousie Law J 31:37
go back to reference Albert R (2009) Nonconstitutional amendments. Can J Law Jurisprud 22:5 Albert R (2009) Nonconstitutional amendments. Can J Law Jurisprud 22:5
go back to reference Albert R (2010) Constitutional handcuffs. Arizona State Law J 43:663 Albert R (2010) Constitutional handcuffs. Arizona State Law J 43:663
go back to reference Albert R (2014a) Constructive unamendability in Canada and the United States. Supreme Court Law Rev 67:181 Albert R (2014a) Constructive unamendability in Canada and the United States. Supreme Court Law Rev 67:181
go back to reference Albert R (2014b) Constitutional disuse or desuetude: the case of article V. Boston U Law Rev 94:1029, 1073 Albert R (2014b) Constitutional disuse or desuetude: the case of article V. Boston U Law Rev 94:1029, 1073
go back to reference Albert R (2015a) Amending constitutional amendment rules. Int J Const Law 3:655 Albert R (2015a) Amending constitutional amendment rules. Int J Const Law 3:655
go back to reference Albert R (2015b) The unamendable core of the United States constitution. In: Koltay A (ed) Comparative perspectives on the fundamental freedom of expression. Wolters Kluwer Albert R (2015b) The unamendable core of the United States constitution. In: Koltay A (ed) Comparative perspectives on the fundamental freedom of expression. Wolters Kluwer
go back to reference Allan TRS (1985) Legislative supremacy and the rule of law: democracy and constitutionalism. CLJ 44:111 Allan TRS (1985) Legislative supremacy and the rule of law: democracy and constitutionalism. CLJ 44:111
go back to reference Allan TRS (1993) Law, liberty and justice: The legal foundations of British constitutionalism. OUP, p 267 Allan TRS (1993) Law, liberty and justice: The legal foundations of British constitutionalism. OUP, p 267
go back to reference Allan TRS (2001) Constitutional justice: a liberal theory of justice. OUP Allan TRS (2001) Constitutional justice: a liberal theory of justice. OUP
go back to reference Allan TRS (2013) The Sovereignty of law: freedom, constitution and common law. OUP, pp 156–161 Allan TRS (2013) The Sovereignty of law: freedom, constitution and common law. OUP, pp 156–161
go back to reference Andeweg RB, Irwin GA (2014) Governance and politics of the Netherlands. Palgrave Macmillan, p 167 Andeweg RB, Irwin GA (2014) Governance and politics of the Netherlands. Palgrave Macmillan, p 167
go back to reference Barak A (2011) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments. Israel Law Rev 44:321 Barak A (2011) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments. Israel Law Rev 44:321
go back to reference Barber NW (2011) The afterlife of parliamentary Sovereignty. Int J Const Law 9:144 Barber NW (2011) The afterlife of parliamentary Sovereignty. Int J Const Law 9:144
go back to reference Bates E (2015) The UK and Strasbourg: a strained relationship—the long view. In: Ziegler KS, Wicks E, Hodson L (eds) The UK and European human rights: a strained relationship? Hart Bates E (2015) The UK and Strasbourg: a strained relationship—the long view. In: Ziegler KS, Wicks E, Hodson L (eds) The UK and European human rights: a strained relationship? Hart
go back to reference Bellamy R (2011) Political constitutionalism and the human rights act. Int J Const Law 9:86, 92 Bellamy R (2011) Political constitutionalism and the human rights act. Int J Const Law 9:86, 92
go back to reference Bernal C (2013) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments in the case study of Colombia: an analysis of the justification and meaning of the constitutional replacement doctrine. Int J Const Law 11:339 Bernal C (2013) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments in the case study of Colombia: an analysis of the justification and meaning of the constitutional replacement doctrine. Int J Const Law 11:339
go back to reference Besson S (2008) The reception process in Ireland and the United Kingdom. In: Keller H, Stone-Sweet A (eds) A Europe of rights: the impact of the ECHR on national legal systems. OUP, p 40 Besson S (2008) The reception process in Ireland and the United Kingdom. In: Keller H, Stone-Sweet A (eds) A Europe of rights: the impact of the ECHR on national legal systems. OUP, p 40
