Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Social Choice and Welfare 4/2022

Open Access 17-05-2022 | Original Paper

Need, equity, and accountability

Evidence on third-party distribution decisions from a vignette study

Authors: Alexander Max Bauer, Frauke Meyer, Jan Romann, Mark Siebel, Stefan Traub

Published in: Social Choice and Welfare | Issue 4/2022

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We report the results of a vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population in which we analyze the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions. We asked participants to divide firewood between two hypothetical persons who either differ in their need for heat or in their productivity in terms of their ability to chop wood. The study systematically varies the persons’ accountability for their neediness as well as for their productivity. We find that participants distribute significantly fewer logs of wood to persons who are held accountable for their disadvantage. Independently of being held accountable or not, the needier person is partially compensated with a share of logs that exceeds her contribution, while the person who contributes less is given a share of logs smaller than her need share. Moreover, there is a domain effect in terms of participants being more sensitive to lower contributions than to greater need.
Notes

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

1 Introduction

This paper contributes to the growing empirical social choice literature which was initiated by the investigations of participants’ individual and group distribution choices by Yaari and Bar-Hillel (1984) as well as Frohlich et al. (1987a) (for overviews see, for example, Konow 2003; Traub et al. 2005; Konow 2009, as well as Gaertner and Schokkaert 2012). This literature shows that participants’ distribution preferences are pluralistic and context-dependent (Konow and Schwettmann 2016). Distribution preferences are pluralistic if they consist of multiple fairness criteria. They are context-dependent if the weight that is given to each criterion depends on institutional factors and personal traits. Apart from the two most important criteria, equality and equity, need has also been identified as relevant in pluralistic justice theories (Konow 2001, 2003; Nicklisch and Paetzel 2020). Moreover, several studies (see, for example, Konow 2001; Schwettmann 2009) have found that people’s support for need-based fairness is balanced against accountability.
However, apart from these stylized facts, not much is known about the quantitative relationship between distribution principles like need and equity, on the one hand, and moderating factors like accountability, on the other hand. In this paper, we will contribute to filling this gap by reporting the results of a vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population in which we analyze the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions.
Following Miller (1999), we define need as the amount of some good that a member of society requires in order to avoid harm. Equity is understood as a variant of Aristotle’s proportionality principle, which holds that output should be allocated in proportion to the participant’s contribution in terms of her productive work effort (Konow 1996). The accountability principle (Konow 2001) is implemented both as responsibility for contribution to output and as responsibility for need.
Participants, who were recruited by an online platform, were asked to divide firewood needed for heating in winter between two hypothetical persons who differed in their need for heat and their productivity in terms of their ability to chop wood (and thus to contribute to the total stock of firewood available). As a novel feature, the study systematically varied the hypothetical persons’ accountability for their neediness as well as for their lower productivity in two separate scenarios.
Our main results are as follows. On average, participants distributed significantly fewer logs of wood to persons who were held accountable for their disadvantage in terms of exhibiting greater need or lower productivity. Independently of being held accountable or not, the needier person was always partially compensated for her disadvantage with a share of logs that exceeded her contribution, while the person who contributed less was given a share of logs smaller than her need share.
When accountability was low, participants did not differentiate between the source of a person’s disadvantage when compensating her with additional logs, that is, greater need and lower productivity were processed symmetrically. In contrast to this, high accountability gave rise to an asymmetry where a disadvantaged person’s compensation was significantly smaller when her disadvantage was due to lower productivity instead of greater need.
We explain this asymmetry by reference points and loss aversion (Tversky and Kahneman 1991), that is, a gain-loss domain effect. If participants perceive the equal-split distribution of logs as a natural reference point (Yaari and Bar-Hillel 1984), loss averse participants might recode the compensation for a self-inflicted disadvantage in terms of a contribution falling below half of the total logs as the reduction of a loss (negative domain) and the compensation for a self-inflicted disadvantage in terms of need exceeding half of the total logs as a gain (positive domain). Hence, due to loss aversion, the former case requires a smaller compensation to establish a just distribution of logs.
Increasing inequality (in terms of different need or productivity) among the two persons left the relative weight put to need and equity unchanged. One case where the disadvantaged person had a deficit of logs and the other person had a surplus made an exception. Here, some participants applied the “net split” principle where both persons received the absolute number of logs they needed plus (or minus) half of the oversupply (or undersupply) of logs.
The analysis of individual choices confirmed that participants were less generous towards the person who was accountable for her own disadvantage. It also showed that the negative impact of accountability was both due to a larger share of participants choosing not to compensate the disadvantaged person at all (extensive margin) and a diminished willingness to compensate her partially (intensive margin). Some participants applied complex distribution principles like the “net split” which cannot be formally represented by a simple convex combination of need, equity, and equality.
Our result concerning the impact of accountability on distribution choices is in line with the vast majority of the empirical and experimental social choice literature which will be reviewed in Sect. 2. For example, Schwettmann (2012), who also used a “heating-in-winter” scenario, found that when the disadvantage of the worse-off individuals was caused by their “careless behaviour” (p. 368), participants chose significantly less often the options that lifted the disadvantaged individual to the poverty line.
Schwettmann (2012) and related studies usually present participants with an exogenously given choice set of distributions that correspond to specific distribution principles such as egalitarianism, Rawls’ maximin principle, or truncated utilitarianism. In our study, we take a different approach by letting participants freely choose how many logs of wood they want to distribute to the persons who differ in their need and productivity. Eliminating the fixed choice set avoids a possible drawback of the expert approach, namely, researcher’s bias (Ahlert et al. 2012), and gives room for behavior more in line with participants’ rather pluralistic opinions about distributive justice.
Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012) comprehensively address methodological issues regarding empirical social choice. They also dwell on the pros and cons of (incentivized) laboratory and (non-incentivized) survey experiments. Empirical research on justice is useful for several reasons. For example, our study, which uses a stratified sample of the German adult population, shows that justice attitudes are linked to personal characteristics such as income; we discover unusual distribution principles like the “net split”; and we contribute data to the development of “empirically informed” pluralistic and context-dependent theories of justice (Konow and Schwettmann 2016). While game-theoretic experiments make predictions about actual behavior, which is to some extent driven by self-interest, Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012) underline that the aim of empirical social choice is to derive information about people’s norms. Vignette studies “provide a contextual richness that is better suited” than incentivized experiments to study fairness judgments embedded in real social institutions (Konow 2009, p. 109).
The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 reviews the theoretical background of this study and introduces previous empirical research on the matter. In Sect. 3, we outline the research design, before presenting the data analysis and results in Sect. 4. Section 5 concludes the paper.

2 Literature review

Needs play an important role in political theory (Doyal and Gough 1984; Weale 1984; Nussbaum 1992; Dean 2013), as a policy goal (Esping-Andersen 1990; Boarini and d’Ercole 2006), and are deeply linked with conceptions of the welfare state (Dean 2002; Plant et al. 2009). Because of their fundamental nature—they refer to the basic conditions for human existence—needs have also been proposed by many as the principal normative grounding for human rights (see, for example, Brock 2005; Gasper 2005, and Renzo 2015). As a distributional criterion, need also features prominently in positive justice research (see, for example, Frohlich and Oppenheimer 1990; Scott et al. 2001; Konow 2003; Michelbach et al. 2003; Scott and Bornstein 2009, as well as Liebig and Sauer 2016), suggesting that voters, too, care about needs.
A need can be understood as an amount of some good that a member of society requires in order to avoid harm (see Miller 1999, for an overview on philosophical approaches to need-based justice, see Siebel and Schramme 2020 as well as Miller 2020). Some needs are biological (for example, the amount of calories a person should consume every day), while many others are social in nature (for example, the amount of money necessary to participate in social life). What separates needs from mere wants is, among other things, that the former are based on a socially shared understanding (Miller 1999). That is, for someone’s want to become a need, others must acknowledge that it is necessary for her in order not to be harmed. As an inter-subjectively acknowledged threshold, needs provide a fundamentally different basis of social justice than other criteria, such as equality, equity, and the Rawlsian maximin principle.
Equity is understood here in terms of Aristotle’s proportionality principle, which relates a person’s entitlement to her contribution (Aristotle 2009; Young 1994). Hence, in equity theory (Homans 1958; Adams 1965), this principle is often called the “contribution principle” (compare Diederich 2020).
Our understanding of accountability is based on Konow’s “principle of accountability”. He states that this principle “calls for allocations to be in proportion to volitional contributions” (Konow 2001, p. 138) and that “individuals are only held accountable for factors they may reasonably control” (Konow 2001, p. 142). Hence, the accountability principle differentiates between actual and controllable contributions.
In the context of distributive justice, one might also think of luck egalitarianism, which argues that someone being worse-off than others can only be justified if she is not accountable for her situation. The effects of “brute luck”, therefore, should be compensated, while those resulting from “option luck” do not qualify for compensation (see, for example, Dworkin 1981; Temkin 1993; Knight 2009; Cohen 2011; Tan 2012; an experimental investigation on attitudes towards compensation and risk-taking can be found in Cappelen et al. 2013a). Theoretical considerations in economics are also relevant. For example, Cappelen and Norheim (2005, 2006), Cappelen and Tungodden (2006), as well as Cappelen et al. (2010) investigated the possible relevance of accountability for liberal egalitarian theories of justice.
From an empirical point of view, Konow (2009) highlighted that many empirical and experimental studies have found preferences for unequal distributions, giving room for principles other than equality (for some examples that also include the principle of need, see Deutsch 1975; Leventhal 1976; Lerner 1977; Lamm and Schwinger 1980; Deutsch 1985; Scott et al. 2001; Cappelen et al. 2008).
Concerning need, participants have been found to prefer distributions that grant a minimum income to everyone. For example, Ahlert et al. (2012) have reported great support for the need principle in terms of “truncated utilitarianism” or a “truncated split” in a modified dictator game. Frohlich and Oppenheimer (1992) have demonstrated that maximizing the average income with a floor constraint is the overwhelmingly preferred distribution principle by groups (also see Frohlich et al. 1987a).
Concerning accountability, Weiner (1993) has found that being accountable leads to greater reward or punishment. Weiner and Kukla (1970) have also demonstrated that lack of effort is punished more severely than lack of ability. Skitka and Tetlock (1993a1993b) have shown that personal ideological orientation influences whether accountability has an impact on distribution decisions. Conservatives are in favor of withholding public assistance to people who are accountable for their predicament while liberals tend to help everyone. Konow (1996) has found support for the assumption that persons are only held accountable for variables they can control (for example a person’s work effort).
Moreover, there are some studies that explore need and accountability in combination. Lamm and Schwinger (1980) investigated the influence of social proximity and accountability, calling it “the perceived causal locus of the needs” (p. 426). However, they did not find a significant influence of accountability on distribution choices. Gaertner and Schwettmann (2007) used questionnaire-experimental studies to assess participants’ justice evaluations for scenarios that involved trade-offs between basic needs on the one hand and efficiency or accountability on the other hand. Incorporating a more efficient choice alternative often led to decisions against the needy person. Introducing personal accountability (in terms of having an innate or acquired handicap) had, if at all, a rather weak impact on justice evaluations. Using a charity game, Buitrago et al. (2009) explored whether it makes a difference if the causes of neediness were known or not, including cases in which neediness was self-inflicted by low effort. They did not find a significant effect, concluding that “help attitudes may result from idiosyncratic preferences, which are unaffected by the causes of neediness” (p. 83).
In contrast to this, Konow (2001) found that telephone and questionnaire survey participants’ support for need-based justice was balanced against both accountability and efficiency. Schwettmann (2012), using a questionnaire study, presented participants with distribution problems that required them to distribute a resource between two groups, providing them with information on benefit, need, efficiency, and accountability. He found strong support for need-oriented distribution choices that were not influenced by concerns for efficiency. Accountability, though, had a significant impact on distribution decisions. When a group was accountable for a shortage of supplies, fewer participants decided to lift its members up to the need threshold. Furthermore, Cappelen et al. (2013b) has found evidence for the influence of need (represented by subjects from low-income countries) and accountability (represented by “entitlement” through real-effort tasks) in a dictator game.
Skitka and Tetlock (1992) have investigated the influence of the causes of neediness on subjects’ readiness to help others. They concluded that subjects “are least likely to help victims whose need is attributed to internal-controllable causes—such as carelessness, laziness, greed, and self indulgence” (p. 496f.). This conclusion is supported by other studies, which all find that performance and accountability have an influence on the support for need as a distribution criterion (see Wagstaff 1994; Farwell and Weiner 1996, as well as Scott and Bornstein 2009).
A considerable literature deals with medical interventions that can obviously be considered as situations of (basic) need satisfaction. For example, Ubel et al. (2001) investigated the influence of accountability on hypothetical decisions for the allocation of transplant livers (also see Neuberger et al. 1998). Those who were accountable for their illness received the transplant less often. Diederich and Schreier (2010) have confirmed the relevance of accountability for prioritization in health care using a mixed-methods design (also see Diederich et al. 2014). Similar results have been obtained by Betancourt (1990), Karasawa (1991), Murphy-Berman et al. (1984), Turner DePalma et al. (1999), as well as Yamauchi and Lee (1999). Annas (1985) and Stanton (1999) have shown the relevance of accountability for the allocation of scarce life-saving technology. Finally, Fowler et al. (1994) have shown that clinical services directed at patients that can be held accountable for their illness were considered a lower priority.
In summary, apart from a small number of exceptions, the literature finds—in a wide range of different scenarios—a significant negative impact of a person’s accountability for her neediness on other persons’ willingness to distribute resources to her. This paper contributes to this literature by reporting the results of a novel vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population that analyzes the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions.
In the following section, we introduce the design of our vignette study. As noted by Konow (2003), vignette studies provide a flexible and easily controllable way to present relevant contextual information to participants. In particular, the empirical social choice literature, pioneered by Yaari and Bar-Hillel (1984), relies on such designs to study preferences for distributions in hypothetical scenarios (overviews are given by Schokkaert 1999; Schwettmann 2009, as well as Gaertner and Schokkaert 2012). As suggested by Konow (2003, 2005), subjects acted as impartial decision-makers in order to avoid self-serving bias. Like Schwettmann (2012), we used heating in winter as a background story. The accountability framing followed Diederich and Schreier (2010), who also used smoking and hereditary factors as causes for a disease, as well as Skitka and Tetlock (1992), who also named the disregard of a doctor’s warning and a gene defect as causes for low and high accountability.
However, most of the above mentioned experimental social choice studies (for example, Gaertner and Schwettmann 2007; Schwettmann 2012; Ahlert et al. 2012) are based on sets of predefined choice alternatives in terms of distributions of resources among two or more persons that correspond to certain normative distribution principles (such as egalitarianism, Rawls’ maximin criterion, and truncated utilitarianism). That is, in these settings, subjects or groups make choices between standards of behavior that were devised by experts. Like in a beauty contest, the standard of behavior that is met with the greatest approval from subjects is declared the winner.
A distinct advantage of this expert driven approach is its ability to provide direct tests of certain axioms and normative theories of distributive justice (see Frohlich et al. 1987a for a prototypical experiment; see Bauer and Meyerhuber 2019, 2020 for general considerations on the interplay of empirical research and normative theory). A drawback of this approach is that such preselections may involve researcher’s bias (Ahlert et al. 2012). Related to the previous argument, people’s opinions about distributive justice frequently are in conflict with these traditional norms and assumptions (see Schokkaert 1999; also see Amiel and Cowell 1999 as well as Traub et al. 2005). Moreover, as noted by Ahlert et al. (2012), rankings of monistic distribution principles according to their approval by subjects in choice experiments do not adequately reflect the fact that “pluralism of distribution principles is the predominant outcome of many empirical investigations” (p. 980; also see Konow 2003).
Consequently, although this study has been heavily inspired by the aforementioned literature, we took a different path by letting participants freely choose how much of a given resource they want to distribute among two persons who differ in their need, productivity, and accountability. This procedure is similar to Question 3 in (Konow 2009). A related approach, though in a modified dictator-game setting, was taken by Andreoni and Miller (2002) as well as Fisman et al. (2007), who let subjects divide fixed amounts of tokens between themselves and another subject with varying prices for payoffs. Hence, whether or not these endogenously determined distributions meet certain distribution principles is an outcome of the study. The main goal of this paper is to quantitatively measure the impact of giving information on accountability on participants’ distribution decisions while systematically varying recipients’ need and productivity.

