Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Journal of Business Ethics 4/2019

02-05-2018 | Original Paper

Individual Actions and Corporate Moral Responsibility: A (Reconstituted) Kantian Approach

Author: Tobey Scharding

Published in: Journal of Business Ethics | Issue 4/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper examines the resources of Kantian ethics to establish corporate moral responsibility. I defend Matthew Altman’s claim that Kantian ethics cannot hold corporations morally responsible for corporate malfeasance. Rather than following Altman in interpreting this inability as a reason not to use Kantian ethics, however, I argue that the Kantian framework is correct: business ethicists should not seek to hold corporations morally responsible. Instead, they should use Kantian (and/or other ethical-theoretical) resources to criticize the actions of individual businesspeople. I set forth a model for decomposing business actions into their individual parts and reconstituting them in a context-specific “maxim” that Kantian ethics can evaluate. The reconstituted form of Kantian ethics that I defend is better able to manage decision-making complexity than traditional interpretations. To demonstrate the usefulness of my approach, I apply it to the recent Wells Fargo bogus-accounts scandal.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
The first three claims come from Reckard (2013, pp. 2–3); the last owes to Glazer et al. (2016, p. 2).
 
2
Bowie endorses Korsgaard’s claims that the greatest wrongs from a Kantian perspective are fraud and exploitation (or, to use their terms, “deception” and “coercion”) (1999, p. 48).
 
3
For a helpful discussion of cases like this, see Sinnott-Armstrong (2005).
 
4
For an excellent defense of the alternative view (that a person-centered view of moral responsibility can be extended to corporations), see Goodpaster and Matthews (1982, p. 3).
 
5
Altman names Korsgaard, Wood, and Harman as important sources of his interpretation (2014, vi).
 
6
The two other important strategies are the “respect for persons” and “ethical community” approaches. For a discussion of these approaches, see Bowie (1999, pp. 41–81 and 82–119).
 
7
Cf. Henry Allison’s “Incorporation Thesis” (Allison 1990, pp. 5–6). For an insightful (critical) discussion of this viewpoint, see Wood (2003).
 
8
Altman and I have the same conclusion here—Kantian ethics lacks resources to hold corporations morally responsible—but our arguments differ. Altman argues that corporations are not capable of moral responsibility because they lack inclinations and the ability to use reason. I believe that there is good ground to claim that corporations do experience at least one kind of inclination: to maximize profits. As grounds for this claim, I offer that profit maximization is the goal that corporations are created to pursue. Because of possible weaknesses in Altman’s support for his claim, I have decided to provide an alternative argument.
 
9
In theory, if every member of a corporation could agree to a maxim and endorse it from their own perspectives, it might be possible to have a corporate maxim, as discussed in Rönnegard (2015). However, this seems highly impractical. Anyway, it would only permit all of the corporate actors to be held individually morally responsible when the corporation is held morally responsible. So there is no practical difference between this unlikely scenario and the scenario in which individual people are held individually responsible for their ethical achievements and shortcomings.
 
10
That is not to say that Kantian ethics does not need a concept of collective responsibility. On Kant’s view, the sovereign (the state) has certain responsibilities towards its citizens, though it is constituted by the unified will of its subjects (Kant 1996). For a discussion, see Rauscher (2017).
 
11
For an insightful discussion of this problem, see Luban et al. (1992).
 
12
Pettit’s grammar here seems suspect; the passive voice obscures that reality that individual people would abuse the lack of corporate moral responsibility—and they would be responsible for the wrongdoing.
 
13
A number of similar claims have been discussed by others. Velasquez writes that: “Saying that a corporation is morally responsible for some wrongful act is acceptable only if it is an elliptical way of claiming that there are some people in the corporation who are morally responsible for that act and who should therefore be blamed and punished” (Velasquez 1983, p. 13). He has also referred to this “elliptical” usage as a “fallacy of division” and an “as-if” usage (Velasquez 1983, pp. 546–549). Larry May has written that corporations are “vicarious” agents (May 1987, pp. 84–86). Thomas L. Carson defends a “translatability thesis”: “We can talk in a loose sense about the duties or responsibilities of corporations, provided that we remember that this is only a ‘shorthand way’ of talking about duties or responsibilities of individuals” (Carson 1994, p. 155). Ramie Tuomela and Pekka Antero Mäkelä argue that group agents like corporations are “functional,” but not literal, agents (Tuomela and Mäkelä 2016, p. 299). My “synecdochical” discussion develops these approaches by specifying the way in which the corporation serves as an elliptical, as-if, vicarious, shorthand for an individual, or functional agent within the corporation: the whole stands in for the part.
 
