Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Journal of Business Ethics 4/2019

02-05-2018 | Original Paper

Decomposing Legal Personhood

Author: Jon Garthoff

Published in: Journal of Business Ethics | Issue 4/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

The claim that corporations are not people is perhaps the most frequently voiced criticism of the United States Supreme Court decision Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission. There is something obviously correct about this claim. While the nature and extent of obligations with respect to group agents like corporations and labor unions is far from clear, it is manifest in moral understanding and deeply embedded in legal practice that there is no general requirement to treat them like natural persons. Group agents may be denied rights to marry, vote, or run for public office. More generally the need to guard against discrimination, the core injustice in racism and sexism, has no direct application to the case of group agents. There is also something obviously incorrect about the claim that corporations are not people. The legal practice of treating some group agents as persons under law is ancient, found already in Roman law at the time of Justinian. In this essay I propose that reflection on this tension reveals that fundamental revision to the doctrine of legal personhood is needed. More specifically I propose that legal personhood be decomposed into at least two elements—standing and liability—and that legal systems reject the principle that an entity possesses one just in case it possesses the other. The import of this change ramifies broadly. Decomposing legal personhood not only enables a satisfactory account of the status of corporations and labor unions, who as such have liability but not standing, it also enables a satisfactory account of the status of those who as such have standing but not liability: severely mentally disabled persons, very young children (including fetuses), and non-human animals with phenomenal consciousness but lacking capacities to understand reasons and justifications.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
558 U.S. 310 (2010).
 
2
In some jurisdictions in Australia certain group agents have the right to vote in local elections, but this is highly unusual. Though the view I articulate and defend in this essay does not strictly rule out voting rights for group agents in principle, I doubt it would support such rights in ordinary circumstances.
 
3
Two cases of significance in the establishment of legal personhood for limited liability corporations were Trustees of Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 17 U.S. 518 (1819), and Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railroad, 118 U.S. 394 (1886).
 
4
494 U.S. 652 (1990).
 
5
I here use the term “personhood,” which is more frequently used by philosophers of law, rather than the term “personality,” which is more frequently used in the law itself (hence also more frequently used in law schools). I make no distinction between legal personhood and legal personality.
 
6
It is not only legal personhood which needs to be decomposed; analogous revision is needed to the idea of moral personhood. For further development of this claim see Garthoff (2010; Animal punishment, unpublished).
 
7
The idea of society more generally as a reciprocal and cooperative vehicle of mutual advantage, which has roots in the political theory of Hume (1739), has more recently been given rich development by Rawls (1971, 2001).
 
8
It is likely that the most psychologically sophisticated non-human terrestrial animals—I have in mind apes and elephants—lack the capacities constituting critical reason. It is more speculative to rule out all whales and dolphins as critically rational, but there is no strong evidence that they are. For defense of the view that only humans are critically rational see Burge (1999).
 
9
For a summary of empirical work on animal cognition, see Marc Hauser (2000).
 
10
See Garthoff (Animal punishment, unpublished).
 
11
For support for this claim see Burge (2010), including especially p 104, pp 431–433, and pp 537–544.
 
12
See Garthoff (Animal punishment, unpublished).
 
13
This claim is famously found in the introduction to Bentham (1781) and in Singer (1974). The claim itself does not, however, entail anything like consequentialism.
 
14
Francione (2008) also endorses sentience as the criterion of moral and legal standing (hence also as the criterion of rights-possession), but he resists decomposing moral and legal personhood by claiming all sentient non-human animals are persons in the same sense as fully developed adult human beings. This view is not defended well by Francione, and garners little support from common sense or moral reflection.
 
15
The phenomenon of group agency is sometimes labeled instead as “shared agency”; I make no distinction here between those terms. Also, as packs of wolves and herds of elephants illustrate, not all group agents are persons. I restrict my discussion to groups of persons, however, since only these groups have obligations.
 
16
In recent years there has been an explosion of interest, among philosophers, in the phenomenon of group agency. There are too many significant relevant works to enumerate here, but much credit for sparking this interest belongs to Gilbert (1989, 1990) and Bratman (1992, 1993).
 
17
This claim is also defended from within a different theoretical framework in Chap. 7 of List and Pettit (2011).
 
18
The existence of strict liability in the law also underscores the distinction here, since it is plausible that there is no strict liability within morality as such.
 
