Skip to main content
Top
Published in:
Cover of the book

2020 | OriginalPaper | Chapter

Reclaiming Democratic Classical Liberalism

Author : David P. Ellerman

Published in: Reclaiming Liberalism

Publisher: Springer International Publishing

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Classical liberalism is skeptical about governmental organizations “doing good” for people. Instead governments should create the conditions so that people individually (Adam Smith) and in associations (Tocqueville) are empowered to do good for themselves. The market implications of classical liberalism are well known, but the implications for organizations are controversial. We will take James Buchanan as our guide (with assists from Mill and Dewey). Unpacking the implications of classical liberalism for the “science of associations” (Tocqueville) requires a tour through the intellectual history of the voluntary slavery contract and the voluntary non-democratic constitution. The argument concludes that the classical liberal endorsement of sovereign individuals acting in the marketplace generalizes to the joint action of individuals as the principals in their own organizations and associations.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
The phrase “external organization” does not apply to associations where people join together to apply their collective efficacy to address some problems of their own; it applies to organizations, particularly those with a paid staff, tasked to help others. The aim of a helping agency should be to do itself out of a job—which is rather difficult for a professionally staffed organization of any type. See Ellerman (2005) for a development of this theme along with a philosophical analysis of why it is so difficult for such external helping organizations to actually “help people help themselves.”
 
2
See Laslett (1960), notes on §24, pp. 325–26.
 
3
Locke, Montesquieu, and Blackstone are not arbitrary choices. When discussing Adam Smith’s classical liberalism, Frank Knight noted: “Interestingly enough, the political and legal theory had been stated in a series of classics, well in advance of the formulation of the economic theory by Smith. The leading names are, of course, Locke, Montesquieu, and Blackstone” (Knight 1947, p. 27, fn. 4).
 
4
For more of this development, see Ellerman (1992 or 2010).
 
5
It is a re-validation since in the decade prior to the Civil War, there was explicit legislation in six states “to permit a free Negro to become a slave voluntarily” (Gray 1958, p. 527; quoted in Philmore 1982, p. 47). For instance in Louisiana, legislation was passed in 1859 “which would enable free persons of color to voluntarily select masters and become slaves for life” (Sterkx 1972, p. 149).
 
6
David Boaz (2011) reports that Tom Palmer said that David Schmidtz said at a Cato Institute forum in 2002 that:
Nozick told him that his alleged “apostasy” was mainly about rejecting the idea that to have a right is necessarily to have the right to alienate it, a thesis that he had reconsidered, on the basis of which reconsideration he concluded that some rights had to be inalienable. That represents, not a movement away from libertarianism, but a shift toward the mainstream of libertarian thought.
In his own book on libertarian theory, Palmer traces the “mainstream of libertarian thought” (2009, p. 457) about inalienable rights back to Locke’s treatment.
 
7
See, for example, Genovese (1971), Wish (1960), or Fitzhugh (1960).
 
8
For a more complete story, see Philmore (1982) or Ellerman (2010).
 
9
This may seem an unusual use of “rent” but “hiring a car” in the U. K. and “renting a car” in the U.S. are the same thing. As Paul Samuelson (1915–2009) goes on to explain:
One can even say that wages are the rentals paid for the use of a man’s personal services for a day or a week or a year. This may seem a strange use of terms, but on second thought, one recognizes that every agreement to hire labor is really for some limited period of time. By outright purchase, you might avoid ever renting any kind of land. But in our society, labor is one of the few productive factors that cannot legally be bought outright. Labor can only be rented, and the wage rate is really a rental (1976, p. 569).
 
10
Institutes, Lib. I, Tit. II, 6; Quoted in: Corwin (1955, p. 4).
 
11
Often the liberal literature just fudges or ignores the alienation-versus-delegation distinction by describing either type of contract as “giving up rights” to the government or as establishing “hierarchy.”
 
12
Again, this follows the intellectual pattern set by Locke who had no genuine inalienable rights theory to counter Hobbes so he ignored Hobbes and took Robert Filmer (1588–1653) as his foil since Filmer’s patriarchal theory (1680) did not require the consent of the governed anymore that the father’s governance over his children requires the consent of the children.
 