14
John D. Bishop’s analysis of executives’ responsibility for corporate malfeasance is relevant here (though not offered from a Kantian perspective). He argues that information typically fails to reach corporate executives in predictable ways, which corporate executives are responsible for managing and mitigating (Bishop 1991).
 
15
Altman appears to agree with this point (Altman 2014, p. 229). He discusses the idea that legal responsibility relates only to the corporation’s actions (whether they conform to the law) and not to the corporation’s motivations for meeting legal requirements. Obeying the law does not require corporations to be rational or act on maxims. It does not matter, legally speaking, why corporations have a particular policy or engage in particular practices. What matters is whether these policies and practices conform to legal requirements.
 
16
As Velasquez has it: “unlike compensatory liability, th[e]…kind of responsibility [that I call moral responsibility] does not transfer to other parties” (Velasquez 1983, p. 2).
 
17
I am here discussing and elaborating Kantian ideas, not interpreting Kant’s own writings. For a helpful discussion of Kant’s own writing about the non-transferability of moral responsibility in the Metaphysics of Morals, see Velasquez (1983, pp. 2–3). The key point, as Velasquez has it, is that “moral responsibility is the kind of responsibility that is attributed to an agent only for those actions that originate in the agent” (emphasis original)(Velasquez 1983, p. 3).
 
18
This formulation reflects what has been written about maxims by leading Kantians but is not identical to any other model. O’Neill discusses a variety of possible models. One of the most interesting of these models is “To - - - if…” (O’Neill 1975, 2013, p. 99). Rawls proposes a longer model. His model is structured differently from O’Neill’s: “I am to do X in circumstances C in order to bring about Y unless Z” (2000, p. 168). Korsgaard offers a simpler formulation than Rawls. She writes that: “A maxim of action will usually have the form ‘I will to do action-A in order to achieve purpose-P’ ” (Korsgaard 1996, pp. 57–58).
 
19
As suggested by note 17, above, scholars such as Rawls also include the circumstances of an action in their formulations of the maxims that underlie the actions.
 
20
For a complete discussion of this process, see Scharding (2016).
 
21
Note that these circumstances can (partially) explain why an employee engaged in unethical behavior, on Trevino’s account. These contextual factors do not, though, render such behavior ethical, for her (Trevino 1986, p. 602).
 
22
As discussed above, a corporation’s legal responsibility for the consequences of its actions does not depend on regulators’ being able to hold the corporation morally responsible.
 
23
For an insightful discussion of some of the problems that arise when corporations blame their employees for corporate wrongdoing, see Warren (2007).
 