3 Study design

In Sect. 3.1, we first describe the vignette-based study design. In Sect. 3.2, we then describes the procedure of the study. After that, in Sect. 3.3, we formulate working hypotheses about the impact of different accountability framings and scenarios on participants’ distribution choices.

3.1 The vignettes

In the vignettes, we asked participants to imagine two persons, denoted “Person A” and “Person B”, who do not know each other (for the instructions and the exact wording of the vignette, see Appendix A; we used a set of common German surnames to identify the protagonists). Participants were told that these two persons heat their homes exclusively with firewood and that both have enough logs in stock to survive the upcoming winter. Nonetheless, they need additional firewood so that they will not feel cold. With this in mind, the community allows them to chop wood in the community forest for a certain period of time. Both A and B have little money and, therefore, they have no other means of getting firewood or any other heating material.
In accordance with our definition of need as the amount of some good that a member of society requires in order to avoid harm, the vignettes described the consequences of unfulfilled need (“If they get less than they need, it will get unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be.”). The participants’ task was to distribute an exogenously given number of logs among A and B. In order to justify unequal distributions of logs, we introduced heterogeneity between A and B with respect to their need for logs, or their productivity in terms of the number of logs contributed, and their accountability for their situation.
Participants’ distribution choices therefore reveal how far need is acknowledged, and whether and how the acknowledgment of need is affected by the two persons’ heterogeneity. Note that we intentionally described the consequences of unfulfilled need as mildly harmful (“[...] it will become unreasonably cold in their huts.”) and not as life threatening in order to leave participants more scope for judgment. We also allowed for over-fulfillment of need (“The persons can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts up to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.”) in order to study how participants handle mixed situations (where one person has unfulfilled need and the other has fulfilled need) and situations of “oversupply” (where both persons have different fulfilled needs).
In the following, we call the framing of the vignette with respect to need and productivity scenario and the framing with respect to accountability treatment. The study consisted of two treatments (accountability framings). In the High Accountability Treatment, participants were told that Person A had continued to smoke heavily against the advice of her doctor, which caused a metabolic disease. This is the reason why she needs a higher room temperature (being accountable for greater need in the Need Scenario) or has chopped less wood (being accountable for lower productivity in the Productivity Scenario). In the Low Accountability Treatment, Person A suffers from a congenital metabolic disease, which is why she needs a higher room temperature (hence not accountable for greater need in the Need Scenario) or has chopped less wood (hence not accountable for lower productivity in the Productivity Scenario).
Participants were randomly assigned to one of the two treatments in the beginning of the study. That is, the treatment effect of the source of heterogeneity—high or low accountability—on participants’ distribution decisions was measured at the between-participants level. In both treatments, all participants were presented both scenarios in randomized order. Hence, the impact of the type of heterogeneity—need or productivity differences—on participants’ distribution decisions was measured at the within-participants level.
Table 1
Parametrization of the vignette by scenario and case
Case
1
2
3
4
5
 
Need scenario
Supply situation (AB)
DD
DS
XS
SS
SS
Need A
1800
1400
1000
700
600
Productivity A
1000
1000
1000
1000
1000
Need B
1200
800
400
200
100
Productivity B
1000
1000
1000
1000
1000
Total Need
3000
2200
1400
900
700
Total Logs
2000
2000
2000
2000
2000
 
Productivity scenario
Supply situation (AB)
SS
DS
DX
DD
DD
Need A
1000
1000
1000
1000
1000
Productivity A
1200
800
400
200
100
Need B
1000
1000
1000
1000
1000
Productivity B
1800
1400
1000
700
600
Total Need
2000
2000
2000
2000
2000
Total Logs
3000
2200
1400
900
700
Need Scenario: number of logs needed by Person A, B, and overall while keeping productivity constant. Productivity Scenario: number of logs contributed by Person A, B, and overall while keeping need constant. Participants were presented both scenarios in a randomized order and all five cases of each scenario also in a randomized order. Supply situation of A and B: D = deficit, S = surplus, X = exact need satisfaction
Pretests showed that we could place up to a dozen different cases in our online survey that should not last longer than 30 min altogether (including a post-survey questionnaire). Hence, we decided to present each participant with ten different cases, five per scenario (a sixth case per scenario, which we dropped from the analysis, was used only as a consistency check). The cases varied the amount and distribution of needs and contributed logs. Participants were presented the cases of each scenario in a randomized order. They were shown the number of logs contributed by Person A and Person B (productivity), the number of logs needed by A and B (need), the total number of logs needed and the total number of logs contributed. Participants were then asked to distribute the logs between the two persons according to what they thought to be “most just”. Participants distributed the logs freely among the hypothetical persons, without being provided with predefined or default options. However, participants always had to allocate all available resources to A and B.
When asking participants for the “most just” distribution, we assume (i) that they care about justice and (ii) that some possible distributions are judged as more just than others. In the literature, there are basically two approaches assuring that the elicitation of participants’ fairness preferences is unbiased by selfish motives. One approach holds that, in order to discover “which pattern is the most just” (Frohlich et al. 1987b, p. 2), participants must be able to rationally evaluate the fairness of different distributions “under conditions of very imperfect information”, that is, in a position that creates impartiality of involved social planners by a (more or less transparent) veil of ignorance. In this paper, we follow—like many of the empirical and experimental studies mentioned in the literature review—the quasi-spectator method. The quasi-spectator “is an observer who has no salient stakes in the matter at hand and possesses some, if not all, information relevant to his internalized moral values” (Konow 2009, p. 106). Hence, our vignette study is concerned with the fairness views of third parties.
Table 1 shows the parametrization of the vignette by scenario and case. Let \(p_i^s\) and \(n_i^s\) denote \(i\in \{A,B\}\)’s productivity and need in scenario \(s\in \{(N)eed,(P)roductivity\}\). As shown in the table, the Need Scenario provided both persons with \(p_A^N=p_B^N=1000\) logs (equal constant productivity), but different needs. For example, in case 2, A’s (B’s) need of \(n^N_A=1400\) (\(n^N_B=800\)) logs was greater (smaller) than her productivity of 1000 logs, and their joint need of \(n^N=2200\) logs was greater than their total productivity of \(p^N=2000\) logs. Likewise, the Productivity Scenario attached an equal constant need of \(n^P_A=n^P_B=1000\) logs to both persons, but varied their productivity. For example, in case 2, A’s (B’s) productivity of \(p^P_A=800\) (\(p^P_B=1400\)) logs was insufficient (more than sufficient) to meet her need of 1000 logs, and their joint productivity of \(p^P=2200\) logs was sufficient to meet their total need of \(n^P=2000\). Note that in both scenarios, Person A was always in the disadvantaged position, that is, she was more needy or less productive than Person B.
The parametrization of the vignettes enables studying the effect of the supply situation (D = deficit, S = surplus, X = exact need satisfaction) and the source of heterogeneity on the distribution of logs among A and B. Figure 1 illustrates the design of the cases. Case 1, displayed in the top left diagram, introduces a situation where both A and B have a deficit of logs (DD) in the Need Scenario and a surplus of logs (SS) in the Productivity Scenario.
In the Need Scenario, total productivity is displayed as a straight “supply” line with intercept \(p^N\). Point \(P^N\) on this line marks the actual distribution of productivity. Total need is displayed as a straight “demand” line with intercept \(n^N\). Point \(N^N\) on this line marks the distribution of need. Since \(N^N\) is located in the grey shaded area at the top right of \(P^N\), both A and B have a deficit. And since \(N^N\) is located to the right of the \(45^\circ\) line of equality (where \(x_A=x_B\)), A is worse off than B because she has a bigger deficit.
Analogously, in the Productivity Scenario, total productivity is displayed as a straight line with intercept \(p^P\), and point \(P^P\) on this line marks the actual distribution of productivity. Total need is displayed as a straight line with intercept \(n^P\), and point \(N^P\) on this line marks the distribution of need. Since \(P^P\) is located in the grey shaded area at the top right of \(N^P\), both A and B have a surplus. And since \(P^P\) is located to the left of the \(45^\circ\) line of equality, A is worse off than B because she has a lower surplus. Hence, case 1 in the Productivity Scenario is a mirror image of case 1 in the Need Scenario where the source of heterogeneity and A’s disadvantage is either need or productivity.
The other cases are constructed similarly. In case 2 in the top right diagram of Fig. 1, A has a deficit and B a surplus in the Need Scenario (point \(N^N\) is in the area at the bottom right of \(N^P\)), and A has a surplus and B a deficit in the Productivity Scenario (point \(P^P\) is in the area at the top left of \(P^N\)). Case 3 in the bottom left diagram shows a situation where A’s need is either exactly satisfied or she has surplus, and where B has a surplus or her need is exactly satisfied, depending on the scenario. In cases 4 and 5, \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) are located in the grey shaded area at the bottom left of \(P^N\) and \(N^P\), respectively, and, hence, both A and B have a surplus in the Need Scenario or a surplus in the Productivity Scenario. Case 5 “doubles” case 4, has a slightly different parametrization, and was included to study participants’ sensitivity towards need in more “extreme” situations. The results regarding this question will be reported in a different paper.

3.2 Procedures

Since participants received only a flat payment, we promoted internal validity by asking three control questions after the distribution task in order to make sure that the participants read the instructions carefully and actually understood the task. For the wording of the control questions, see Appendix B. Only those who passed at least two out of three checks were included in the final analysis.
In order to control for participants’ heterogeneity with regard to their socio-demographics and justice attitudes, we asked them, in a post-survey questionnaire, for their age, gender, and equivalent household net income and to state their support for three different distribution principles—need, equity, and equality (compare, for example, Skitka and Tetlock 1992 as well as Mitchell et al. 1993) as well as their evaluation of Person A’s accountability for her situation on a 7-point Likert scale. We also assessed participants’ perceived locus of control in a similar way (see Fong 2001; Phares and Lamiell 1975) and collected information on participants’ health status (dummy variables for being a smoker and suffering from a cardiovascular or metabolic disease). Ubel et al. (2001) found that smokers tend to punish unhealthy behavior regarding the need for transplant organs less often than participants who never smoked (also see Diederich and Schreier 2010). Participants were also asked for their political orientations using a 7-point Likert scale ranging from 1 (most left-wing) to 7 (most right-wing), see Appendix B for wordings.
The survey was programmed in oTree (Chen et al. 2016) and conducted online in September 2019. For reasons of external validity, participants were recruited via the private market research institute respondi. We used respondi’s Online Access Panel which offers a quota sample of the German adult population. Our sample is a random sample of the Online Access Panel, stratified by the three characteristics gender, age, and equivalent household net income, with a sample-size of \(N=200\) (for a breakdown of the sample by gender, age, and income, see Table 9 in Appendix E). The sampling rates of these characteristics in our sample are representative of the adult German population. On the importance of a sample being representative if empirical research is considered as relevant for normative theory, see Schwettmann (2020). Due to financial constraints, though, it was not possible to draw a larger sample that would potentially have captured more characteristics of the German population. The 200 participants who passed the control questions were paid a flat fee of 4.90 euro, equal to 9.80 euro per hour. Note that a further 203 persons started the survey but failed to pass the control questions. These persons were not asked any further questions and did not receive any payment. It was announced by respondi in the beginning of the study that failure to answer the control questions correctly would lead to exclusion from the study without being compensated. The control questions generated similar failure rates (Q1: 29%, Q2: 31%, Q3: 38%). Participants who failed to pass the control questions did not differ from included participants by their stratification characteristics (gender: \(\chi _1^2=0.517\), \(p=0.526\); age: \(\chi _4^2=5.083\), \(p=0.279\); income: \(\chi _4^2=3.447\), \(p=0.486\)). The enormous amount of dropouts shows that general population samples without performance-related incentives can potentially generate a lot of noise in the data. Hence, relatively strict exclusion criteria should be applied.
Before conducting the main study, we tested the efficacy of the vignette with respect to the accountability framing. All details of the pretest are reported in Appendix C. It clearly confirmed that participants attribute higher accountability to persons who disregard their doctor’s warning.