13
This phrase was used without apparent irony in an earlier version of the free cities website. In the current version of the startup cities site, the phrase is “democratizing access to law and governance.” Even though the subjects have no vote, the startup cities nevertheless have “democratic accountability by giving people the ability to raise their voice through the power of exit.”
 
14
See also: http://​bleedingheartlib​ertarians.​com/​2014/​03/​vote-markets/​. As James Tobin grudgingly noted: “Any good second year graduate student in economics could write a short examination paper proving that voluntary transactions in votes would increase the welfare of the sellers as well as the buyers” (Tobin 1970, p. 269; quoted in: Ellerman 1992, p. 100).
 
15
This has generated a minor industry of thinkers who develop ad hoc arguments against the perpetual service contract (e.g., the rule against perpetuities supposedly rules out all “till death do us part” contracts) but not against the time-limited person rental contract. These arguments are dealt with from a Nozickian perspective by J. Philmore who concludes with what libertarians would take as a reductio ad absurdum: “Any thorough and decisive critique of voluntary slavery or constitutional non-democratic government would carry over to the employment contract—which is the voluntary contractual basis for the free market free enterprise system” (1982, p. 55).
 
16
The fact that the inalienability of conscience was rooted in the aspects of personhood that do not change with consent or contract was expressed with great clarity by the New Light minister Elisha Williams in 1744:
No action is a religious action without understanding and choice in the agent. Whence it follows, the rights of conscience are sacred and equal in all, and strictly speaking unalienable. This right of judging every one for himself in matters of religion result from the nature of man, and is so inseperably connected therewith, that a man can no more part with it than he can with his power of thinking: and it is equally reasonable for him to attempt to strip himself of the power of reasoning, as to attempt the vesting of another with this right. And whoever invades this right of another, be he pope or Caesar, may with equal reason assume the other’s power of thinking, and so level him with the brutal creation. A man may alienate some branches of his property and give up his right in them to others; but he cannot transfer the right of conscience, unless he could destroy his rational and moral powers (Williams 1998, p. 62).
See also Smith (2013, pp. 88–94) on inalienability which includes references to Williams.
 
17
These and related “forgotten” ideas are developed at book length with a focus on economic theory in Ellerman (1992) which was published in a series co-edited by the late neo-Austrian economist, Don Lavoie, who described the theory in his acceptance letter as follows:
The book’s radical re-interpretation of property and contract is, I think, among the most powerful critiques of mainstream economics ever developed. It undermines the neoclassical way of thinking about property by articulating a theory of inalienable rights, and constructs out of this perspective a ‘labor theory of property’ which is as different from Marx’s labor theory of value as it is from neoclassicism. It traces roots of such ideas in some fascinating and largely forgotten strands of the history of economics. It draws attention to the question of ‘responsibility’ which neoclassicism has utterly lost sight of. …It constitutes a better case for its economic democracy viewpoint than anything else in the literature (Lavoie 1991, pp. 1–2).
 
18
Cornuelle (1991) is a welcome exception to the rule.
 
19
The older name of the relation was the “master-servant” relation but, aside from a few law books on agency law that use the “master-servant” language as technical terms (e.g., Batt 1967), that usage was slowly replaced in the late nineteenth century and early twentieth century with the Newspeak terms of “employer” and “employee.”
 
20
Kant considered working for a master in the master-servant relation as being so subordinating as to disqualify one for a civic personality.
Apprentices to merchants or tradesmen, servants who are not employed by the state, minors (naturaliter vel civiliter), women in general and all those who are obligated to depend for their living (i.e., food and protection) on the offices of others (excluding the state)—all of these people have no civil personality,…. (Kant 1991 (1797), p. 126, Section 46).
 
21
Note how the implications of Buchanan’s principals principle gives essentially the same results as Dewey’s democratic “principle (that) holds as much of one form of association, say in industry and commerce, as it does in government.”
 
22
This is much like Jefferson and the Founding Fathers who enunciated the principle of inalienable rights, but did not apply it to the peculiar institution of their time.
 