go back to reference Bezemek C (2011) Constitutional core(s): amendments, entrenchments, eternities and beyond—Prolegomena to a theory of normative volatility. J Jurisprud 11:517 Bezemek C (2011) Constitutional core(s): amendments, entrenchments, eternities and beyond—Prolegomena to a theory of normative volatility. J Jurisprud 11:517
go back to reference Bogdanor V (2009) The New British constitution. Hart, pp 271–290 Bogdanor V (2009) The New British constitution. Hart, pp 271–290
go back to reference Campbell T (2001) Incorporation through interpretation. In Campbell T, Ewing K, Tomkins A (eds) Sceptical essays on human rights. OUP Campbell T (2001) Incorporation through interpretation. In Campbell T, Ewing K, Tomkins A (eds) Sceptical essays on human rights. OUP
go back to reference Cariás AB (2011) Constitutional courts as positive legislators: a comparative law study. CUP, Chapter 2 Cariás AB (2011) Constitutional courts as positive legislators: a comparative law study. CUP, Chapter 2
go back to reference Colón-Ríos J (2013) Beyond parliamentary sovereignty and judicial supremacy: the doctrine of implicit limits to constitutional reform in Latin America. Victoria U Wellington Law Rev 44:521 Colón-Ríos J (2013) Beyond parliamentary sovereignty and judicial supremacy: the doctrine of implicit limits to constitutional reform in Latin America. Victoria U Wellington Law Rev 44:521
go back to reference Colón-Ríos J (2014) A new typology of judicial review of legislation. Glob Constitutionalism 3:143 Colón-Ríos J (2014) A new typology of judicial review of legislation. Glob Constitutionalism 3:143
go back to reference Dicey AV (1959) Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution. Macmillan, pp 3–4 Dicey AV (1959) Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution. Macmillan, pp 3–4
go back to reference Donner JPH (2013) The principle of legality revisited. In van Roosmalen M et al (eds) Fundamental rights and principles. Intersentia Donner JPH (2013) The principle of legality revisited. In van Roosmalen M et al (eds) Fundamental rights and principles. Intersentia
go back to reference Dworkin R (1977) Taking rights seriously. Duckworth, pp 22–28 Dworkin R (1977) Taking rights seriously. Duckworth, pp 22–28
go back to reference Elliott M (2001) The constitutional foundations of judicial review. Hart, p 197 Elliott M (2001) The constitutional foundations of judicial review. Hart, p 197
go back to reference Elliott M (2002) Parliamentary Sovereignty and the new constitutional order: legislative freedom, political reality and convention. LS 22:340 Elliott M (2002) Parliamentary Sovereignty and the new constitutional order: legislative freedom, political reality and convention. LS 22:340
go back to reference Elliott M (2013) A Damp Squib in the long grass: the report of the commission on a bill of rights. Europ Human Rights Law Rev 137 Elliott M (2013) A Damp Squib in the long grass: the report of the commission on a bill of rights. Europ Human Rights Law Rev 137
go back to reference Elliott M (2015) Beyond the European convention: human rights and the common law. CLP 68:1 Elliott M (2015) Beyond the European convention: human rights and the common law. CLP 68:1
go back to reference Ewing KD, Gearty CA (1990) Freedom under thatcher: civil liberties in modern Britain. OUP, p 255 Ewing KD, Gearty CA (1990) Freedom under thatcher: civil liberties in modern Britain. OUP, p 255
go back to reference Feldman D (2002) Civil liberties and human rights in England and Wales, 2nd ed. OUP, pp 70–74 Feldman D (2002) Civil liberties and human rights in England and Wales, 2nd ed. OUP, pp 70–74
go back to reference Feldman D (2005) None, one or several? Perspectives on the UK’s constitution. CLJ 64:329, 334 Feldman D (2005) None, one or several? Perspectives on the UK’s constitution. CLJ 64:329, 334