3.3 Working hypotheses

As explained above, participants were asked to distribute the logs between A and B according to what they thought to be most just. Let \(x_i^s\) denote the number of logs distributed to person \(i\in \{A,B\}\) in scenario \(s\in \{N,P\}\). We assume that participants maximize the justice J of the distribution \((x_A^s,x_B^s)\) subject to \(x_B^s=p_A^s+p_B^s-x_A^s\) where the parametrization of the vignette by case and scenario with respect to need \((n_A^s,n_B^s)\), productivity \((p_A^s,p_B^s)\), and accountability treatment \(T=\{low,high\}\) is given. Hence, the optimum number of logs distributed to person A is given by
$$\begin{aligned} x_A^{s*}=\arg \max J(x_A,p_A+p_B-x_A|n_A,n_B,p_A,p_B,T). \end{aligned}$$
(1)
Since we study the justice views of laypersons in terms of participants’ actual distribution choices \(x_A^{s*}\), J is not further specified or “axiomatized”. For a comprehensive account of justice evaluation functions, see Jasso (1978) and Jasso et al. (2016).
We consider two outcome measures of the experiment which both are based on \(x_A^{s*}\). Since the total number of logs available differs from case to case and between the scenarios, we normalize \(x_A^{s*}\) by Person A’s and Person B’s total productivity, \(p^s\), to obtain the first outcome measure, namely, the share of logs distributed to Person A:
$$\begin{aligned} \text{ logshare}_A^s=\frac{x_A^{s*}}{p^s}. \end{aligned}$$
(2)
For example, point \(P^N\) in case 1 in Fig. 1 shows a situation where the logs are distributed exactly according to productivity. Thus, we have \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=0.5\) and \(\tan ^{-1}(x^N_B/x^N_A)=\tan ^{-1}(1000/1000)=45^\circ =\alpha\). Analogously, point \(\nu\) where the line through the origin \(\overline{0N^N}\) and the “supply” line \(p^N\) intersect, shows a situation where the logs are distributed proportional to need. Thus, we have \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=0.6\) and \(\tan ^{-1}(800/1200)=\alpha '=34^\circ\).
The second outcome measure is the normalized deviation from the equal split in favor of Person A:
$$\begin{aligned} \text{ deviation}_A^s=\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \frac{\text{ logshare}_A^s-0.5}{n_A^s/n^s-0.5} &{} \quad \text{(Need } \text{ Scenario) } \\ \frac{0.5-\text{ logshare}_A^s}{0.5-p_A^s/p^s} &{} \quad \text{(Productvitiy } \text{ Scenario) }. \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(3)
The allocation that distributes resources equally—the equal split—has been demonstrated to serve as a natural reference point or social norm for bargaining processes (compare, for example, Yaari and Bar-Hillel 1984; Dawid and Dermietzel 2006, as well as Andreoni and Bernheim 2009). In bargaining experiments, participants frequently choose equal-split allocations even though they are Pareto dominated (Herreiner and Puppe 2010). However, in social choice experiments, only a minority of participants still opts for the equal split when objective reasons like need differences speak in favor of an unequal distribution (Gaertner and Schokkaert 2012). Hence, participants’ sense of justice is reflected in the deviation from the equal split.
We have \(\text{ deviation}_A^s=0\) (equal split) when participants think that heterogeneity among A and B is irrelevant. In Fig. 1, equal-split distributions are located on the \(45^\circ\) line which goes through points \(N^P\) (equal productivity) and \(P^N\) (equal need). We have \(\text{ deviation}_A^s>0\) when participants think that A should be compensated for her disadvantage due to greater need (clockwise rotation) or smaller productivity (counterclockwise rotation). Observations that do not meet the condition \(0\le \text{ deviation}_A^s\le 1\), that is, choices that make A’s situation even worse than it is or make A better off than B are considered as noise in the analysis.
We expect that, on average, participants distribute more than A’s productivity share and less than A’s need share to her, because they think it is just to partially compensate A for her disadvantage. Consequently, \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) in the Productivity Scenario is smaller than in the Need Scenario because A’s need share in the Productivity Scenario is 50% (the upper bound for \(\text{ logshare}_A^P\)), and her productivity share in the Need Scenario is also 50% (the lower bound for \(\text{ logshare}_A^N\)). Hence, the deviation from the equal split is between zero and one. Put into graphs, we expect participants to pick the just distributions from the line \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) in the Need Scenario and from the line \(\overline{P^P\rho }\) in the Productivity Scenario in Fig. 1.
Hypothesis 1
(Partial Compensation) Participants compensate Person A partially for her disadvantage: \(p_A^s/p^s<\text{ logshare}_A^s<n_A^s/n^s\). Partial compensation implies that \(\text{ logshare}_A^P<0.5<\text{ logshare}_A^N\) and \(0<\text{ deviation}_A^s<1\).
We expect that participants’ willingness to compensate Person A for her disadvantage is diminished by high accountability. Hence, participants distribute fewer logs to A and they favor smaller (greater) deviations from the equal split in the Need Scenario (Productivity Scenario).
Hypothesis 2
(Accountability) The just distribution of logs depends on A’s accountability such that
(a)
\(\text{ logshare}_A^s(low)>\text{ logshare}_A^s(high)\),
 
(b)
\(\text{ deviation}_A^N(low)>\text{ deviation}_A^N(high)\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^P(low)<\text{ deviation}_A^P(high)\).
 
If J is homogeneous in the number of logs, A’s just share of logs is determined by her need share and her productivity share, and not by total need and total productivity. Let \(\alpha ^s=\tan ^{-1}(x_B^{s*}/x_A^{s*})\) denote the angle of the line through the origin that contains all just distributions. Since Need Scenario and Productivity Scenario are mirror images of each other, we expect \(45^\circ -\alpha ^N=\alpha ^P-45^\circ\) which is equivalent to \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\text{ logshare}_A^P\). This implies that the just deviation from the equal split is independent of the scenario as indicated by the black arrows in Fig. 1.
Hypothesis 3
(Scenario) Disadvantages that are due to greater need and smaller productivity are treated symmetrically, that is, \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\text{ logshare}_A^P\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^N=\text{ deviation}_A^P\).
However, one could argue that the cognitive perception of the scenarios differs because the equal split is seen as a reference point (Trueblood 2015). Loss averse participants might find compensating A less justified when her disadvantage is due to lower contribution (negative domain, reduction of a loss for A) than when her disadvantage is due to greater need (positive domain, gain for A). Hence, there could be a gain-loss domain effect (Tversky and Kahneman 1991, also see Weiß et al. 2017) that would imply \(\text{ deviation}_A^P>\text{ deviation}_A^N\). Moreover, there could also be an interaction effect between scenario framing and accountability treatment.
As can be seen in Table 1 and Fig. 1, the five cases differ by their supply situation. Figure 1 shows that \(P^N\) and \(N^P\) remain constant, while \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) are obtained from systematically changing both relative inequality in productivity or need (visualized by the angles of the dashed lines through \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) to the line of equality) and total need or total productivity (visualized by the “demand” and “supply” lines). Hence, the study design does not allow the separation of both possible effects on the just distribution of logs. Keeping relative inequality constant would have led to very small absolute need and productivity differences in cases where \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) are located in the grey shaded area at the bottom left of \(P^N\) and \(N^P\). Hence, we decided to additionally increase relative inequality among A and B.
In order to deal with this problem, we first assume that the absolute supply situation in terms of A having a deficit or surplus (the location of the “demand” and “supply” lines) does not affect participants’ justice considerations. Hence, in the Need Scenario, we expect that the share of logs that is distributed to A increases in relative inequality when moving from case 1 to 5 because point \(\nu\) moves outward on the line of just distributions \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) and \(\alpha '\) decreases. The opposite applies to the Productivity Scenario where \(P^P\) moves outward on the line of just distributions \(\overline{P^P\rho }\) and \(90-\alpha '\) increases. Hence, in the Need Scenario (Productivity Scenario), we hypothesize that participants distribute relatively more (less) logs to A when a case exhibits greater inequality among A and B. Since the deviation from the equal split is normalized by the difference between A’s need share and her productivity share (the length of \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) and \(\overline{P^P\rho }\)), we expect it to be independent of the supply situation.
Hypothesis 4
(Supply situation) Let \(y,z\in \{1,2,3,4,5\}\) denote the number of the case where \(y<z\) and cases with lower numbers exhibit less inequality (with respect to need or productivity) among A and B, then we have \(\text{ logshare}_A^N(z)-\text{ logshare}_A^P(z)>\text{ logshare}_A^N(y)-\text{ logshare}_A^P(y)\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s(y)=\text{ deviation}_A^s(z)\).
If the absolute supply situation matters for the distribution of logs, it is likely to have a dampening effect in the Need Scenario (A receives relatively less, \(\alpha '\) decreases less) because increasing inequality is combined with an improving absolute supply situation (Person A starts with a deficit and ends up with a surplus). It is also likely to have a dampening effect in the Productivity Scenario (A receives relatively more, \(90-\alpha '\) increases less) because increasing inequality is combined with a worsening absolute supply situation (Person A starts with a surplus and ends up with a deficit). Hence, the two scenario differences in H4 might get smaller, but the effect of increasing inequality should remain.

4 Results

We begin the presentation of the results with participants’ responses to the accountability question posed in the post-survey questionnaire. In order to interpret the results of this study in terms of Person A’s accountability for her disadvantage, it is necessary to establish that the accountability framing actually worked. As noted in the previous section, the vignette design had already been successfully tested in a pretest, though with a student sample. Next, in Sect. 4.2, we test our working hypotheses by studying participants’ average distribution choices. In Sect. 4.3, we then turn to participants’ individual distribution choices, and we identify different distribution principles that participants consistently applied in order to distribute the logs of wood to Persons A and B.

4.1 Accountability judgments

Figure 2 shows participants’ mean judgment of Person A’s accountability for her greater need and her lower productivity on a 7-point Likert scale. A two-tailed t test confirms that, in both scenarios, the bar representing the High Accountability Treatment is significantly larger than the one representing the low accountability treatment (Need Scenario, High Accountability Treatment: mean \(=5.00\) (90% CI [4.72, 5.28]), Low Accountability Treatment: mean \(=4.04\) (90% CI [3.75, 4.34]), mean difference \(=0.96\) (90% CI [0.55, 1.36]), \(p\le 0.01\); Productivity Scenario, High Accountability Treatment: mean \(=5.16\) (90% CI [4.88, 5.43]), Low Accountability Treatment: mean \(=3.98\) (90% CI [3.68, 4.28]), mean difference \(=1.18\) (90% CI [0.78, 1.58]), \(p\le 0.01\); two-sample two-tailed t test, between-participants treatment). Hence, as already suggested by the pretest, the vignette was effective for inducing a low and a high accountability frame in participants with respect to Person A’s disadvantage.
Moreover, Fig. 2 indicates that there is no significant difference in participants’ mean judgment of Person A’s accountability between Need and Productivity Scenario. A pairwise two-tailed t test cannot reject the null hypothesis of equality of the mean accountability judgment (High Accountability Treatment, Need Scenario vs. Productivity Scenario: mean difference \(= -0.16\) (90% CI \([-0.31, 0.02]\)), \(p = 0.104\); Low Accountability Treatment, Need Scenario vs. Productivity Scenario: mean difference \(=0.07\) (90% CI \([-0.18, 0.31]\)), \(p = 0.659\); paired-sample two-tailed t test, within-participants treatment). Hence, we conclude that it did not matter to the participants whether A’s disadvantage was caused by need or productivity differences.

4.2 Average distribution choices

In this subsection, we turn to our main interest, namely, the impact of scenario and accountability treatment on the just distribution of logs. We also analyze how the supply situation affects the distribution of logs. The following analyses of \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s\) are based on 2000 distribution choices (10 per participant). Note that only 208 distribution choices (10.4%) do not meet the condition \(0\le \text{ deviation}_A\le 1\).

4.2.1 Means

Figure 3 displays \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) as a bar chart (left panels) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s\) as a range plot (right panels). The top panels show the distribution of logs by treatment and scenario; the middle (bottom) panels show the distribution of logs in the Need Scenario (Productivity Scenario) by treatment and case. Means, standard errors, cases numbers, and t tests can be seen in Tables 10 and 11 in Appendix E.
Concerning the partial compensation hypothesis (H1), the bar charts show as hypothesized that participants on average distributed significantly more logs to Person A than her productivity share and significantly less than her need share in all scenarios, treatments, and cases. Consequently, \(\text{ logshare}_A\) exceeds 50% in the Need Scenario and falls below 50% in the Productivity Scenario. The range plots of \(\text{ deviation}_A\) lie between 0 and 1.
The accountability hypothesis (H2) is clearly confirmed by the data, too. As regards the share of logs distributed to A, the treatment effect of high accountability is significant in all cases except for case 1 in the Need Scenario (see Table 10). As regards the deviation from the equal split, the treatment effect is also significant (except for case 1), and it is negative in the Need Scenario and positive in the Productivity Scenario (see Table 11 in the Appendix) as hypothesized.
The hypotheses concerning the symmetry of the scenarios (H3) and the impact of the supply situation (H4) are tested using regression analysis. Test results are reported in the following paragraphs.

4.2.2 Marginal effects of scenario and supply situation

The analysis of means controls neither for participants’ socio-demographics and attitudes nor for potential ordering effects. Hence, we perform regression analysis. All statistical details and tables are given in Appendix D. The estimated marginal effects of scenario, supply situation, and accountability treatment are displayed in Fig. 4.
First, we turn to the marginal effects of scenario and supply situation on the share of logs. The top left panel of Fig. 4 displays the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario (the Need Scenario is the benchmark case) on the share of logs distributed to A by accountability treatment and case. All marginal effects are negatively significant as hypothesized by the partial compensation hypothesis (H1). There is no difference between the accountability treatments with respect to the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario, except for case 1 (see Table 5 in Appendix D).
A pairwise comparison of the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario by case shows that the negative impact of the Productivity Scenario in cases 4 and 5 is significantly greater than in case 1. This confirms the supply-situation hypothesis (H4) which holds that increasing inequality with respect to need or productivity among A and B causes greater differences of A’s just share of logs between the scenarios (see the top panel of Table 8 in Appendix D, significance levels are corrected for multiple hypotheses testing using the Bonferroni correction).
In order to test the symmetry of the scenarios (H3), we first compute \(\text{ logshare}_A^N\) and \(\text{ logshare}_A^P\), and then we test \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\text{ logshare}_A^P\). In the top left panel of Fig. 4, the thick lines indicate the reference values for testing symmetry of the scenarios. As can be seen in Fig. 4, in the Low Accountability Treatment, symmetry cannot be rejected, except for cases 2 and 3 where the positive difference of A’s share of logs from 50% in the Need Scenario exceeded the negative difference of her share of logs from 50% in the Productivity Scenario. In the High Accountability Treatment, symmetry is clearly rejected (except for case 2). Just distributions are “biased” in the direction discussed in Sect. 3.3; participants deviated more from the equal-split distribution when A’s disadvantage was due to lower productivity than when it was due to greater need (see Table 6 in Appendix D).
The top right panel of Fig. 4 displays the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario on the deviation from the equal split by accountability treatment and case (also see Table 5 in Appendix D). Except for case 2 in both treatments as well as cases 1 and 3 in the High Accountability Treatment, all marginal effects are positively significant, thereby rejecting the hypothesis that disadvantages due to greater need and smaller productivity are treated symmetrically (H3). High accountability dampens the asymmetry because the share of respondents who are not all willing to compensate Person A for her disadvantage is relatively high in both scenarios.
Case 2 differs significantly from all other cases. In this regard, we have to qualify our previous conclusion that H4 (\(\text{ deviation}_A^s(y)=\text{ deviation}_A^s(z)\)) is supported by the data. Remember that case 2 involves a deficit for A and a surplus for B in both scenarios. In Sect. 4.3, we show that some participants applied a specific distribution principle in this mixed supply situation, which we call “net split”.