23
As was noted long ago (for example, Scitovsky 1951), there is no reason for the entrepreneur or family firm to take profits as the sole maximizing goal (although costs, of course, have to be covered for long-term sustainability). But with scattered absentee owners, profit seems to be the only thing that they can agree on in general. Hence profit maximization has been canonized as “the goal” of the firm when in fact it is only an artifact of a particular organizational form.
 
Literature
go back to reference Batt, Francis. 1967. The Law of Master and Servant. London: Pitman. Batt, Francis. 1967. The Law of Master and Servant. London: Pitman.
go back to reference Blackstone, William. 1959 (1765). Ehrlich’s Blackstone. New York: Capricorn Books. Blackstone, William. 1959 (1765). Ehrlich’s Blackstone. New York: Capricorn Books.
go back to reference Bryan, Edward B. 1858. Letters to the Southern People. Charleston: Press of Walker, Evans & Co. Bryan, Edward B. 1858. Letters to the Southern People. Charleston: Press of Walker, Evans & Co.
go back to reference Buchanan, James M. 1999. The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty: The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan Vol. 1. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Buchanan, James M. 1999. The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty: The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan Vol. 1. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
go back to reference _____. 2005. Why I, Too, Am Not a Conservative: The Normative Vision of Classical Liberalism. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. _____. 2005. Why I, Too, Am Not a Conservative: The Normative Vision of Classical Liberalism. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
go back to reference Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Cassirer, Ernst. 1963. The Myth of the State. New Haven: Yale University Press. Cassirer, Ernst. 1963. The Myth of the State. New Haven: Yale University Press.
go back to reference Catterall, Helen T. 1926. Judicial Cases Concerning Slavery and the Negro. Washington, DC: Carnegie Institute. Catterall, Helen T. 1926. Judicial Cases Concerning Slavery and the Negro. Washington, DC: Carnegie Institute.
go back to reference Christ, Carl F. 1975. The Competitive Market and Optimal Allocative Efficiency. In: Competing Philosophies in American Political Economics. John Elliott and John Cownie eds., pp. 332–338. Pacific Palisades: Goodyear. Christ, Carl F. 1975. The Competitive Market and Optimal Allocative Efficiency. In: Competing Philosophies in American Political Economics. John Elliott and John Cownie eds., pp. 332–338. Pacific Palisades: Goodyear.
go back to reference Coase, R. H. 1937. The Nature of the Firm. Economica IV (Nov. 1937): 386–405.CrossRef Coase, R. H. 1937. The Nature of the Firm. Economica IV (Nov. 1937): 386–405.CrossRef
go back to reference Cornuelle, Richard C. 1991. New Work for Invisible Hands. Times Literary Supplement (5 April 1991): 1–4. Cornuelle, Richard C. 1991. New Work for Invisible Hands. Times Literary Supplement (5 April 1991): 1–4.
go back to reference Corwin, Edward S. 1955. The ‘Higher Law’ Background of American Constitutional Law. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Corwin, Edward S. 1955. The ‘Higher Law’ Background of American Constitutional Law. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
go back to reference Davis, David Brion. 1966. The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Davis, David Brion. 1966. The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
go back to reference Dewey, John. 1916. Democracy and Education. New York: Free Press. Dewey, John. 1916. Democracy and Education. New York: Free Press.
go back to reference _____. 1948. Reconstruction in Philosophy (Enlarged edition). Boston: Beacon Press. _____. 1948. Reconstruction in Philosophy (Enlarged edition). Boston: Beacon Press.
go back to reference Dewey, John and James Tufts. 1908. Ethics. New York: Henry Holt. Dewey, John and James Tufts. 1908. Ethics. New York: Henry Holt.
go back to reference _____. 1932. Ethics. Revised ed., New York: Henry Holt. _____. 1932. Ethics. Revised ed., New York: Henry Holt.
go back to reference Ellerman, David. 1992. Property & Contract in Economics: The Case for Economic Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell. Ellerman, David. 1992. Property & Contract in Economics: The Case for Economic Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