go back to reference Feldman D (2007) Institutional roles and meanings of compatibility under the human rights act 1998. In: Fenwick H, Masterman R, Phillipson G (eds) Judicial reasoning under the human rights act. CUP Feldman D (2007) Institutional roles and meanings of compatibility under the human rights act 1998. In: Fenwick H, Masterman R, Phillipson G (eds) Judicial reasoning under the human rights act. CUP
go back to reference Feldman D (2009) Human rights. In: Blom-Cooper L, Dickson B, Drewry G (eds) The judicial house of lords 1876–2009. OUP, p 544 Feldman D (2009) Human rights. In: Blom-Cooper L, Dickson B, Drewry G (eds) The judicial house of lords 1876–2009. OUP, p 544
go back to reference Feldman D (2011) Which in you case you have not got: constitutionalism at home and abroad. CLP 64:117, 123 Feldman D (2011) Which in you case you have not got: constitutionalism at home and abroad. CLP 64:117, 123
go back to reference Feldman D (2013) Constitutional conventions. In: Qvortrup M (ed) The British constitution: continuity and change. A Festschrift for Vernon Bogdanor. Hart, p 106 Feldman D (2013) Constitutional conventions. In: Qvortrup M (ed) The British constitution: continuity and change. A Festschrift for Vernon Bogdanor. Hart, p 106
go back to reference Fredman S (2013) From dialogue to deliberation: human rights adjudication and prisoners’ rights to vote. PL 292 Fredman S (2013) From dialogue to deliberation: human rights adjudication and prisoners’ rights to vote. PL 292
go back to reference Garlicki L, Garlicka Z (2011) External review of constitutional amendments? International law as norm of reference. Israel Law Rev 44:343, 343 Garlicki L, Garlicka Z (2011) External review of constitutional amendments? International law as norm of reference. Israel Law Rev 44:343, 343
go back to reference Goldsworthy J (1999) The Sovereignty of Parliament: history and philosophy. OUP, p 243 Goldsworthy J (1999) The Sovereignty of Parliament: history and philosophy. OUP, p 243
go back to reference Goldsworthy J (2008) Unwritten constitutional principles. In: Huscroft G (ed) Expounding the constitution: essays in constitutional theory. CUP, pp 277, 302 Goldsworthy J (2008) Unwritten constitutional principles. In: Huscroft G (ed) Expounding the constitution: essays in constitutional theory. CUP, pp 277, 302
go back to reference Goldsworthy J (2010) Parliamentary Sovereignty: contemporary debates. CUP, pp 123–126 Goldsworthy J (2010) Parliamentary Sovereignty: contemporary debates. CUP, pp 123–126
go back to reference Gözler K (2008) Judicial review of constitutional amendments. Ekin Press Gözler K (2008) Judicial review of constitutional amendments. Ekin Press
go back to reference Green T (2010) The resistance to minarets in Europe. J Church State 52:619 Green T (2010) The resistance to minarets in Europe. J Church State 52:619
go back to reference Griffith JAG (1979) The political constitution. MLR 42:15 Griffith JAG (1979) The political constitution. MLR 42:15
go back to reference Halmai G (2012) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments: constitutional courts as guardians of the constitution? Constellations 19:182 Halmai G (2012) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments: constitutional courts as guardians of the constitution? Constellations 19:182
go back to reference Hirschl R (2006) The new constitution and the judicialization of pure politics worldwide. Fordham Law Rev 75:721 Hirschl R (2006) The new constitution and the judicialization of pure politics worldwide. Fordham Law Rev 75:721
go back to reference Hirschl R (2008) The judicialization of mega-politics and the rise of political courts. Annu Rev Political Sci 11:93 Hirschl R (2008) The judicialization of mega-politics and the rise of political courts. Annu Rev Political Sci 11:93
go back to reference Jacobsohn G (2006) An unconstitutional constitution? A comparative perspective? Int J Const Law 4:460 Jacobsohn G (2006) An unconstitutional constitution? A comparative perspective? Int J Const Law 4:460