4.2.3 Marginal effect of accountability

Now, we turn to the marginal effect of accountability (for statistical details, see Tables 7 and 8 in Appendix D). The bottom left panel of Fig. 4 displays the marginal effect of the High Accountability Treatment on the share of logs distributed to A (the Low Accountability Treatment is the benchmark case). Except for cases 1 and 2 in the Need Scenario, all marginal effects are negatively significant. The figure also shows that high accountability had a significantly greater negative impact in cases 4 and 5 than in case 1. Hence, the supply situation in terms of greater inequality among A and B caused a greater accountability effect with respect to the just share of logs distributed to A.
According to H2, we also expect \(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A<0\) in the Need Scenario and \(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A>0\) in the Productivity Scenario. Hence, we display \(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A|\) in the bottom right panel of Fig. 4 to ease visual comparisons. The bottom right panel displays the marginal effect of the High Accountability Treatment by scenario and case. As expected, the marginal effects are negatively significant (except for case 1 of the Need Scenario). There is no difference between the scenarios and there are case differences similar to the share of logs. In summary, the negative effect of high accountability is clearly confirmed (H2).

4.2.4 Control variables

Next, we address the control variables (for statistical details, see Table 4 in Appendix D). Participants with higher equivalent household net incomes were willing to allocate a greater share of logs to Person A. Among the health-related variables, only the smoker dummy exhibits a significant positive coefficient in the regressions on \(\text{ logshare}_A\) (and a negative coefficient in the regressions on \(\text{ deviation}_A\)), which may point to a “solidarity effect” among smokers.
The covariates that capture participants’ support for different distribution principles are significant in all regressions on the share of logs distributed to A. Participants who think that need is an important criterion of distributive justice distributed more logs to A and chose greater deviations from the equal split. Participants who think that equity is an important criterion of justice distributed less to A and, also, chose greater deviations from the equal split. Participants who show stronger support for equality gave more to A and, naturally, tolerated only smaller deviations from the equal split. The positive coefficient of the political-attitude variable indicates that people who place themselves rather on the right side of the political spectrum made less equal distribution choices.
Each participant submitted two accountability judgments—one for the Need Scenario and one for the Productivity Scenario. As can be seen in the bottom row of Table 4 in Appendix E, the accountability judgments do not have a significant impact on average distribution choices (\(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s\)) when the accountability judgment enters the regression model as a differential intercept. Beyond that, it would be interesting to analyze whether the size of the accountability effect (\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A^s\) and \(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A^s|\)) depends on within-subjects differences between the accountability judgments of the two treatments in a given scenario. However, since participants were assigned to either the Low Accountability Treatment or the High Accountability Treatment, this analysis cannot be performed with our between-subjects design.

4.3 Individual distribution choices

In this subsection, we look at participants’ individual distribution choices. First, we group the five choices made by each participant in each scenario into several mutually exclusive categories according to the share of logs distributed to Person A. In the Need Scenario, the choice categories correspond to the following distribution principles: “less” than the equal split (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N<0.5\)), “equal split” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N=0.5\)), “partial compensation” (\(0.5<\text{ logshare}_A^N<n_A^N/n^N\)), A receives her “need share” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N=n_A^N/n^N\)), and A receives “more” than her need share (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N>n_A^N/n^N\)). In the Productivity Scenario, the categories correspond to the following distribution principles: A receives “less” than her productivity share (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P<p_A^P/p^P\)), A receives her “productivity share” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P=p_A^P/p^P\)), “partial compensation” (\(p_A^P/p^P<\text{ logshare}_A^P<0.5\)), “equal split” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P=0.5\)), and “more” than the equal split (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P>0.5\)). With regard to the exact distribution principles “need share”, “productivity share”, and “equal split”, we tolerate that \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) deviates 1 percentage point from the respective target value in order to account for typos and small rounding errors. Second, we identify participants who consistently applied the same distribution principle across all cases within a scenario.
Figure 5 shows the relative frequency of individual choices that conform with one of the distribution principles by case and scenario. Grey (white) bars refer to the Low (High) Accountability Treatment. In the Need Scenario, equal split, partial compensation, and need share make up 89% of all choices in the Low Accountability Treatment and 92% in the High Accountability Treatment. Interestingly, participants almost never distributed logs of wood in exact accordance with A’s need share (except for case 1 which depicts a situation of severe undersupply). A comparison of participants’ distribution choices between the accountability treatments shows a clear shift towards the equal split when Person A is highly accountable for her disadvantage. The overall share of equal-split choices increases from 44% to 66% (\(\chi ^2_1=49.993\), \(p\le 0.01\)). Increasing inequality from case 1 to case 5 does not intensify the effect of high accountability on the share of equal splits, however.
The dark shaded bars indicate the share of choices in the respective category that are also compatible with a distribution principle that might be called “net split”. Here, A and B receive the absolute number of logs they need plus (minus) half of the oversupply (undersupply). Although the net split is an unusual distribution principle, 8% of all choices in the Low Accountability Treatment and 5% in the High Accountability Treatment are in line with the net-split principle, and it is particularly prevalent in the “mixed supply” case 2 (23% vs. 12%). Though we can conceive distribution principles which are perhaps more sophisticated than the ones displayed in the figure, other principles did not play a significant role in terms of having been chosen more than once or twice in the Need Scenario.
The right panel of Fig. 5 shows a slightly different picture for the Productivity Scenario. Here, 85% of the choices in the Low Accountability Treatment and 94% of the choices in the High Accountability Treatment distribute A’s productivity share to her, compensate her partially, or split the logs equally among A and B. The distribution of the choices to the categories is more balanced, however. There is a clear shift from equal split and partial compensation towards A’s productivity share in the High Accountability Treatment. The overall share of equal-split choices decreases from 35 to 19% (\(\chi ^2_1=33.035\), \(p\le 0.01\)). As in the Need Scenario, there is no significant interaction between the size of the need gap and the marginal effect of high accountability on the share of equal splits. Moreover, there is a striking number of choices (14% vs. 5%) which distribute more than 50% of the logs to A (though she has the same need as B and lower productivity than her). Many of these choices can be explained by the “swap” principle (displayed by the dark-shaded bars in the figure): A receives \((1-p_A^P/p^P)=p_B^P/p^P\)% of the logs and B receives \(p_A^P/p^P=(1-p_B^P/p^P)\)%. Note that, in the Productivity Scenario, the net-split principle coincides with the equal split because A and B have equal need of logs.
Finally, we turn to participants who consistently applied the same distribution principle across all five cases within a scenario. In Fig. 6, we focus on the four most important distribution principles according to their choice frequencies in the scenarios (Need Scenario: equal split, partial compensation, A’s need share, and net split; Productivity Scenario: equal split, partial compensation, A’s productivity share, and swap). The number of participants sticking to one of these distribution principles across all cases is 17.6% (Low Accountability) and 38.5% (High Accountability) in the Need Scenario as well as 24.2% (Low Accountability) and 29.4% (High Accountability) in the Productivity Scenario. Considering six monistic distribution principles, Meyer (2019) found that across several experiments 37% of the subjects always chose in line with the same distribution principle. In five experiments that also involved need as a distribution principle, up to 18% chose the need principle.
In the Need Scenario, 37% of the participants consistently distributed logs to A and B according to the equal-split principle, when A was highly accountable for her disadvantage. This number is significantly greater than the 13% who applied the equal-split principle in the Low Accountability Treatment (\(\chi ^2_1=14.248\), \(p\le 0.01\)). Only a small percentage of participants always compensated A partially. 3% of the participants in the Low Accountability Treatment and none of the participants in the High Accountability Treatment distributed the logs according to A’s need (\(\chi ^2_1=3.648, p=0.056\)). Although Fig. 5 showed that there is a substantial number of choices in line with the net split, none of the participants consistently applied the principle. The right panel of Fig. 6 confirms a more balanced distribution of participants to the categories in the Productivity Scenario. 12% (Low Accountability) and 7% (High Accountability) of the participants consistently applied the equal-split principle, but the treatment difference is insignificant (\(\chi ^2_1=1.301\), \(p=0.254\)). Here, the only significant difference between Low Accountability Treatment and High Accountability Treatment can be observed with regard to the productivity principle (\(\chi ^2_1=6.621\), \(p=0.010\)).
In summary, the analysis of individual choices shows that we have to qualify hypothesis (H1), in particular when we focus on equal-split choices. The large number of equal-split choices indicates that partial compensation is a better prediction of average rather than of individual distribution choices. Our second main hypothesis (H2) is clearly confirmed, as participants’ individual choices became less generous towards Person A when she was highly accountable for her own disadvantage. The previous result suggests, however, that the accountability effect is partly due to a larger share of participants choosing not to compensate Person A at all (extensive margin) rather than to a diminished willingness to compensate her partially (intensive margin) in the High Accountability Treatment.

5 Conclusion

In this paper, we have reported the results of a vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population in which we analyzed the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions. Participants, who were recruited via an online platform, were asked to divide firewood needed for heating in winter between two hypothetical persons who differed in their need for heat and their productivity in terms of their ability to chop wood (and thus their ability to contribute to the total stock of firewood available). The study systematically varied the disadvantaged person’s accountability for her neediness as well as for her lower productivity.
The findings presented in the previous section support our main hypothesis that the disadvantaged Person A’s accountability impacts participants’ willingness to compensate her for her greater need and her lower productivity. Participants distributed significantly fewer logs of wood to Person A when she was held accountable for her disadvantage. Independently of being held accountable or not, the needier person was always compensated with a share of logs that exceeded her contribution, while the person who contributed less was given a share of logs smaller than her need share.
This result is in line with the vast majority of the experimental social choice literature briefly reviewed in Sect. 2 of this paper. For example, Schwettmann (2012), who also used a “heating-in-winter” scenario, found that when the disadvantage of the worse-off individuals was caused by their “careless behaviour” (p. 368), participants chose significantly less often the options (“splits”) that lifted the disadvantaged individual to the poverty line. He therefore concluded that “[a]lthough support for people in need continued to be high, a conflict between the principles of needs and responsibility clearly existed” (p. 372).
Schwettmann (2012) and related studies usually present participants with an exogenously given choice set of distributions that correspond to specific distribution principles such as egalitarianism, Rawls’ maximin principle, or truncated utilitarianism. Like in a beauty contest, the distribution principle that meets with the most approval from participants is declared the winner. In our study, we took a different approach by letting participants freely choose how many logs of wood they wanted to distribute to Persons A and B, who differed in their need and productivity. Eliminating the fixed choice set avoids a possible drawback of the expert approach, namely, researcher’s bias (Ahlert et al. 2012), and leads to behavior more in line with participants’ rather pluralistic opinions about distributive justice (see Schokkaert 1999; Amiel and Cowell 1999; Konow 2003; Traub et al. 2005; Ahlert et al. 2012).
Apart from the main treatment effect of accountability, a regression analysis additionally revealed interesting differences between the two scenarios presented to the participants. In the analysis of the share of logs distributed to A, participants did not differentiate between the source of a person’s disadvantage when compensating her with additional logs in the Low Accountability Treatment, that is, greater need and lower productivity were processed symmetrically. In contrast to this, high accountability gave rise to an asymmetry, with a disadvantaged person’s compensation being significantly smaller when her disadvantage is due to lower productivity instead of greater need. Assuming that equality of need and productivity are perceived as reference points, this result points to a gain-loss domain effect (Tversky and Kahneman 1991, also see Weiß et al. 2017) and an increased perceptual sensitivity (Trueblood 2015) to Person A’s lower contribution (negative domain) than to her greater need (positive domain). In the analysis of the deviation from the equal split, the asymmetry between need and productivity prevailed even in the Low Accountability Treatment and was more pronounced.
With one exception, increasing inequality with respect to need or productivity among the two persons caused greater differences of the disadvantaged person’s just share of logs between the scenarios, and it left the deviation from the equal split unchanged. In other words, the relative weight put to need and equity was almost independent of the supply situation. The case where the disadvantaged person had a deficit of logs and the other person had a surplus made an exception. Here, some subjects applied the “net-split” principle where A and B received the absolute number of logs they needed plus (minus) half of the oversupply (undersupply).
Our sample is representative of the German population with respect to gender, age, and income distribution. We saw that participants with higher equivalent household net incomes were willing to allocate a greater share of logs to Person A. Regression analysis also showed that smokers were willing to distribute more logs to the disadvantaged person, which may point to a “solidarity effect” among smokers. Participants who thought that need was an important criterion of distributive justice distributed more logs to A and chose greater deviations from the equal split; participants who thought that equity was an important criterion of justice distributed less to A and chose greater deviations from the equal split; participants who showed stronger support for equality gave more to A and, naturally, were less tolerant to deviations from the equal split. Moreover, participants who placed themselves rather on the right side of the political spectrum made less equal distribution choices.
This quantitative analysis of individual distribution preferences clearly shows that participants trade off distribution principles like equity (contribution) and need against each other and take into account a person’s accountability for her disadvantage. Hence, the evidence presented here supports earlier studies on accountability and need-based justice (see, for example, Konow 2001; Schwettmann 2009). It also supports the empirical and experimental social choice literature (see Konow and Schwettmann 2016) that posits that participants’ distribution preferences are pluralistic (in terms of consisting of multiple fairness criteria) and context-dependent (the weight that is given to each fairness criterion depends on, for example, institutional factors and personal traits). Finally, our results also underline the (sometimes underestimated) importance of need as a distribution criterion.

Acknowledgements

We are grateful for the support and input throughout all project phases from participants of FOR 2104 meetings. We thank Densua Mumford for proofreading the manuscript as well as participants at the 1st European Experimental Philosophy Conference, the 2020 Conference of the Society for the Advancement of Behavioral Economics, and the 25th Congress of the German Society for Philosophy for their input. We also thank three anonymous referees for their helpful and constructive comments.

Declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.
Open AccessThis article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by/​4.​0/​.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Appendix

Appendix A: Instructions of the main experiment

Welcome screen

In this survey, we are interested in your personal opinion and judgment. Therefore, there are no correct or incorrect answers in this study.
You will probably need about 30 min if you work intently. It is important that you complete the study without interruption and without closing your browser. If you cannot avoid closing your browser, you can continue the study by clicking on the link in the invitation e-mail again.
We will analyze your answers together with the answers of all other participants in this study. All data will be stored in an anonymous format so that no participant can be identified. The results of the study will be published. They may influence future research and may be used to inform policymakers.
If you are editing this study on a smartphone, it is likely that some of the tables displayed will extend beyond the right edge of the screen. Hence, it is best to use “landscape mode” or scroll through the tables to view them in their entirety.
Thank you for participating!

Introduction

Your task is to distribute logs of wood.
We will present you with a number of different scenarios and ask you to imagine that they are real. Please take the time to put yourself in the position of the scenarios and come to a personal judgment.
In these scenarios, when moving from screen to screen, text that differs from the previous page is highlighted in blue. Text that is similar to that in the previous page is not highlighted in blue. Moreover, the numbers reported in the tables change from page to page.