Literature
go back to reference Allison, H. (1990). Kant’s theory of freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Allison, H. (1990). Kant’s theory of freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Altman, M. C. (2014). Kant and applied ethics: The uses and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell. Altman, M. C. (2014). Kant and applied ethics: The uses and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell.
go back to reference Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2003). Sweatshops and respect for persons. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 221–242.CrossRef Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2003). Sweatshops and respect for persons. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 221–242.CrossRef
go back to reference Bishop, J. D. (1991). The moral responsibility of corporate executives for disasters. Journal of Business Ethics, 10(5), 377–383.CrossRef Bishop, J. D. (1991). The moral responsibility of corporate executives for disasters. Journal of Business Ethics, 10(5), 377–383.CrossRef
go back to reference Borowski, P. J. (1998). Manager-employee relationships: Guided by Kant’s categorical imperative or by Dilbert’s business principle. Journal of Business Ethics, 17(15), 1623–1632.CrossRef Borowski, P. J. (1998). Manager-employee relationships: Guided by Kant’s categorical imperative or by Dilbert’s business principle. Journal of Business Ethics, 17(15), 1623–1632.CrossRef
go back to reference Bowie, N. E. (1999). Business ethics: A Kantian perspective. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. Bowie, N. E. (1999). Business ethics: A Kantian perspective. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
go back to reference Bowie, N. E. (2002). A Kantian approach to business ethics. In T. Donaldson, P. H. Werhane & M. Coding (Eds.), Ethical issues in business: A philosophical approach (7th edn., pp. 61–71). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Bowie, N. E. (2002). A Kantian approach to business ethics. In T. Donaldson, P. H. Werhane & M. Coding (Eds.), Ethical issues in business: A philosophical approach (7th edn., pp. 61–71). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
go back to reference Buchanan, A. (1996). Perfecting imperfect duties: Collective action to create moral obligations. Business Ethics Quarterly, 6(1), 27–42.CrossRef Buchanan, A. (1996). Perfecting imperfect duties: Collective action to create moral obligations. Business Ethics Quarterly, 6(1), 27–42.CrossRef
go back to reference Carson, T. L. (1994). Corporate moral agency: A case from literature. Journal of Business Ethics, 13(2), 155–156.CrossRef Carson, T. L. (1994). Corporate moral agency: A case from literature. Journal of Business Ethics, 13(2), 155–156.CrossRef
go back to reference Davidson, A. (2016). How regulation failed with Wells Fargo. The New Yorker (Sep. 12, 2016). Davidson, A. (2016). How regulation failed with Wells Fargo. The New Yorker (Sep. 12, 2016).
go back to reference De George, R. (1981). Moral responsibility and the corporation. Philosophic Exchange, 12(1), 41–53. De George, R. (1981). Moral responsibility and the corporation. Philosophic Exchange, 12(1), 41–53.
go back to reference French, P. A. (1979). The corporation as a moral person. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(3), 207–215. French, P. A. (1979). The corporation as a moral person. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(3), 207–215.
go back to reference Glazer, E., Rexrode, C., & Andriotis, A. M. (2016). Wells Fargo is trying to fix its rogue account scandal, one grueling case at a time. The Wall Street Journal (Dec. 27, 2016). Glazer, E., Rexrode, C., & Andriotis, A. M. (2016). Wells Fargo is trying to fix its rogue account scandal, one grueling case at a time. The Wall Street Journal (Dec. 27, 2016).
go back to reference Goodpaster, K. E., & Matthews, J. B. Jr. (1982). Can a corporation have a conscience? Harvard Business Review (Jan., 1982). Goodpaster, K. E., & Matthews, J. B. Jr. (1982). Can a corporation have a conscience? Harvard Business Review (Jan., 1982).
go back to reference Hasnas, J. (2012). Reflections on corporate moral responsibility and the problem solving technique of Alexander the Great. Journal of Business Ethics, 107(2), 183–195.CrossRef Hasnas, J. (2012). Reflections on corporate moral responsibility and the problem solving technique of Alexander the Great. Journal of Business Ethics, 107(2), 183–195.CrossRef
go back to reference Herman, B. (1993). The practice of moral judgement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Herman, B. (1993). The practice of moral judgement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Hill, T. E. Jr. (1992). Dignity and practical reasoning in Kant’s moral theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hill, T. E. Jr. (1992). Dignity and practical reasoning in Kant’s moral theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
go back to reference Kant, I. (1996). On the common saying: That may bee correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice. In M. Gregor (trans. and Ed.), Practical philosophy (pp. 273–210). In The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1996). On the common saying: That may bee correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice. In M. Gregor (trans. and Ed.), Practical philosophy (pp. 273–210). In The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Kant, I. (1998). Religion within the boundaries of mere reason. In A. Wood & G. Di Giovanni (trans. and Eds.), Religion within the boundaries of mere reason and other writings (pp. 31–192). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Kant, I. (1998). Religion within the boundaries of mere reason. In A. Wood & G. Di Giovanni (trans. and Eds.), Religion within the boundaries of mere reason and other writings (pp. 31–192). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Kant, I. (2005). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (T.К. Abbott, trans., and L. Denis, trans, and Ed.). Peterboro, ON: Broadview Press. Kant, I. (2005). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (T.К. Abbott, trans., and L. Denis, trans, and Ed.). Peterboro, ON: Broadview Press.