19
See Garthoff (2004a, b).
 
20
424 U.S. 1 (1976).
 
21
For the same reason I do not discuss McCutcheon v. Federal Election Commission [283 U.S. 514 (2014)] in this essay, even though it is a crucial element of recent United States campaign finance jurisprudence.
 
22
443 U.S. 622 (1978).
 
23
479 U.S. 238 (1986).
 
24
494 U.S. 652 (1990).
 
25
540 U.S. 93 (2003).
 
26
558 U.S. 310 (2010).
 
27
See Rawls (2001), pp 148–150; see also Daniels (1975) and Cohen (1989). This is sufficient ground, independent from issues to do with artificial personhood, to reject major elements of Buckley.
 
28
In my view this supports not only civil, but also criminal, liability for corporations and labor unions. I do not explore that issue in this essay.
 
29
It is unclear exactly what Justice Stevens holds regarding this issue, since his dissent in Citizens United alternates between arguments that appear to deny this claim and arguments that appear to endorse it.
 
30
The majority opinion in Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores Inc., 573 U.S.__(2014), extends the rights of religious expression and thought to certain artificial persons. This conclusion is not plausibly reached from within the framework articulated in this essay, for it is highly doubtful that such rights could be grounded solely in respect and concern for natural persons and sentient animals.
 
Literature
go back to reference Bentham, J. (1781). The principles of morals and legislation. Buffalo: Prometheus Books. Bentham, J. (1781). The principles of morals and legislation. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.
go back to reference Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperative activity. The Philosophical Review, 101, 327–341.CrossRef Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperative activity. The Philosophical Review, 101, 327–341.CrossRef
go back to reference Burge, T. (1999). A century of deflation and a moment about self-knowledge. In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 73, 25–46. Burge, T. (1999). A century of deflation and a moment about self-knowledge. In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 73, 25–46.
go back to reference Cohen, J. (1989). Deliberation and democratic legitimacy. In A. Hamlin, & P. Pettit (Eds.), The good polity. Hoboken: Blackwell Publishing. Cohen, J. (1989). Deliberation and democratic legitimacy. In A. Hamlin, & P. Pettit (Eds.), The good polity. Hoboken: Blackwell Publishing.
go back to reference Daniels, N. (1975). Equal liberty and unequal worth of liberty. In N. Daniels (Ed.), Reading rawls. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press. Daniels, N. (1975). Equal liberty and unequal worth of liberty. In N. Daniels (Ed.), Reading rawls. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.
go back to reference Francione, G. (2008). Animals as persons. New York: Columbia University Press. Francione, G. (2008). Animals as persons. New York: Columbia University Press.
go back to reference Garthoff, J. (2004b). The embodiment thesis. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 7(1), 15–29.CrossRef Garthoff, J. (2004b). The embodiment thesis. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 7(1), 15–29.CrossRef
go back to reference Garthoff, J. (2010). Meriting concern and meriting respect. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 5, 1–28.CrossRef Garthoff, J. (2010). Meriting concern and meriting respect. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 5, 1–28.CrossRef
go back to reference Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. London: Routledge Publishing. Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. London: Routledge Publishing.
go back to reference Gilbert, M. (1990). Walking together: A paradigmatic social phenomenon. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15, 1–14.CrossRef Gilbert, M. (1990). Walking together: A paradigmatic social phenomenon. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15, 1–14.CrossRef
go back to reference Hauser, M. (2000). Wild minds. New York: Henry Holt. Hauser, M. (2000). Wild minds. New York: Henry Holt.
go back to reference Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature. New York: Penguin Books. Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature. New York: Penguin Books.
go back to reference List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Singer, P. (1974). All animals are equal. Philosophic Exchange, 1, 215–228. Singer, P. (1974). All animals are equal. Philosophic Exchange, 1, 215–228.
Metadata
Title
Decomposing Legal Personhood
Author
Jon Garthoff
Publication date
02-05-2018
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Journal of Business Ethics / Issue 4/2019
Print ISSN: 0167-4544
Electronic ISSN: 1573-0697
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-018-3888-0

Other articles of this Issue 4/2019

Journal of Business Ethics 4/2019 Go to the issue

Original Paper

Kantian Group Agency