Vignette text and treatments

Note: The surnames of the two persons, denoted by A and B in the following, were randomly drawn from a set of typical German surnames: A,B \(\in\) {Fischer, Meyer, Müller, Schmidt, Schneider, Weber}. The presentation of the information in the table was randomized (more productive/more needy person in upper/lower row, information on need and wood chopped in left/right column).
Please imagine two persons, A and B, who do not know each other. Both heat their huts exclusively with firewood and have enough logs in stock to survive in winter. However, they need additional firewood in order not to feel cold in winter. The community allows the two persons to chop wood in the community forest for a certain period of time. A and B have little money and therefore have no other way to get firewood.
[High Responsibility Treatment, Need Scenario]
A needs r and B needs s logs. If they get less than they need, it will get unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. The persons can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts up to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
Both A and B have chopped o logs.
A continued to smoke heavily against the advice of her doctor. Therefore, A is suffering from a metabolic disease, which is why she needs a higher room temperature. Therefore, A needs more firewood than B.
[High Responsibility Treatment, Productivity Scenario]
A and B both need r logs. If they get less than they need, it will get unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. The persons can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts up to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
A has chopped o logs and B has chopped p logs.
A continued to smoke heavily against the advice of her doctor and is suffering from a cardiovascular disease. That is why A has chopped less wood than B.
[Low Responsibility Treatment, Need Scenario]
A needs r and B needs s logs. If they get less than they need, it will become unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. The persons can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
Both A and B have chopped o logs.
A suffers from a congenital metabolic disease, which is why she needs a higher room temperature. Therefore, A needs more firewood than B.
[Low Responsibility Treatment, Productivity Scenario]
A and B both need r logs. If they get less than they need, it gets unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. The persons can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts up to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
A has chopped o logs and B has chopped p logs.
A suffers from a congenital cardiovascular disease. Therefore, A chopped less wood than B.
So, both persons have cut q logs together. In the table, you can see how much wood they have chopped and how much firewood in terms of logs they need. Please enter in the free spaces how you want to distribute the firewood between the two persons in the way that you think is most just. Please distribute all q logs, that is, 100% to A and B.
There are n logs left.
Person
Chopped
Needs
Should receive
Percentage
A
o
r
u
x
B
p
s
v
y
Total
q
t
w
z
o, p, \(q=o+p\), r, s, \(t=r+s\) are parameters of the experiment (see Sect. 3); u and v had to be entered by the participants; \(n=q-w\), \(w=u+v\), \(x=100u/w\), \(y=100v/w\), and \(z=x+y\) were automatically calculated while typing

Appendix B: Additional questions

Control questions

Note: Options for questions 2 and 3 were displayed in randomized order.
Question 1
Please describe how often you reflect on justice issues in your daily life and what this means to you.
We ask this question to ensure that the tasks are read carefully. If you are reading this, please enter the number 42 in the field below instead of an answer to the question itself.
Have you ever reflected on justice issues?
Question 2
Which statements apply to this study? Multiple answers are possible.
Farmers work a rye field.
Farmers work a sunflower field.
Farmers work a wheat field.
Wood is needed to build a house.
Wood is needed to heat in winter.
Water is needed to run a mill.
Water is needed to drink.
Question 3
What was the largest quantity of logs to be distributed in the previous scenarios?
44
55
770
3000
9999
55505
70777

Support for different distribution principles

Note: Items were displayed in a randomized order.
Please indicate on the following scale from 1 to 7 how important the considerations below were for your distribution decisions. 1 stands for not important at all. 7 stands for very important.
  • Each person should receive as much wood as they need.
  • Each person should receive the wood they have chopped.
  • Each person should receive the same amount of wood.

Locus of control

Some people think that they have complete freedom of choice in how they live their lives; others think that they have no choice in how they live their lives. What do you believe to be true for yourself? How much freedom of choice do you have in how you shape your life? Please give your answer on a scale from 1 to 7. 1 stands for no free choice at all. 7 stands for completely free choice.

Political orientation

In politics, one speaks of left-wing and right-wing. How would you generally describe your own political position? On a scale from 1 to 7, where would you rate yourself? 1 stands for left. 7 stands for right.

Person A’s accountability

How do you rate A’s personal accountability for the smaller [higher] amount of wood she cut [needs]? Please give your answer on a scale from 1 to 7. 1 stands for not accountable at all. 7 stands for completely accountable.

Participants’ health

  • Do you currently smoke, for example, (e-)cigarettes, pipes, or cigars?
  • Do you currently suffer from a cardiovascular disease or have you suffered from a cardiovascular disease in the past?
  • Do you currently suffer from a metabolic disorder or have you suffered from a metabolic disorder in the past?

Appendix C: Pretest

Instructions of the pretest

Please imagine two people, Schneider and Müller, who do not know each other. Both heat exclusively with firewood and have enough logs in stock to survive in winter. However, they need additional firewood in order not to feel cold during winter. Their community allows them to chop wood in the community forest for a certain period of time. Schneider and Müller have little money and therefore have no other way to get firewood.
[High Responsibility for Need Treatment]
Both Schneider and Müller chopped the same amount of wood. Schneider needs more firewood than Müller. If they get less than they need, it will become unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. They can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
Schneider has continued to smoke heavily against the advice of her doctor. As a result, Schneider is suffering from a metabolic disease, which is why she needs a higher room temperature. Therefore, Schneider needs more firewood than Müller.
How do you assess Schneider’s personal accountability for the higher amount of firewood she needs?
[High Responsibility for Productivity Treatment]
Both Schneider and Müller need the same amount of firewood. If they get less than they need, it will become unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. They can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
Schneider has continued to smoke heavily against the advice of her doctor. As a result, Schneider is suffering from a cardiovascular disease. That is why Schneider has chopped less wood than Müller.
How do you assess Schneider’s personal accountability for the smaller amount of wood she has chopped?
[Low Responsibility for Need Treatment]
Both Schneider and Müller have chopped the same amount of wood. Schneider needs more firewood than Müller. If they get less than they need, it will become unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. They can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
Schneider suffers from a congenital metabolic disease, which is why she needs a higher room temperature. Therefore, Schneider needs more firewood than Müller.
How do you assess Schneider’s personal accountability for the higher amount of firewood she needs?
[Low Responsibility for Productivity Treatment]
Both Schneider and Müller need the same amount of firewood. If they get less than they need, it will become unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be. They can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.
Schneider suffers from a congenital cardiovascular disease. Therefore, Schneider has chopped less wood than Müller.
How do you assess Schneider’s personal accountability for the smaller amount of wood she has chopped?
Please give your answer on a scale from 1 to 10. 1 stands for not at all accountable. 10 stands for fully accountable.

Results of the pretest

In the pretest, participants were simply asked to rate Person A’s accountability for her situation on a scale from 1 to 10. The pretest was conducted with paper and pencil and involved 82 students at Helmut Schmidt University Hamburg in January 2019. 53 participants were randomly assigned to the Need Scenario, 29 to the Productivity Scenario, and all of them were treated with both the Low and High Accountability framings (that is, in contrast to the main study, we used a within-participants treatment for the accountability framing and a between-participants treatment for the scenario). In both scenarios, the mean difference of participants’ accountability judgment was significantly greater for the High than for the Low Accountability Treatment (Need Scenario, High Accountability Treatment: mean \(=8.53\) (90% CI [8.14, 8.92]), Low Accountability Treatment: mean \(=2.85\) (90% CI [2.25, 3.45]), mean difference \(=5.68\) (90% CI [5.07, 6.29]), \(p\le 0.01\); Productivity Scenario, High Accountability Treatment: mean \(=8.90\) (90% CI [8.30, 9.50]), Low Accountability Treatment: mean \(=3.90\) (90% CI [2.92, 4.88]), mean difference \(=5.00\) (90% CI [3.78, 6.22]), \(p\le 0.01\); pairwise two-tailed t test, within-participants treatment). Hence, the pretest clearly confirmed that participants attribute higher accountability to persons who have disregarded their doctor’s warning (Fig. 7).

Appendix D: Regression analysis

Details

The marginal effects of scenario, supply situation, and accountability displayed in Fig. 4 are based on regression analyses. Table 2 shows the results of a GLS random effects panel regression with robust standard errors on the share of logs distributed to Person A as the endogenous variable. All models include scenario-order and case-order dummies that control for the randomization of the order in which the vignettes were presented to the participants. Model (1) provides an isolated test for scenario differences; model (2) tests for the isolated effect of high accountability; model (3) interacts scenario and accountability treatment; model (4) additionally includes the participants’ socio-demographics and attitudes as covariates; model (5) includes case dummies and all possible interactions between scenario, treatment, and case; model (6) additionally includes the participants’ socio-demographics and attitudes as covariates.
Since models (5) and (6) include 16 additional coefficients and interaction terms, we only report the main effects of scenario, accountability, and their interaction in the table (the full regression output is available from the authors on request). The marginal effects of scenario and accountability treatment (by case) estimated by the “full” model (6) are shown in the left panel of Tables 5 (Productivity Scenario) and 7 (High Accountability Treatment). They are also displayed in the top and bottom left panels of Fig. 4.
Analogously, Table 3 shows the results of a GLS random effects panel regression with robust standard errors on the deviation from the equal split as the endogenous variable. Again, there are six different models where model (6) is the “full” model including all case dummies and interactions, control variables, and scenario-order as well as case-order dummies. The marginal effects of scenario and accountability treatment (by case) estimated by this model are shown in the right panel of Tables 5 (Productivity Scenario) and 7 (High Accountability Treatment). They are also displayed in the top and bottom right panels of Fig. 4 in the main text.
Additionally, Table 6 reports the results of the test on symmetry of the scenarios (H3). The effect of the supply situation on the share of logs and the deviation from the equal split (H4) is tested in Table 1. Table 4 shows the control variables of regression models (4) and (6).

Regression tables

See Tables 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, and 8.
Table 2
Share of logs distributed to person A: regression results
 
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
Scenario
\(-\)0.132\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.120\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.120\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0830\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0829\(^{***}\)
\(\{0=Need,1=Productivity\}\)
(0.00773)
 
(0.0122)
(0.0122)
(0.00968)
(0.00967)
Accountability
\(-\)0.0585\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0473\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0285\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0123
0.00637
\(\{0=low,1=high\}\)
 
(0.00908)
(0.00865)
(0.00872)
(0.00938)
(0.0102)
Accountability \(\times\) scenario
\(-\)0.0224
\(-\)0.0231
\(-\)0.0212\(^{*}\)
\(-\)0.0219\(^{*}\)
   
(0.0156)
(0.0156)
(0.0121)
(0.0122)
Constant
0.555\(^{***}\)
0.513\(^{***}\)
0.579\(^{***}\)
0.526\(^{***}\)
0.543\(^{***}\)
0.491\(^{***}\)
(0.00717)
(0.00931)
(0.00945)
(0.0345)
(0.00859)
(0.0345)
Case dummies and interactions
No
No
No
No
Yes
Yes
Control variables
No
No
No
Yes
No
Yes
Scenario-order and case-order dummies
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
\(\chi ^2\)
328.8\(^{***}\)
56.51\(^{***}\)
357.9\(^{***}\)
731.7\(^{***}\)
740.4\(^{***}\)
1399.3\(^{***}\)
\(R^2\) within
0.358
0.00185
0.360
0.361
0.423
0.423
\(R^2\) between
0.00237
0.178
0.177
0.551
0.177
0.551
\(R^2\) overall
0.257
0.0517
0.308
0.415
0.353
0.460
The table reports the results of a GLS random effects panel regression with robust standard errors. Endogenous variable: share of logs distributed to Person A (\(\text{ logshare}_A\)). First row: coefficients, second row: standard errors in parentheses. Control variables include age, gender, equivalent household net income, accountability judgment, smoker, cardiovascular disease, metabolic disease, importance of need, importance of equity, importance of equality, locus of control, political attitude (see Table 4 in the Appendix). \(N=2000\) (200 participants). Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Table 3
Deviation from the equal split: regression results
 
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
Scenario
0.102\(^{**}\)
0.126\(^{**}\)
0.107\(^{**}\)
0.306\(^{***}\)
0.288\(^{***}\)
\(\{0=Need,1=Productivity\}\)
(0.0467)
 
(0.0545)
(0.0536)
(0.0879)
(0.0868)
Accountability
\(-\)0.273\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.218\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.237\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.125
\(-\)0.145
N: \(\{0=low,1=high\}\)
P: \(\{0=high,1=low\}\)
 
(0.0429)
(0.0433)
(0.0506)
(0.0944)
(0.0985)
Accountability \(\times\) scenario
\(-\)0.0954
\(-\)0.0575
\(-\)0.198\(^{*}\)
\(-\)0.161
   
(0.0711)
(0.0742)
(0.118)
(0.120)
Constant
0.199\(^{***}\)
0.387\(^{***}\)
0.317\(^{***}\)
0.528\(^{***}\)
0.345\(^{***}\)
0.556\(^{***}\)
(0.0376)
(0.0405)
(0.0467)
(0.148)
(0.0771)
(0.154)
Case dummies and interactions
No
No
No
No
Yes
Yes
Control variables
No
No
No
Yes
No
Yes
Scenario-order and case-order dummies
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
\(\chi ^2\)
38.62\(^{***}\)
72.42\(^{***}\)
95.22\(^{***}\)
211.2\(^{***}\)
632.0\(^{***}\)
937.5\(^{***}\)
\(R^2\) within
0.0152
0.0877
0.0945
0.0944
0.170
0.170
\(R^2\) between
0.0564
0.0567
0.0654
0.339
0.0646
0.339
\(R^2\) overall
0.0246
0.0806
0.0878
0.150
0.146
0.209
The table reports the results of a GLS random effects panel regression. Endogenous variable: deviation from the equal split (\(\text{ deviation}_A\)). First row: coefficients, second row: standard errors in parentheses. Control variables include age, gender, equivalent household net income, accountability judgment, smoker, cardiovascular disease, metabolic disease, importance of need, importance of equity, importance of equality, locus of control, political attitude (see Table 4 in the Appendix). All regressions include scenario- and case-order dummies. \(N=2000\) (200 participants). Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Table 4
Control variables
 