go back to reference _____. 2005. Helping People Help Themselves: From the World Bank to an Alternative Philosophy of Development Assistance. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef _____. 2005. Helping People Help Themselves: From the World Bank to an Alternative Philosophy of Development Assistance. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef
go back to reference _____. 2010. Inalienable Rights: A Litmus Test for Liberal Theories of Justice. Law and Philosophy. 29 (5 September): 571–599.CrossRef _____. 2010. Inalienable Rights: A Litmus Test for Liberal Theories of Justice. Law and Philosophy. 29 (5 September): 571–599.CrossRef
go back to reference Faust, Drew Gilpin, ed. 1981. The Ideology of Slavery: Proslavery Thought in the Antebellum South, 1830–1860. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press. Faust, Drew Gilpin, ed. 1981. The Ideology of Slavery: Proslavery Thought in the Antebellum South, 1830–1860. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press.
go back to reference Filmer, Robert. 1680. Patriarcha; of the Natural Power of Kings. London: Richard Chiswell. Filmer, Robert. 1680. Patriarcha; of the Natural Power of Kings. London: Richard Chiswell.
go back to reference Finkelman, Paul. 2003. Defending Slavery: Proslavery Thought in the Old South: A Brief History with Documents. Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s. Finkelman, Paul. 2003. Defending Slavery: Proslavery Thought in the Old South: A Brief History with Documents. Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s.
go back to reference Fitzhugh, George. 1960 (1857). Cannibals All! or, Slaves Without Masters. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Fitzhugh, George. 1960 (1857). Cannibals All! or, Slaves Without Masters. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Freiman, Christopher. 2013. Cosmopolitanism Within Borders: On Behalf of Charter Cities. Journal of Applied Philosophy. 30 (1): 40–52.CrossRef Freiman, Christopher. 2013. Cosmopolitanism Within Borders: On Behalf of Charter Cities. Journal of Applied Philosophy. 30 (1): 40–52.CrossRef
go back to reference _____. 2014. Vote Markets. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (4): 759–74.CrossRef _____. 2014. Vote Markets. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (4): 759–74.CrossRef
go back to reference Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Genovese, Eugene. 1971. The World the Slaveholders Made. New York: Vintage Books. Genovese, Eugene. 1971. The World the Slaveholders Made. New York: Vintage Books.
go back to reference Gierke, Otto von. 1958. Political Theories of the Middle Age. F. W. Maitland (trans.), Boston: Beacon Press. Gierke, Otto von. 1958. Political Theories of the Middle Age. F. W. Maitland (trans.), Boston: Beacon Press.
go back to reference _____. 1966. The Development of Political Theory. B. Freyd (trans.), New York: Howard Fertig. _____. 1966. The Development of Political Theory. B. Freyd (trans.), New York: Howard Fertig.
go back to reference Goyder, George. 1961. The Responsible Company. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Goyder, George. 1961. The Responsible Company. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
go back to reference Gray, Lewis Cecil. 1958. History of Agriculture in the Southern United States to 1860. Gloucester: Peter Smith. Gray, Lewis Cecil. 1958. History of Agriculture in the Southern United States to 1860. Gloucester: Peter Smith.
go back to reference Grotius, Hugo. 1901 (1625). The Rights of War and Peace. A. C. Campbell (trans.), Washington: M. Walter Dunne. Grotius, Hugo. 1901 (1625). The Rights of War and Peace. A. C. Campbell (trans.), Washington: M. Walter Dunne.
go back to reference Heyne, Paul, Peter Boettke and David Prychitko. 2006. The Economic Way of Thinking. Eleventh edition. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall. Heyne, Paul, Peter Boettke and David Prychitko. 2006. The Economic Way of Thinking. Eleventh edition. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.
go back to reference Hobbes, Thomas. 1958 (1651). Leviathan. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Hobbes, Thomas. 1958 (1651). Leviathan. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
go back to reference Hutcheson, Francis. 1725. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. London. Hutcheson, Francis. 1725. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. London.
go back to reference _____. 1755. A System of Moral Philosophy. London. _____. 1755. A System of Moral Philosophy. London.