go back to reference Jacobsohn G (2009) Constitutional identity. Harvard University Press, p 82 Jacobsohn G (2009) Constitutional identity. Harvard University Press, p 82
go back to reference Jaconelli J (2005) Do constitutional conventions bind? CLJ 64:149, 168–176 Jaconelli J (2005) Do constitutional conventions bind? CLJ 64:149, 168–176
go back to reference Jaconelli J (2015) The proper role for constitutional conventions. DULJ 38:363, 368 Jaconelli J (2015) The proper role for constitutional conventions. DULJ 38:363, 368
go back to reference Jennings SI (1959) The law and the constitution, 3rd ed. London University Press, p 136 Jennings SI (1959) The law and the constitution, 3rd ed. London University Press, p 136
go back to reference Kavanagh A (2004) The elusive divide between interpretation and legislation under the human rights act 1998. OJLS 24:259 Kavanagh A (2004) The elusive divide between interpretation and legislation under the human rights act 1998. OJLS 24:259
go back to reference Kavanagh A (2009) Constitutional review under the human rights act. CUP, UK Kavanagh A (2009) Constitutional review under the human rights act. CUP, UK
go back to reference Marshall G (1986) Constitutional conventions: the rules and forms of political accountability. Clarendon Press, pp 10–12 Marshall G (1986) Constitutional conventions: the rules and forms of political accountability. Clarendon Press, pp 10–12
go back to reference Matsui S (2011) Why is the Japanese supreme court so conservative? Washington U Law Rev 88:1375, 1413 Matsui S (2011) Why is the Japanese supreme court so conservative? Washington U Law Rev 88:1375, 1413
go back to reference Mazzone J (2005) Unamendments. Iowa Law Rev 90:1747 Mazzone J (2005) Unamendments. Iowa Law Rev 90:1747
go back to reference Morton PA (1991–92) Conventions of the British constitution. Holdsworth Law Rev 15:114, 157–158 Morton PA (1991–92) Conventions of the British constitution. Holdsworth Law Rev 15:114, 157–158
go back to reference Munro CR (1975) Laws and conventions distinguished. LQR 91:218, 222 Munro CR (1975) Laws and conventions distinguished. LQR 91:218, 222
go back to reference O’Connell R (1999) Guardians of the constitution: unconstitutional constitutional norms. J Civ Liberties 4:48 O’Connell R (1999) Guardians of the constitution: unconstitutional constitutional norms. J Civ Liberties 4:48
go back to reference Otto JM (2007) The compatibility of Sharia with the rule of law. Fundamental conflict: between civilisations? Within civilisations? Or between scholars?. In: Groen A et al (eds) Knowledge in ferment: dilemmas in science, scholarship and society. Leiden University Press, p 137 Otto JM (2007) The compatibility of Sharia with the rule of law. Fundamental conflict: between civilisations? Within civilisations? Or between scholars?. In: Groen A et al (eds) Knowledge in ferment: dilemmas in science, scholarship and society. Leiden University Press, p 137
go back to reference Özbudun E (2009) Judicial review of constitutional amendments in Turkey. Europ Publ Law 15:533 Özbudun E (2009) Judicial review of constitutional amendments in Turkey. Europ Publ Law 15:533
go back to reference Patterson M (2007) Surely you didn’t mean no jurisdiction: why the supreme court’s selective hearing in Hamdan is good for democracy. Harvard Law Policy Rev 1:279, 280 Patterson M (2007) Surely you didn’t mean no jurisdiction: why the supreme court’s selective hearing in Hamdan is good for democracy. Harvard Law Policy Rev 1:279, 280
go back to reference Roznai Y (2013) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments: the migration and success of a constitutional idea. Am J Comp Law 61:657, 662 Roznai Y (2013) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments: the migration and success of a constitutional idea. Am J Comp Law 61:657, 662
go back to reference Roznai Y (2014) Legisprudence limitations on constitutional amendments? Reflections on the Czech constitutional court’s declaration of unconstitutional constitutional act. ICL J 8:8 29 Roznai Y (2014) Legisprudence limitations on constitutional amendments? Reflections on the Czech constitutional court’s declaration of unconstitutional constitutional act. ICL J 8:8 29