\(\text{ logshare}_A\)
\(\text{ deviation}_A\)
(4)
(6)
(4)
(6)
Age
0.000292
0.000290
\(-\)0.00146
\(-\)0.00146
\(\{\sharp years\}\)
(0.000244)
(0.000245)
(0.000937)
(0.000944)
Male
\(-\)0.00506
\(-\)0.00506
\(-\)0.0248
\(-\)0.0248
\(\{0=female,1=male\}\)
(0.00708)
(0.00710)
(0.0317)
(0.0319)
Equiv. household net income
0.00000111\(^{***}\)
0.00000111\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.00000853\(^{**}\)
\(-\)0.00000856\(^{**}\)
\(\{euros\}\)
(0.000000427)
(0.000000426)
(0.00000418)
(0.00000422)
Smoker
0.0224\(^{**}\)
0.0224\(^{**}\)
\(-\)0.0725\(^{*}\)
\(-\)0.0721\(^{*}\)
\(\{0=no,1=yes\}\)
(0.00889)
(0.00893)
(0.0402)
(0.0403)
Cardiovascular disease
0.00332
0.00327
\(-\)0.0737
\(-\)0.0740
\(\{0=no,1=yes\}\)
(0.00940)
(0.00942)
(0.0489)
(0.0490)
Metabolic disease
0.00508
0.00515
0.0559
0.0566
\(\{0=no,1=yes\}\)
(0.0117)
(0.0117)
(0.0502)
(0.0504)
Locus of control
0.000553
0.000554
0.00590
0.00585
\(\{1,\ldots ,7\}\)
(0.00319)
(0.00320)
(0.0180)
(0.0181)
Political attitude
\(-\)0.00464
\(-\)0.00462
0.0300\(^{**}\)
0.0300\(^{**}\)
\(\{1,\ldots ,7\}\)
(0.00314)
(0.00315)
(0.0132)
(0.0133)
Importance need
0.00965\(^{***}\)
0.00964\(^{***}\)
0.00801
0.00805
\(\{1,\ldots ,7\}\)
(0.00207)
(0.00208)
(0.00995)
(0.00998)
Importance equity
\(-\)0.0130\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0130\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.00122
\(-\)0.00126
\(\{1,\ldots ,7\}\)
(0.00240)
(0.00241)
(0.0118)
(0.0119)
Importance equality
0.00913\(^{***}\)
0.00913\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0618\(^{***}\)
\(-\)0.0619\(^{***}\)
\(\{1,\ldots ,7\}\)
(0.00211)
(0.00211)
(0.00953)
(0.00959)
Acc. Judgment
0.00306
0.00312
\(-\)0.00525
\(-\)0.00522
\(\{1,\ldots ,7\}\)
(0.00229)
(0.00234)
(0.0109)
(0.0111)
The table reports the results of a GLS random effects panel regressions with robust standard errors (control variables of models (4) and (6) in Table 2 and in Table 3). First row: coefficients, second row: standard errors in parentheses. Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Table 5
Marginal effect of the productivity scenario
Case
\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A\)
\(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A\)
Low
High
Difference
Low
High
Difference
1
\(-0.083^{***}\)
\(-0.105^{***}\)
\(-0.022^{*}\)
\(0.288^{***}\)
0.127
0.161
(0.010)
(0.007)
(0.012)
(0.087)
(0.100)
(0.120)
2
\(-0.106^{***}\)
\(-0.115^{***}\)
\(-0.010\)
\(-0.272^{***}\)
\(-0.284^{***}\)
\(-0.012\)
(0.010)
(0.009)
(0.014)
(0.066)
(0.078)
(0.101)
3
\(-0.115^{***}\)
\(-0.139^{***}\)
\(-0.024\)
\(0.113^{*}\)
0.052
\(-0.061\)
(0.016)
(0.010)
(0.019)
(0.064)
(0.067)
(0.085)
4
\(-0.132^{***}\)
\(-0.153^{***}\)
\(-0.021\)
\(0.176^{**}\)
\(0.171^{***}\)
\(-0.005\)
(0.018)
(0.016)
(0.024)
(0.070)
(0.061)
(0.088)
5
\(-0.163^{***}\)
\(-0.201^{***}\)
\(-0.038\)
\(0.231^{***}\)
\(0.182^{***}\)
\(-0.049\)
(0.020)
(0.018)
(0.028)
(0.062)
(0.0.58
(0.079)
All
\(-0.120^{***}\)
\(-0.143^{***}\)
\(-.023\)
\(0.107^{**}\)
0.050
0.057
(0.012)
(0.010)
(0.016)
(0.054)
(0.061)
(0.075)
The table reports the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario on the share of logs distributed to Person A (\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A\)) and the deviation from the equal split (\(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A\)). GLS effects panel model estimates are reported in Table 2 (share of logs) and in Table 3 (deviation). \(N=2000\) (200 participants). First row: coefficients, second row: standard errors in parentheses. Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Table 6
Symmetry of the scenarios
Case
Low accountability
High accountability
Need
Productivity
p
Need
Productivity
p
1
0.532
0.450
0.105
0.539
0.434
0.004
(0.008)
(0.007)
(\(=\))
(0.007)
(0.005)
(P)
2
0.581
0.476
0.000
0.565
0.450
0.117
(0.007)
(0.008)
(N)
(0.007)
(0.005)
(\(=\))
3
0.575
0.460
0.017
0.533
0.394
0.000
(0.010)
(0.012)
(N)
(0.007)
(0.008)
(P)
4
0.563
0.431
0.728
0.531
0.378
0.000
(0.011)
(0.014)
(\(=\))
(0.007)
(0.014)
(P)
5
0.584
0.421
0.812
0.524
0.324
0.000
(0.013)
(0.017)
(\(=\))
(0.007)
(0.015)
(P)
All
0.567
0.447
0.219
0.538
0.396
0.000
(0.007)
(0.010)
(\(=\))
(0.005)
(0.007)
(P)
The table reports the share of logs distributed to Person A (\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A^s\)) by scenario and accountability treatment estimated by a GLS random effects panel model (marginal effects). Estimates are reported in Table 2. First row: coefficients, second row: standard errors in parentheses. p gives the significance level of testing symmetry of the scenarios (H3): \(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\Delta \text{ logshare}_A^s\). Here, \(=\) means that the null hypothesis of symmetry cannot be rejected; N (P) means that the equality sign has to be replaced by > (<)
Table 7
Marginal effect of high accountability
Case
\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A\)
\(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A|\)
Need
Productivity
Difference
Need
Productivity
Difference
1
0.006
\(-0.016^{*}\)
\(-0.022^{*}\)
\(-0.145\)
\(-0.305^{***}\)
\(-0.161\)
(0.010)
(0.009)
(0.012)
(0.098)
(0.089)
(0.120)
2
\(-0.016\)
\(-0.026^{***}\)
\(-0.010\)
\(-0.275^{***}\)
\(-0.287^{*}\)
\(-0.012\)
(0.010)
(0.010)
(0.014)
(0.074)
(0.071)
(0.101)
3
\(-0.042^{***}\)
\(-0.066^{***}\)
\(-0.024\)
\(-0.306^{***}\)
\(-0.367^{***}\)
\(-0.061\)
(0.012)
(0.014)
(0.019)
(0.058)
(0.072)
(0.085)
4
\(-0.032^{**}\)
\(-0.053^{***}\)
\(-0.021\)
\(-0.216^{***}\)
\(-0.220^{***}\)
\(-0.005\)
(0.013)
(0.020)
(0.024)
(0.055)
(0.075)
(0.088)
5
\(-0.059^{***}\)
\(-0.097^{***}\)
\(-0.038\)
\(-0.246^{***}\)
\(-0.295^{***}\)
\(-0.049\)
(0.015)
(0.023)
(0.028)
(0.050)
(0.068)
(0.079)
All
\(-0.029^{***}\)
\(-0.052^{***}\)
\(-.023\)
\(-0.238^{***}\)
\(-0.295^{***}\)
\(-0.057\)
(0.009)
(0.013)
(0.016)
(0.051)
(0.064)
(0.075)
The table reports the marginal effects of high accountability on the share of logs distributed to Person A (\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A\)) and the deviation from the equal split (\(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A|\)). GLS effects panel model estimates are reported in Table 2 (share of logs) and in Table 3 (deviation). \(N=2000\) (200 participants). First row: coefficients, second row: standard errors in parentheses. Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Table 8
Case differences
Share of logs distributed to A
Case
Marginal effect of productivity scenario
Low accountability
High accountability
2
3
4
5
2
3
4
5
1
ns
ns
\(^{**}\)
\(^{***}\)
ns
\(^{**}\)
\(^{**}\)
\(^{***}\)
2
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
\(^{***}\)
3
ns
\(^{**}\)
ns
\(^{***}\)
4
ns
\(^{***}\)
Case
Marginal effect of high accountability
Need scenario
Productivity scenario
2
3
4
5
2
3
4
5
1
ns
\(^{***}\)
\(^{**}\)
\(^{***}\)
ns
\(^{***}\)
ns
\(^{***}\)
2
ns
ns
\(^{**}\)
\(^{**}\)
ns
\(^{***}\)
3
ns
ns
ns
\(^{***}\)
4
ns
\(^{***}\)
Deviation from the equal split
Case
Marginal effect of productivity scenario
Low accountability
High accountability
2
3
4
5
2
3
4
5
1
\(^{***}\)
ns
ns
ns
\(^{***}\)
ns
ns
ns
2
\(^{***}\)
\(^{***}\)
\(^{***}\)
\(^{***}\)
\(^{***}\)
\(^{***}\)
3
ns
ns
\(^{**}\)
\(^{**}\)
4
ns
ns
Case
Marginal effect of high accountability
Need scenario
Productivity scenario
2
3
4
5
2
3
4
5
1
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
2
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
ns
3
ns
ns
\(^{**}\)
ns
4
ns
ns
The table shows pairwise comparisons of the marginal effects of the Productivity Scenario (High Accountability Treatment) on the logs distributed to A (deviation from the equal split). \(ns=\)not significant. Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\)). Bonferroni correction for multiple hypotheses testing