go back to reference Israel, Jonathan. 2010. A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Israel, Jonathan. 2010. A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Justinian. 1948. The Institutes of Justinian. T. C. Sandars (trans.), London: Longmans, Green & Co. Justinian. 1948. The Institutes of Justinian. T. C. Sandars (trans.), London: Longmans, Green & Co.
go back to reference Kant, Immanuel. 1991 (1797). The Metaphysics of Morals. Mary Gregor (trans.), New York: Cambridge University Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1991 (1797). The Metaphysics of Morals. Mary Gregor (trans.), New York: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Knight, Frank. 1947. Freedom and Reform. New York: Harper & Row. Knight, Frank. 1947. Freedom and Reform. New York: Harper & Row.
go back to reference Laslett, Peter. 1960. Introduction with Notes. In: John Locke: Two Treatises of Government. Peter Laslett (ed.), New York: New American Library. Laslett, Peter. 1960. Introduction with Notes. In: John Locke: Two Treatises of Government. Peter Laslett (ed.), New York: New American Library.
go back to reference Lavoie, Don. 1991. Letter to Publishing Assistant Jane Betar (Private Comm. April 24). 2 pages. Lavoie, Don. 1991. Letter to Publishing Assistant Jane Betar (Private Comm. April 24). 2 pages.
go back to reference Lincoln, Anthony. 1971. Some Political & Social Ideas of English Dissent 1763–1800. New York: Octagon Books. Lincoln, Anthony. 1971. Some Political & Social Ideas of English Dissent 1763–1800. New York: Octagon Books.
go back to reference Locke, John. 1960 (1690). Two Treatises of Government. New York: New American Library. Locke, John. 1960 (1690). Two Treatises of Government. New York: New American Library.
go back to reference Luther, Martin. 1942 (1523). Concerning Secular Authority. In Readings in Political Philosophy. Francis W. Coker ed., New York: Macmillan, pp. 306–329. Luther, Martin. 1942 (1523). Concerning Secular Authority. In Readings in Political Philosophy. Francis W. Coker ed., New York: Macmillan, pp. 306–329.
go back to reference Lynd, Staughton. 1969. Intellectual Origins of American Radicalism. New York: Vintage Books. Lynd, Staughton. 1969. Intellectual Origins of American Radicalism. New York: Vintage Books.
go back to reference Marsilius of Padua. 1980 (1324). Defensor Pacis. Alan Gewirth (trans.), Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Marsilius of Padua. 1980 (1324). Defensor Pacis. Alan Gewirth (trans.), Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
go back to reference McKitrick, Eric. ed. 1963. Slavery Defended: the views of the Old South. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. McKitrick, Eric. ed. 1963. Slavery Defended: the views of the Old South. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
go back to reference Mill, James. 1826. Elements of Political Economy. London. Mill, James. 1826. Elements of Political Economy. London.
go back to reference Mill, John Stuart. 1899. Principles of Political Economy. New York: Colonial Press. Mill, John Stuart. 1899. Principles of Political Economy. New York: Colonial Press.
go back to reference _____. 1961 (1835). Introduction: An appraisal of Volume I of Democracy in America. In: Democracy in America, New York: Schocken, pp. v–xlix. _____. 1961 (1835). Introduction: An appraisal of Volume I of Democracy in America. In: Democracy in America, New York: Schocken, pp. v–xlix.
go back to reference _____. 1972 (1861). Considerations of Representative Government. In: J. S. Mill: Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government. H. B. Acton ed., London: J. M. Dent and Sons, pp. 187–428. _____. 1972 (1861). Considerations of Representative Government. In: J. S. Mill: Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government. H. B. Acton ed., London: J. M. Dent and Sons, pp. 187–428.
go back to reference Montesquieu. 1912 (1748). The Spirit of the Laws. T. Nugent (trans.), New York: Appleton. Montesquieu. 1912 (1748). The Spirit of the Laws. T. Nugent (trans.), New York: Appleton.
go back to reference Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books. Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.
go back to reference Palmer, Tom G. 2009. Realizing Freedom: Libertarian Theory, History, and Practice. Washington DC: Cato Institute. Palmer, Tom G. 2009. Realizing Freedom: Libertarian Theory, History, and Practice. Washington DC: Cato Institute.