go back to reference Roznai Y, Yolcu S (2012) An unconstitutional constitutional amendment—The Turkish perspective: a comment on the Turkish constitutional court’s headscarf decision. Int J Const Law 10:175 Roznai Y, Yolcu S (2012) An unconstitutional constitutional amendment—The Turkish perspective: a comment on the Turkish constitutional court’s headscarf decision. Int J Const Law 10:175
go back to reference Samanta N, Basu S (2008) Test of basic structure: an analysis. NUJS Law Rev 1:499, 501 Samanta N, Basu S (2008) Test of basic structure: an analysis. NUJS Law Rev 1:499, 501
go back to reference Sandalow T (1969) Comment on Powell v MacCormack. UCLA Law Rev 17:164, 168 Sandalow T (1969) Comment on Powell v MacCormack. UCLA Law Rev 17:164, 168
go back to reference Sathanapally A (2012) Beyond disagreement. Open remedies in human rights adjudication. OUP, pp 48, 224 Sathanapally A (2012) Beyond disagreement. Open remedies in human rights adjudication. OUP, pp 48, 224
go back to reference Schwartzberg M (2007) Democracy and legal change. CUP, pp 3–8 Schwartzberg M (2007) Democracy and legal change. CUP, pp 3–8
go back to reference Smith E (2011) Old and protected? On the “supra-constitutional” clause in the constitution of Norway. Israel L Rev 44:369 Smith E (2011) Old and protected? On the “supra-constitutional” clause in the constitution of Norway. Israel L Rev 44:369
go back to reference Stephen L (1882) The science of ethics. Elder and Co, Smith, p 137 Stephen L (1882) The science of ethics. Elder and Co, Smith, p 137
go back to reference Tushnet M (1998) Two versions of judicial supremacy. William Mary Law Rev 39:945 Tushnet M (1998) Two versions of judicial supremacy. William Mary Law Rev 39:945
go back to reference Tushnet M (2006) Comparative constitutional law. In: Reimann M, Zimmermann R (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative law. OUP, pp 1225, 1242 Tushnet M (2006) Comparative constitutional law. In: Reimann M, Zimmermann R (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative law. OUP, pp 1225, 1242
go back to reference Uzman J, Barkhuysen T, van Emmerik ML (2011) The Dutch supreme court: a reluctant positive legislator? In Brewer-Carias AR (ed) Constitutional courts as positive legislators. CUP, the Netherlands Uzman J, Barkhuysen T, van Emmerik ML (2011) The Dutch supreme court: a reluctant positive legislator? In Brewer-Carias AR (ed) Constitutional courts as positive legislators. CUP, the Netherlands
go back to reference van den Berg JTJ (2006) De Eerste Kamer, of de zin van rivaliteit. Leiden University Press van den Berg JTJ (2006) De Eerste Kamer, of de zin van rivaliteit. Leiden University Press
go back to reference Voermans W (2009) Constitutional reserves and covert constitutions. Indian J Const Law 3:84 Voermans W (2009) Constitutional reserves and covert constitutions. Indian J Const Law 3:84
go back to reference Wade HWR (1955) The basis of legal Sovereignty. CLJ 13:172, 189 Wade HWR (1955) The basis of legal Sovereignty. CLJ 13:172, 189
go back to reference Whittington KH (2009) The political foundations of judicial supremacy. Princeton University Press, p 7 Whittington KH (2009) The political foundations of judicial supremacy. Princeton University Press, p 7
go back to reference Wright G (1991) Could a constitutional amendment be unconstitutional? Loyola Univ Law J 22:741 Wright G (1991) Could a constitutional amendment be unconstitutional? Loyola Univ Law J 22:741
go back to reference Young A (2009) Parliamentary Sovereignty and the human rights act. Hart, pp 10–11 Young A (2009) Parliamentary Sovereignty and the human rights act. Hart, pp 10–11
Metadata
Title
Conventions of Unamendability: Covert Constitutional Unamendability in (Two) Politically Enforced Constitutions
Authors
Gert Jan Geertjes
Jerfi Uzman
Copyright Year
2018
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95141-6_4