Appendix E: Additional tables

See Tables 9, 10, and 11.
Table 9
Breakdown of sample by gender, age, and income
Gender
Age
Income interval\(^\mathrm{a}\)
Group
Share
Group
Share
Group
Share
Female
49.5
18–29
20.5
[0, 1100)
20.0
Male
50.5
30–39
18.5
[1100, 1500)
20.0
40–49
19.0
[1500, 2000)
20.0
50–59
24.0
[2000, 2600)
20.0
60–69
18.0
[2600, \(\infty\))
20.0
Share in percent. \(N=200\)
\(^\mathrm{a}\)Equivalent household net income
Table 10
Share of logs distributed to A: means
Case
Low accountability
High accountability
\(\Delta\)Low
\(logshare_A\)
\(p_A/p\)
\(n_A/n\)
\(logshare_A\)
\(p_A/p\)
\(n_A/n\)
High
Need scenario
  1
0.542
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.6\(^{***}\)
0.531
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.6\(^{***}\)
0.011
(0.007)
(.)
(.)
(0.006)
(.)
(.)
(0.009)
  2
0.591
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.64\(^{***}\)
0.557
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.64\(^{***}\)
0.034\(^{***}\)
(0.007)
(.)
(.)
(0.007)
(.)
(.)
(0.010)
  3
0.584
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.71\(^{***}\)
0.525
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.71\(^{***}\)
0.059\(^{***}\)
(0.010)
(.)
(.)
(0.006)
(.)
(.)
(0.012)
  4
0.572
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.78\(^{***}\)
0.522
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.78\(^{***}\)
0.050\(^{***}\)
(0.012)
(.)
(.)
(0.006)
(.)
(.)
(0.013)
  5
0.594
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.86\(^{***}\)
0.516
0.5\(^{**}\)
0.86\(^{***}\)
0.078\(^{***}\)
(0.014)
(.)
(.)
(0.006)
(.)
(.)
(0.015)
  All
0.577
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.717\(^{***}\)
0.530
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.717\(^{***}\)
0.047\(^{***}\)
(0.005)
(.)
(0.004)
(0.003)
(.)
(0.004)
(0.006)
Productivity scenario
  1
0.459
0.4\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.426
0.4\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.033\(^{***}\)
(0.008)
(.)
(.)
(0.005)
(.)
(.)
(0.009)
  2
0.486
0.36\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{**}\)
0.443
0.36\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.043\(^{***}\)
(0.008)
(.)
(.)
(0.006)
(.)
(.)
(0.010)
  3
0.469
0.29\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.386
0.29\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.083\(^{***}\)
(0.013)
(.)
(.)
(0.010)
(.)
(.)
(0.016)
  4
0.440
0.22\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.370
0.22\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.071\(^{***}\)
(0.015)
(.)
(.)
(0.016)
(.)
(.)
(0.022)
  5
0.431
0.14\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.316
0.14\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.115\(^{***}\)
(0.018)
(.)
(.)
(0.018)
(.)
(.)
(0.025)
  All
0.457
0.283\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.388
0.283\(^{***}\)
0.5\(^{***}\)
0.069\(^{***}\)
(0.006)
(0.004)
(.)
(0.006)
(0.004)
(.)
(0.008)
Mean of \(\text{ logshare}_A\) by accountability treatment and scenario. First row: means; second row: standard errors in parentheses. \(p_A/p\): A’s productivity share. \(n_A/n\): A’s need share. Asterisks denote the significance level of a one-tailed t test: \(p(\text{ logshare}_A>p_A/p)\), \(p(\text{ logshare}_A<n_A/n)\), and \(p(\text{ logshare}_A^{\text{ low }}-\text{ logshare}_A^{\text{ high }}>0)\). Low (High) Accountability Treatment: \(N=91\) (109) observations per case; \(N=455\) (545) observations in total per scenario. Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Table 11
Deviation from the equal split: means
Case
Need scenario
Productivity scenario
Low acc.
High acc.
\(\Delta\)
Low acc.
High acc.
\(\Delta\)
1
0.423
0.309
0.114
0.410
0.745
\(-0.334^{***}\)
(0.072)
(0.062)
(0.095)
(0.077)
(0.051)
(0.092)
2
0.671
0.419
0.252\(^{***}\)
0.106
0.420
\(-0.314^{***}\)
(0.049)
(0.051)
(0.070)
(0.055)
(0.045)
(0.071)
3
0.392
0.116
0.276\(^{***}\)
0.143
0.532
\(-0.389^{***}\)
(0.047)
(0.029)
(0.055)
(0.060)
(0.047)
(0.076)
4
0.260
0.080
0.180\(^{***}\)
0.214
0.469
\(-0.254^{**}\)
(0.042)
(0.022)
(0.047)
(0.055)
(0.057)
(0.079)
5
0.262
0.045
0.217\(^{***}\)
0.193
0.514
\(-0.321^{***}\)
(0.039)
(0.018)
(0.043)
(0.052)
(0.049)
(0.071)
All
0.402
0.194
0.208\(^{***}\)
0.213
0.536
\(-0.323^{***}\)
(0.024)
(0.019)
(0.030)
(0.027)
(0.023)
(0.035)
Mean of \(\text{ deviation}_A\) by accountability treatment and scenario. First row: means; second row: standard errors in parentheses. \(N=91\) (109) per case in Low (High) Accountability Treatment; total cases: \(N=455\) (545). Asterisks denote the significance level of a one-tailed t test. Significance levels: \(^{*}(p<0.10\)), \(^{**}(p<0.05\)), \(^{***}(p<0.01\))
Literature
go back to reference Adams S (1965) Inequity in social exchange. Adv Exp Soc Psychol 2:267–299CrossRef Adams S (1965) Inequity in social exchange. Adv Exp Soc Psychol 2:267–299CrossRef
go back to reference Ahlert M, Funke K, Schwettmann L (2012) Thresholds, productivity, and context. An experimental study on determinants of distributive behaviour. Soc Choice Welf 40(4):957–984CrossRef Ahlert M, Funke K, Schwettmann L (2012) Thresholds, productivity, and context. An experimental study on determinants of distributive behaviour. Soc Choice Welf 40(4):957–984CrossRef
go back to reference Amiel Y, Cowell F (1999) Thinking about inequality. Personal judgment and income distributions. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRef Amiel Y, Cowell F (1999) Thinking about inequality. Personal judgment and income distributions. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRef
go back to reference Andreoni J, Bernheim BD (2009) Social image and the 50–50 norm. A theoretical and experimental analysis of audience effects. Econometrica 77(5):1607–1636CrossRef Andreoni J, Bernheim BD (2009) Social image and the 50–50 norm. A theoretical and experimental analysis of audience effects. Econometrica 77(5):1607–1636CrossRef
go back to reference Andreoni J, Miller J (2002) Giving according to GARP. An experimental test of the consistency of preferences for altruism. Econometrica 70(2):737–753CrossRef Andreoni J, Miller J (2002) Giving according to GARP. An experimental test of the consistency of preferences for altruism. Econometrica 70(2):737–753CrossRef
go back to reference Annas G (1985) The prostitute, the playboy, and the poet. Rationing schemes for organ transplantation. Am J Public Health 75(2):187–189CrossRef Annas G (1985) The prostitute, the playboy, and the poet. Rationing schemes for organ transplantation. Am J Public Health 75(2):187–189CrossRef
go back to reference Aristotle (2009) Nicomachean ethics. Oxford University Press, New York Aristotle (2009) Nicomachean ethics. Oxford University Press, New York
go back to reference Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) (2019) Philosophie zwischen Sein und Sollen. Normative Theorie und empirische Forschung im Spannungsfeld. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) (2019) Philosophie zwischen Sein und Sollen. Normative Theorie und empirische Forschung im Spannungsfeld. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin
go back to reference Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) (2020) Empirical research and normative theory. Transdisciplinary perspectives on two methodical traditions between separation and interdependence. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) (2020) Empirical research and normative theory. Transdisciplinary perspectives on two methodical traditions between separation and interdependence. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin
go back to reference Betancourt H (1990) An attribution-empathy model of helping behavior. Behavioral intentions and judgments of help-giving. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 16(3):573–591CrossRef Betancourt H (1990) An attribution-empathy model of helping behavior. Behavioral intentions and judgments of help-giving. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 16(3):573–591CrossRef
go back to reference Boarini R, d’Ercole M (2006) Measures of material deprivation in OECD countries. OECD Social, Employment and Migration Working Papers 37, Organisation for Economic Co-Operation and Development, Paris Boarini R, d’Ercole M (2006) Measures of material deprivation in OECD countries. OECD Social, Employment and Migration Working Papers 37, Organisation for Economic Co-Operation and Development, Paris
go back to reference Buitrago G, Güth W, Levati MV (2009) On the relation between impulses to help and causes of neediness. An experimental study. J Socio-Econ 38(1):80–88CrossRef Buitrago G, Güth W, Levati MV (2009) On the relation between impulses to help and causes of neediness. An experimental study. J Socio-Econ 38(1):80–88CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Norheim OF (2005) Responsibility in health care. A liberal egalitarian approach. J Med Ethics 31(8):476–480CrossRef Cappelen A, Norheim OF (2005) Responsibility in health care. A liberal egalitarian approach. J Med Ethics 31(8):476–480CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Norheim OF (2006) Responsibility, fairness and rationing in health care. Health Policy 76(3):312–319CrossRef Cappelen A, Norheim OF (2006) Responsibility, fairness and rationing in health care. Health Policy 76(3):312–319CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Tungodden B (2006) Relocating the responsibility cut. Should more responsibility imply less redistribution? Polit Philos Econ 5(3):353–362CrossRef Cappelen A, Tungodden B (2006) Relocating the responsibility cut. Should more responsibility imply less redistribution? Polit Philos Econ 5(3):353–362CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Norheim OF, Tungodden B (2010) Disability compensation and responsibility. Polit Philos Econ 9(4):411–427CrossRef Cappelen A, Norheim OF, Tungodden B (2010) Disability compensation and responsibility. Polit Philos Econ 9(4):411–427CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Konow J, Sørensen E, Tungodden B (2013) Just luck. An experimental study of risk-taking and fairness. Am Econ Rev 103(4):1398–1413CrossRef Cappelen A, Konow J, Sørensen E, Tungodden B (2013) Just luck. An experimental study of risk-taking and fairness. Am Econ Rev 103(4):1398–1413CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Moene K, Sørensen E, Tungodden B (2013) Needs versus entitlements. An international fairness experiment. J Eur Econ Assoc 11(3):574–598CrossRef Cappelen A, Moene K, Sørensen E, Tungodden B (2013) Needs versus entitlements. An international fairness experiment. J Eur Econ Assoc 11(3):574–598CrossRef
go back to reference Cappelen A, Moene K, Sørensen E, Tungodden B (2008) Rich meet poor. An international fairness experiment. Discussion Paper 10, Chr. Michelsen Institute Cappelen A, Moene K, Sørensen E, Tungodden B (2008) Rich meet poor. An international fairness experiment. Discussion Paper 10, Chr. Michelsen Institute
go back to reference Chen D, Schonger M, Wickens C (2016) oTree. An open-source platform for laboratory, online, and field experiments. J Behav Exp Financ 9:88–97CrossRef Chen D, Schonger M, Wickens C (2016) oTree. An open-source platform for laboratory, online, and field experiments. J Behav Exp Financ 9:88–97CrossRef
go back to reference Cohen G (2011) On the currency of egalitarian justice, and other essays in political philosophy. Princeton University Press, PrincetonCrossRef Cohen G (2011) On the currency of egalitarian justice, and other essays in political philosophy. Princeton University Press, PrincetonCrossRef
go back to reference Dawid H, Dermietzel J (2006) How robust is the equal split norm? Responsive strategies, selection mechanisms and the need for economic interpretation of simulation parameters. Comput Econ 28(4):371–397CrossRef Dawid H, Dermietzel J (2006) How robust is the equal split norm? Responsive strategies, selection mechanisms and the need for economic interpretation of simulation parameters. Comput Econ 28(4):371–397CrossRef
go back to reference Dean H (2002) Welfare rights and social policy. Pearson Education, Harlow Dean H (2002) Welfare rights and social policy. Pearson Education, Harlow
go back to reference Dean H (2013) The translation of needs into rights. Reconceptualising social citizenship as a global phenomenon. Int J Soc Welf 22(1):32–49 Dean H (2013) The translation of needs into rights. Reconceptualising social citizenship as a global phenomenon. Int J Soc Welf 22(1):32–49
go back to reference Deutsch M (1975) Equity, equality, and need. What determines which value will be used as the basis of distributive justice? J Soc Issues 31(3):137–149CrossRef Deutsch M (1975) Equity, equality, and need. What determines which value will be used as the basis of distributive justice? J Soc Issues 31(3):137–149CrossRef
go back to reference Deutsch M (1985) Distributive justice. A social-psychological perspective. Yale University Press, New Haven Deutsch M (1985) Distributive justice. A social-psychological perspective. Yale University Press, New Haven
go back to reference Diederich A (2020) Identifying needs. The psychological perspective. In: Traub S, Kittel B (eds) Need-based distributive justice. An interdisciplinary perspective. Springer Nature, Cham, pp 59–89CrossRef Diederich A (2020) Identifying needs. The psychological perspective. In: Traub S, Kittel B (eds) Need-based distributive justice. An interdisciplinary perspective. Springer Nature, Cham, pp 59–89CrossRef
go back to reference Diederich A, Schreier M (2010) Zur Akzeptanz von Eigenverantwortung als Posteriorisierungskriterium. Eine empirische Untersuchung. Bundesgesundheitsblatt 53(9):896–902 Diederich A, Schreier M (2010) Zur Akzeptanz von Eigenverantwortung als Posteriorisierungskriterium. Eine empirische Untersuchung. Bundesgesundheitsblatt 53(9):896–902
go back to reference Diederich A, Schwettmann L, Winkelhage J (2014) Does lifestyle matter when deciding on copayment for health care? A survey of the general public. J Public Health 22(5):443–453CrossRef Diederich A, Schwettmann L, Winkelhage J (2014) Does lifestyle matter when deciding on copayment for health care? A survey of the general public. J Public Health 22(5):443–453CrossRef
go back to reference Doyal L, Gough I (1984) A theory of human needs. Crit Soc Policy 4(10):6–38CrossRef Doyal L, Gough I (1984) A theory of human needs. Crit Soc Policy 4(10):6–38CrossRef
go back to reference Dworkin R (1981) What is equality? Part 2. Equality of resources. Philos Public Aff 10(4):283–345 Dworkin R (1981) What is equality? Part 2. Equality of resources. Philos Public Aff 10(4):283–345
go back to reference Esping-Andersen G (1990) The three worlds of welfare capitalism. Princeton University Press, Princeton Esping-Andersen G (1990) The three worlds of welfare capitalism. Princeton University Press, Princeton
go back to reference Farwell L, Weiner B (1996) Self-perception of fairness in individual and group contexts. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 22(9):868–881CrossRef Farwell L, Weiner B (1996) Self-perception of fairness in individual and group contexts. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 22(9):868–881CrossRef
go back to reference Fisman R, Kariv S, Markovits D (2007) Individual preferences for giving. Am Econ Rev 97(5):1858–1876CrossRef Fisman R, Kariv S, Markovits D (2007) Individual preferences for giving. Am Econ Rev 97(5):1858–1876CrossRef
go back to reference Fong C (2001) Social preferences, self-interest, and the demand for redistribution. J Public Econ 82(2):225–246CrossRef Fong C (2001) Social preferences, self-interest, and the demand for redistribution. J Public Econ 82(2):225–246CrossRef
go back to reference Fowler F, Berwick D, Roman A, Massagli M (1994) Measuring public priorities for insurable health care. Med Care 32(6):625–639CrossRef Fowler F, Berwick D, Roman A, Massagli M (1994) Measuring public priorities for insurable health care. Med Care 32(6):625–639CrossRef
go back to reference Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J (1990) Choosing justice in experimental democracies with production. Am Polit Sci Rev 84(2):461–477CrossRef Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J (1990) Choosing justice in experimental democracies with production. Am Polit Sci Rev 84(2):461–477CrossRef
go back to reference Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J (1992) Choosing justice. An experimental approach to ethical theory. University of California Press, BerkeleyCrossRef Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J (1992) Choosing justice. An experimental approach to ethical theory. University of California Press, BerkeleyCrossRef
go back to reference Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J, Eavey C (1987) Choices of principles of distributive justice in experimental groups. Am J Polit Sci 31(3):606–636CrossRef Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J, Eavey C (1987) Choices of principles of distributive justice in experimental groups. Am J Polit Sci 31(3):606–636CrossRef
go back to reference Frohlich N, Oppenheimer JA, Eavey CL (1987) Laboratory results on Rawls’s distributive justice. Br J Polit Sci 17(1):1–21CrossRef Frohlich N, Oppenheimer JA, Eavey CL (1987) Laboratory results on Rawls’s distributive justice. Br J Polit Sci 17(1):1–21CrossRef
go back to reference Gaertner W, Schokkaert E (2012) Empirical social choice. Questionnaire-experimental studies on distributive justice. Cambridge University Press, New York Gaertner W, Schokkaert E (2012) Empirical social choice. Questionnaire-experimental studies on distributive justice. Cambridge University Press, New York
go back to reference Gaertner W, Schwettmann L (2007) Equity, responsibility and the cultural dimension. Economica 74(296):627–649CrossRef Gaertner W, Schwettmann L (2007) Equity, responsibility and the cultural dimension. Economica 74(296):627–649CrossRef