go back to reference Percy, Eustace. 1944. The Unknown State: 16th Riddell Memorial Lectures. London: Oxford University Press. Percy, Eustace. 1944. The Unknown State: 16th Riddell Memorial Lectures. London: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Philmore, J. 1982. The Libertarian Case for Slavery: A Note on Nozick. Philosophical Forum. XIV (Fall 1982): 43–58. Philmore, J. 1982. The Libertarian Case for Slavery: A Note on Nozick. Philosophical Forum. XIV (Fall 1982): 43–58.
go back to reference Pufendorf, Samuel. 2003 (1673). The Whole Duty of Man, According to the Law of Nature. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Pufendorf, Samuel. 2003 (1673). The Whole Duty of Man, According to the Law of Nature. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
go back to reference Ratner, Joseph, ed. 1939. Intelligence in the Modern World: John Dewey’s Philosophy. New York: Modern Library. Ratner, Joseph, ed. 1939. Intelligence in the Modern World: John Dewey’s Philosophy. New York: Modern Library.
go back to reference Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
go back to reference Sabine, George H. 1958. A History of Political Theory. New York: Henry Holt and Company. Sabine, George H. 1958. A History of Political Theory. New York: Henry Holt and Company.
go back to reference Samuelson, Paul A. 1976. Economics. Tenth edition. New York: McGraw-Hill. Samuelson, Paul A. 1976. Economics. Tenth edition. New York: McGraw-Hill.
go back to reference Scitovsky, Tibor. 1951. Welfare and Competition. Chicago: Irwin. Scitovsky, Tibor. 1951. Welfare and Competition. Chicago: Irwin.
go back to reference Seabury, Samuel. 1969 (1861). American Slavery Justified by the Law of Nature. Miami: Mnemosyne Publishing Company. Seabury, Samuel. 1969 (1861). American Slavery Justified by the Law of Nature. Miami: Mnemosyne Publishing Company.
go back to reference Skinner, Quentin. 1978. The foundations of modern political thought. Volumes I and II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Skinner, Quentin. 1978. The foundations of modern political thought. Volumes I and II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Smith, George H. 2013. The System of Liberty: Themes in the History of Classical Liberalism. New York: Cato Institute, Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Smith, George H. 2013. The System of Liberty: Themes in the History of Classical Liberalism. New York: Cato Institute, Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Spinoza, Benedict de. 1951 (1670). Theologico-Political Treatise. R. H. M. Elwes (trans.), New York: Dover Publications. Spinoza, Benedict de. 1951 (1670). Theologico-Political Treatise. R. H. M. Elwes (trans.), New York: Dover Publications.
go back to reference Sterkx, H. E. 1972. The Free Negro in Ante-Bellum Louisiana. Cranbury: Associated University Presses. Sterkx, H. E. 1972. The Free Negro in Ante-Bellum Louisiana. Cranbury: Associated University Presses.
go back to reference Tobin, James. 1970. On Limiting the Domain of Inequality. Journal of Law and Economics. 13 (2 October): 263–277.CrossRef Tobin, James. 1970. On Limiting the Domain of Inequality. Journal of Law and Economics. 13 (2 October): 263–277.CrossRef
go back to reference Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1961. Democracy in America Vol. I. Henry Reeve (trans.), New York: Schocken. Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1961. Democracy in America Vol. I. Henry Reeve (trans.), New York: Schocken.
go back to reference Tomasi, John. 2012. Free Market Fairness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Tomasi, John. 2012. Free Market Fairness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Williams, Elisha. 1998 (1744). The Essential Rights and Liberties of Protestants. In Political Sermons of the American Founding Era, 1730–1805 Vol. I. Ellis Sandoz ed., Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, pp. 55–118. Williams, Elisha. 1998 (1744). The Essential Rights and Liberties of Protestants. In Political Sermons of the American Founding Era, 1730–1805 Vol. I. Ellis Sandoz ed., Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, pp. 55–118.
go back to reference Wills, Garry. 1979. Inventing America. New York: Vintage Books. Wills, Garry. 1979. Inventing America. New York: Vintage Books.
go back to reference Wish, Harvey, ed. 1960. Ante-bellum. New York: Capricorn Books. Wish, Harvey, ed. 1960. Ante-bellum. New York: Capricorn Books.
Metadata
Title
Reclaiming Democratic Classical Liberalism
Author
David P. Ellerman
Copyright Year
2020
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-28760-3_1