go back to reference Korsgaard, C. M. (1985). Kant’s formula of universal law. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66(1–2), 24–47.CrossRef Korsgaard, C. M. (1985). Kant’s formula of universal law. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66(1–2), 24–47.CrossRef
go back to reference Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Korsgaard, C. M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Korsgaard, C. M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference List, C., & Pettit, P. (2013). Group agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. List, C., & Pettit, P. (2013). Group agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Luban, D., Strudler, A., & Wasserman, D. (1992). ‘Moral responsibility in the age of bureaucracy. Michigan Law Review, 90(8), 2348–2392.CrossRef Luban, D., Strudler, A., & Wasserman, D. (1992). ‘Moral responsibility in the age of bureaucracy. Michigan Law Review, 90(8), 2348–2392.CrossRef
go back to reference Mansell, S. (2013). Shareholder theory and Kant’s “duty of beneficence. Journal of Business Ethics, 117(3), 583–599.CrossRef Mansell, S. (2013). Shareholder theory and Kant’s “duty of beneficence. Journal of Business Ethics, 117(3), 583–599.CrossRef
go back to reference May, L. (1987). The morality of groups: Collective responsibility, group-based harm, and corporate rights. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. May, L. (1987). The morality of groups: Collective responsibility, group-based harm, and corporate rights. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
go back to reference O’Neill, O. (1975, 2013). Acting on principle: An essay on Kantian ethics. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. O’Neill, O. (1975, 2013). Acting on principle: An essay on Kantian ethics. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
go back to reference O’Neill, O. (1989, 2003). Constructions of reason: Explorations of Kant’s practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. O’Neill, O. (1989, 2003). Constructions of reason: Explorations of Kant’s practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Rawls, J. (2000). Lectures on the history of morality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2000). Lectures on the history of morality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Reckard, E. S. (2013). Wells Fargo’s pressure-cooker sales culture comes at a cost. LA Times (Dec. 21, 2013). Reckard, E. S. (2013). Wells Fargo’s pressure-cooker sales culture comes at a cost. LA Times (Dec. 21, 2013).
go back to reference Rönnegard, D. (2015). The fallacy of corporate moral agency. Dordrecht, NL: Springer.CrossRef Rönnegard, D. (2015). The fallacy of corporate moral agency. Dordrecht, NL: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2005). It’s not my fault: Global warming and individual moral obligations. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong & R. Howarth (Eds.), Perspectives on climate change: Science, economics, politics (pp. 221–253), Oxford: Elsevier.CrossRef Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2005). It’s not my fault: Global warming and individual moral obligations. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong & R. Howarth (Eds.), Perspectives on climate change: Science, economics, politics (pp. 221–253), Oxford: Elsevier.CrossRef
go back to reference Strudler, A. (1995). On the ethics of deception in negotiation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(4), 805–822.CrossRef Strudler, A. (1995). On the ethics of deception in negotiation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(4), 805–822.CrossRef
go back to reference Trevino, L. K. (1986). Ethical decision making in organizations: A person-situation interactionist model. The Academy of Management Review, 11(3), 601–617.CrossRef Trevino, L. K. (1986). Ethical decision making in organizations: A person-situation interactionist model. The Academy of Management Review, 11(3), 601–617.CrossRef
go back to reference Tuomela, R., & Mäkelä, P. A. (2016). Group agents and their responsibility. Journal of Ethics, 20(1), 299–316.CrossRef Tuomela, R., & Mäkelä, P. A. (2016). Group agents and their responsibility. Journal of Ethics, 20(1), 299–316.CrossRef
go back to reference Velasquez, M. (1983). Why corporations are not morally responsible for anything they do. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 2(3), 1–18.CrossRef Velasquez, M. (1983). Why corporations are not morally responsible for anything they do. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 2(3), 1–18.CrossRef
go back to reference Velasquez, M. (2003). Debunking corporate moral responsibility. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(4), 531–562.CrossRef Velasquez, M. (2003). Debunking corporate moral responsibility. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(4), 531–562.CrossRef
go back to reference Warren, D. E. (2007). Corporate scandals and spoiled identities: How organizations shift stigma to employees. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 477–496.CrossRef Warren, D. E. (2007). Corporate scandals and spoiled identities: How organizations shift stigma to employees. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 477–496.CrossRef
go back to reference Wilmot, S. (2001). Corporate moral responsibility: What can we infer from our understanding of organizations? Journal of Business Ethics 30(2), 161–169.CrossRef Wilmot, S. (2001). Corporate moral responsibility: What can we infer from our understanding of organizations? Journal of Business Ethics 30(2), 161–169.CrossRef
go back to reference Wood, A. W. (1999). Kant’s ethical thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Wood, A. W. (1999). Kant’s ethical thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Wood, A. W. (2003). The good will. Philosophical Topics, 31(1/2), 457–484.CrossRef Wood, A. W. (2003). The good will. Philosophical Topics, 31(1/2), 457–484.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Individual Actions and Corporate Moral Responsibility: A (Reconstituted) Kantian Approach
Author
Tobey Scharding
Publication date
02-05-2018
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Journal of Business Ethics / Issue 4/2019
Print ISSN: 0167-4544
Electronic ISSN: 1573-0697
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-018-3889-z

Other articles of this Issue 4/2019

Journal of Business Ethics 4/2019 Go to the issue