go back to reference Gasper D (2005) Needs and human rights. In: Smith R, van den Anker C (eds) The essentials of human rights. Hodder & Stoughton, London, pp 269–272 Gasper D (2005) Needs and human rights. In: Smith R, van den Anker C (eds) The essentials of human rights. Hodder & Stoughton, London, pp 269–272
go back to reference Herreiner DK, Puppe C (2010) Inequality aversion and efficiency with ordinal and cardinal social preferences. An experimental study. J Econ Behav Organ 76(2):238–253CrossRef Herreiner DK, Puppe C (2010) Inequality aversion and efficiency with ordinal and cardinal social preferences. An experimental study. J Econ Behav Organ 76(2):238–253CrossRef
go back to reference Jasso G (1978) On the justice of earnings. A new specification of the justice evaluation function. Am J Sociol 83(6):1398–1419CrossRef Jasso G (1978) On the justice of earnings. A new specification of the justice evaluation function. Am J Sociol 83(6):1398–1419CrossRef
go back to reference Jasso G, Törnblom KY, Sabbagh C (2016) Distributive justice. In: Sabbagh C, Schmitt M (eds) Handbook of social justice theory and research. Springer, New York, pp 201–218CrossRef Jasso G, Törnblom KY, Sabbagh C (2016) Distributive justice. In: Sabbagh C, Schmitt M (eds) Handbook of social justice theory and research. Springer, New York, pp 201–218CrossRef
go back to reference Karasawa K (1991) The effects of onset and offset responsibility on affects and helping judgments. J Appl Soc Psychol 21(6):482–499CrossRef Karasawa K (1991) The effects of onset and offset responsibility on affects and helping judgments. J Appl Soc Psychol 21(6):482–499CrossRef
go back to reference Knight C (2009) Luck egalitarianism. Equality, responsibility, and justice. Edinburgh University Press, EdinburghCrossRef Knight C (2009) Luck egalitarianism. Equality, responsibility, and justice. Edinburgh University Press, EdinburghCrossRef
go back to reference Konow J (1996) A positive theory of economic fairness. J Econ Behav Organ 31(1):13–35CrossRef Konow J (1996) A positive theory of economic fairness. J Econ Behav Organ 31(1):13–35CrossRef
go back to reference Konow J (2001) Fair and square. The four sides of distributive justice. J Econ Behav Organ 46(2):137–164CrossRef Konow J (2001) Fair and square. The four sides of distributive justice. J Econ Behav Organ 46(2):137–164CrossRef
go back to reference Konow J (2003) Which is the fairest one of all? A positive analysis of justice theories. J Econ Lit 41(4):1188–1239CrossRef Konow J (2003) Which is the fairest one of all? A positive analysis of justice theories. J Econ Lit 41(4):1188–1239CrossRef
go back to reference Konow J (2005) Blind spots. The effects of information and stakes on fairness bias and dispersion. Soc Justice Res 18(4):349–390CrossRef Konow J (2005) Blind spots. The effects of information and stakes on fairness bias and dispersion. Soc Justice Res 18(4):349–390CrossRef
go back to reference Konow J (2009) Is fairness in the eye of the beholder? An impartial spectator analysis of justice. Soc Choice Welf 33(1):101–127CrossRef Konow J (2009) Is fairness in the eye of the beholder? An impartial spectator analysis of justice. Soc Choice Welf 33(1):101–127CrossRef
go back to reference Konow J, Schwettmann L (2016) The economics of justice. In: Sabbagh C, Schmitt M (eds) Handbook of social justice theory and research. Springer, New York, pp 83–106CrossRef Konow J, Schwettmann L (2016) The economics of justice. In: Sabbagh C, Schmitt M (eds) Handbook of social justice theory and research. Springer, New York, pp 83–106CrossRef
go back to reference Lamm H, Schwinger T (1980) Norms concerning distributive justice. Are needs taken into consideration in allocation decisions? Soc Psychol Q 43(4):425–429CrossRef Lamm H, Schwinger T (1980) Norms concerning distributive justice. Are needs taken into consideration in allocation decisions? Soc Psychol Q 43(4):425–429CrossRef
go back to reference Lerner M (1977) The justice motive. Some hypotheses as to its origins and forms. J Pers 45(1):1–52CrossRef Lerner M (1977) The justice motive. Some hypotheses as to its origins and forms. J Pers 45(1):1–52CrossRef
go back to reference Leventhal G (1976) The distribution of rewards and resources in groups and organizations. Adv Exp Soc Psychol 9:91–131CrossRef Leventhal G (1976) The distribution of rewards and resources in groups and organizations. Adv Exp Soc Psychol 9:91–131CrossRef
go back to reference Liebig S, Sauer C (2016) Sociology of justice. In: Sabbagh C, Schmitt M (eds) Handbook of social justice theory and research. Springer, New York, pp 37–59CrossRef Liebig S, Sauer C (2016) Sociology of justice. In: Sabbagh C, Schmitt M (eds) Handbook of social justice theory and research. Springer, New York, pp 37–59CrossRef
go back to reference Meyer F (2019) Individual motives for (re-)distribution. PhD thesis, Maastricht University, Netherlands Meyer F (2019) Individual motives for (re-)distribution. PhD thesis, Maastricht University, Netherlands
go back to reference Michelbach P, Scott J, Matland R, Bornstein B (2003) Doing Rawls justice. An experimental study of income distribution norms. Am J Polit Sci 47(3):523–539CrossRef Michelbach P, Scott J, Matland R, Bornstein B (2003) Doing Rawls justice. An experimental study of income distribution norms. Am J Polit Sci 47(3):523–539CrossRef
go back to reference Miller D (1999) Principles of social justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Miller D (1999) Principles of social justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
go back to reference Miller D (2020) Needs-based justice. Theory and evidence. In: Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) Empirical research and normative theory. Transdisciplinary perspectives on two methodical traditions between separation and interdependence. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 271–292 Miller D (2020) Needs-based justice. Theory and evidence. In: Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) Empirical research and normative theory. Transdisciplinary perspectives on two methodical traditions between separation and interdependence. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 271–292
go back to reference Mitchell G, Tetlock P, Mellers B, Ordóñez L (1993) Judgments of social justice. Compromises between equality and efficiency. J Pers Soc Psychol 65(4):629–639CrossRef Mitchell G, Tetlock P, Mellers B, Ordóñez L (1993) Judgments of social justice. Compromises between equality and efficiency. J Pers Soc Psychol 65(4):629–639CrossRef
go back to reference Murphy-Berman V, Berman J, Singh P, Pachauri A, Kumar P (1984) Factors affecting allocation to needy and meritorious recipients. A cross-cultural comparison. J Pers Soc Psychol 46(6):1267–1272CrossRef Murphy-Berman V, Berman J, Singh P, Pachauri A, Kumar P (1984) Factors affecting allocation to needy and meritorious recipients. A cross-cultural comparison. J Pers Soc Psychol 46(6):1267–1272CrossRef
go back to reference Neuberger J, Adams D, MacMaster P, Maidment A, Speed M (1998) Assessing priorities for allocation of donor liver grafts. Survey of public and clinicians. BMJ 317(7152):172–175CrossRef Neuberger J, Adams D, MacMaster P, Maidment A, Speed M (1998) Assessing priorities for allocation of donor liver grafts. Survey of public and clinicians. BMJ 317(7152):172–175CrossRef
go back to reference Nicklisch A, Paetzel F (2020) Need-based justice and distribution procedures. The perspective of economics. In: Traub S, Kittel B (eds) Need-based distributive justice. An interdisciplinary perspective. Springer Nature, Berlin, pp 161–189CrossRef Nicklisch A, Paetzel F (2020) Need-based justice and distribution procedures. The perspective of economics. In: Traub S, Kittel B (eds) Need-based distributive justice. An interdisciplinary perspective. Springer Nature, Berlin, pp 161–189CrossRef
go back to reference Nussbaum M (1992) Human functioning and social justice. In defense of Aristotelian essentialism. Polit Theory 20(2):202–246CrossRef Nussbaum M (1992) Human functioning and social justice. In defense of Aristotelian essentialism. Polit Theory 20(2):202–246CrossRef
go back to reference Phares J, Lamiell J (1975) Internal-external control, interpersonal judgments of others in need, and attribution of responsibility. J Pers 43(1):23–38CrossRef Phares J, Lamiell J (1975) Internal-external control, interpersonal judgments of others in need, and attribution of responsibility. J Pers 43(1):23–38CrossRef
go back to reference Plant R, Taylor-Gooby P, Lesser A (2009) Political philosophy and social welfare. Essays on the normative basis of welfare provisions. Routledge, New York Plant R, Taylor-Gooby P, Lesser A (2009) Political philosophy and social welfare. Essays on the normative basis of welfare provisions. Routledge, New York
go back to reference Renzo M (2015) Human needs, human rights. In: Cruft R, Liao M, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 570–587CrossRef Renzo M (2015) Human needs, human rights. In: Cruft R, Liao M, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 570–587CrossRef
go back to reference Schokkaert EM (1999) Tout-le-monde est ‘post-welfariste’. Opinions sur la justice redistributive. Revue économique 50(4):811–831 Schokkaert EM (1999) Tout-le-monde est ‘post-welfariste’. Opinions sur la justice redistributive. Revue économique 50(4):811–831
go back to reference Schwettmann L (2009) Trading off competing allocation principles. Theoretical approaches and empirical investigations. Peter Lang, Frankfurt am Main Schwettmann L (2009) Trading off competing allocation principles. Theoretical approaches and empirical investigations. Peter Lang, Frankfurt am Main
go back to reference Schwettmann L (2012) Competing allocation principles. Time for compromise? Theor Decis 73(3):357–380CrossRef Schwettmann L (2012) Competing allocation principles. Time for compromise? Theor Decis 73(3):357–380CrossRef
go back to reference Schwettmann L (2020) A simple vote won’t do it. Empirical social choice and the fair allocation of health care resources. In: Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) Empirical research and normative theory. Transdisciplinary perspectives on two methodical traditions between separation and interdependence. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 293–314 Schwettmann L (2020) A simple vote won’t do it. Empirical social choice and the fair allocation of health care resources. In: Bauer AM, Meyerhuber MI (eds) Empirical research and normative theory. Transdisciplinary perspectives on two methodical traditions between separation and interdependence. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 293–314
go back to reference Scott J, Bornstein B (2009) What’s fair in foul weather and fair? Distributive justice across different allocation contexts and goods. J Polit 71(3):831–846CrossRef Scott J, Bornstein B (2009) What’s fair in foul weather and fair? Distributive justice across different allocation contexts and goods. J Polit 71(3):831–846CrossRef
go back to reference Scott J, Matland R, Michelbach P, Bornstein B (2001) Just deserts. An experimental study of distributive justice norms. Am J Polit Sci 45(4):749–767CrossRef Scott J, Matland R, Michelbach P, Bornstein B (2001) Just deserts. An experimental study of distributive justice norms. Am J Polit Sci 45(4):749–767CrossRef
go back to reference Siebel M, Schramme T (2020) Need-based justice from the perspective of philosophy. In: Traub S, Kittel B (eds) Need-based distributive justice. An interdisciplinary perspective. Springer, Cham, pp 21–58CrossRef Siebel M, Schramme T (2020) Need-based justice from the perspective of philosophy. In: Traub S, Kittel B (eds) Need-based distributive justice. An interdisciplinary perspective. Springer, Cham, pp 21–58CrossRef
go back to reference Skitka L, Tetlock P (1992) Allocating scarce resources. A contingency model of distributive justice. J Exp Soc Psychol 28(6):491–522CrossRef Skitka L, Tetlock P (1992) Allocating scarce resources. A contingency model of distributive justice. J Exp Soc Psychol 28(6):491–522CrossRef
go back to reference Skitka L, Tetlock P (1993) Of ants and grasshoppers. The political psychology of allocating public assistance. In: Mellers B, Baron J (eds) Psychological perspectives on justice. Theory and applications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 205–233CrossRef Skitka L, Tetlock P (1993) Of ants and grasshoppers. The political psychology of allocating public assistance. In: Mellers B, Baron J (eds) Psychological perspectives on justice. Theory and applications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 205–233CrossRef
go back to reference Skitka L, Tetlock P (1993) Providing public assistance. Cognitive and motivational processes underlying liberal and conservative policy preferences. J Pers Soc Psychol 65(6):1205–1223CrossRef Skitka L, Tetlock P (1993) Providing public assistance. Cognitive and motivational processes underlying liberal and conservative policy preferences. J Pers Soc Psychol 65(6):1205–1223CrossRef
go back to reference Stanton J (1999) The cost of living. Kidney dialysis, rationing and health economics in Britain, 1965–1996. Soc Sci Med 49(9):1169–1182CrossRef Stanton J (1999) The cost of living. Kidney dialysis, rationing and health economics in Britain, 1965–1996. Soc Sci Med 49(9):1169–1182CrossRef
go back to reference Tan KC (2012) Justice, institutions, and luck. The site, ground, and scope of equality. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRef Tan KC (2012) Justice, institutions, and luck. The site, ground, and scope of equality. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRef
go back to reference Temkin L (1993) Inequality. Oxford University Press, New York Temkin L (1993) Inequality. Oxford University Press, New York
go back to reference Traub S, Seid C, Schmidt U, Levati M (2005) Friedman, Harsanyi, Rawls, Boulding–or somebody else? An experimental investigation of distributive justice. Soc Choice Welf 24(2):283–309CrossRef Traub S, Seid C, Schmidt U, Levati M (2005) Friedman, Harsanyi, Rawls, Boulding–or somebody else? An experimental investigation of distributive justice. Soc Choice Welf 24(2):283–309CrossRef
go back to reference Trueblood J (2015) Reference point effects in riskless choice without loss aversion. Decision 2(1):13–26CrossRef Trueblood J (2015) Reference point effects in riskless choice without loss aversion. Decision 2(1):13–26CrossRef
go back to reference Turner DePalma M, Madey S, Tillman T, Wheeler J (1999) Perceived patient responsibility and belief in a just world affect helping. Basic Appl Soc Psychol 21(2):131–137CrossRef Turner DePalma M, Madey S, Tillman T, Wheeler J (1999) Perceived patient responsibility and belief in a just world affect helping. Basic Appl Soc Psychol 21(2):131–137CrossRef
go back to reference Tversky A, Kahneman D (1991) Loss aversion in riskless choice. A reference-dependent model. Q J Econ 106(4):1039–1061CrossRef Tversky A, Kahneman D (1991) Loss aversion in riskless choice. A reference-dependent model. Q J Econ 106(4):1039–1061CrossRef
go back to reference Ubel P, Jepson C, Baron J, Mohr T, McMorrow S, Asch D (2001) Allocation of transplantable organs. Do people want to punish patients for causing their illness? Liver Transpl 7(7):600–607CrossRef Ubel P, Jepson C, Baron J, Mohr T, McMorrow S, Asch D (2001) Allocation of transplantable organs. Do people want to punish patients for causing their illness? Liver Transpl 7(7):600–607CrossRef
go back to reference Wagstaff G (1994) Equity, equality, and need. Three principles of justice or one? An analysis of “equity as desert’’. Curr Psychol 13(2):138–152CrossRef Wagstaff G (1994) Equity, equality, and need. Three principles of justice or one? An analysis of “equity as desert’’. Curr Psychol 13(2):138–152CrossRef
go back to reference Weale A (1984) Political theory and social policy. Macmillan, London Weale A (1984) Political theory and social policy. Macmillan, London
go back to reference Weiner B (1993) On sin versus sickness. A theory of perceived responsibility and social motivation. Am Psychol 48(9):957–965CrossRef Weiner B (1993) On sin versus sickness. A theory of perceived responsibility and social motivation. Am Psychol 48(9):957–965CrossRef
go back to reference Weiner B, Kukla A (1970) An attributional analysis of achievement motivation. J Pers Soc Psychol 15(1):1–20CrossRef Weiner B, Kukla A (1970) An attributional analysis of achievement motivation. J Pers Soc Psychol 15(1):1–20CrossRef
go back to reference Weiß AR, Bauer AM, Traub S (2017) Needs as reference points. When marginal gains to the poor do not matter. FOR 2104 Discussion Papers 13, Helmut Schmidt University, Hamburg Weiß AR, Bauer AM, Traub S (2017) Needs as reference points. When marginal gains to the poor do not matter. FOR 2104 Discussion Papers 13, Helmut Schmidt University, Hamburg
go back to reference Yaari M, Bar-Hillel M (1984) On dividing justly. Soc Choice Welf 1(1):1–24CrossRef Yaari M, Bar-Hillel M (1984) On dividing justly. Soc Choice Welf 1(1):1–24CrossRef
go back to reference Yamauchi H, Lee K (1999) An attribution-emotion model of helping behavior. Psychol Rep 84(3):1073–1074CrossRef Yamauchi H, Lee K (1999) An attribution-emotion model of helping behavior. Psychol Rep 84(3):1073–1074CrossRef
go back to reference Young HP (1994) Equity. Theory and practice. Princeton University Press, Princeton Young HP (1994) Equity. Theory and practice. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Metadata
Title
Need, equity, and accountability
Evidence on third-party distribution decisions from a vignette study
Authors
Alexander Max Bauer
Frauke Meyer
Jan Romann
Mark Siebel
Stefan Traub
Publication date
17-05-2022
Publisher
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Published in
Social Choice and Welfare / Issue 4/2022
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Electronic ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-022-01410-w

Other articles of this Issue 4/2022

Social Choice and Welfare 4/2022 Go to the issue