Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Theory and Decision 3/2019

03-06-2019

Strategic communication with reporting costs

Published in: Theory and Decision | Issue 3/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

A decision maker relies on information of parties affected by her decision. These parties try to influence her decision by selective disclosure of facts. As is well known from the literature, competition between the informed parties constrains their ability to manipulate information. We depart from this literature by introducing a cost to communicate. Our parties trade off their reporting cost against the effect on the decision. Some information is never revealed. In contrast to setups without communication costs, our decision maker can benefit by ex ante committing to an ex post suboptimal decision rule. Moreover, committing ex ante not to listen to one of the parties may also be beneficial for the decision maker.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Appendix
Available only for authorised users
Footnotes
1
See Milgrom and Roberts (1986), Lipman and Seppi (1995), and Gentzkov and Kamenica (2017). At the end of the section, we review the literature related to our paper.
 
2
Under the adversary system “it is for the parties to determine not only the issues which the court is to decide, but also the material on which the decision will be based. The evidence presented to the court will be that which the parties choose to present and none other. The judge may not require that a particular witness be summoned to give evidence or that a particular document be produced; he may not even question the witnesses himself except for the purpose of clarifying some doubt as to the meaning of what a witness has said under examination by counsel,” Jolowicz (2000, p. 28).
 
3
In the inquisitorial procedure of civil law countries, “it is for the judge to examine the witnesses, if any, it is for the judge to decide whether to summon the parties for interrogation and it is the judge who acts to obtain the assistance of an expert when required,” Jolowicz (2000, p. 220). Our weak form of active adjudication is only one of the multiple instruments an inquisitorial judge has at hand.
 
4
Matthis (2008) provides necessary and sufficient conditions, with respect to preferences and available messages, for full unraveling in one-sender games.
 
5
The irrelevance of commitment is representative of a family of equivalence results between optimal mechanisms and equilibria in one-sender persuasion games; see Glazer and Rubinstein (2004, 2006), Sher (2011), and Hart et al. (2017). In the mechanism design approach, the decision maker moves first and commits to decision rules. The equivalence results state that she does as well when she moves second and plays a sequentially rational strategy. Bhattacharya and Mukherjee (2013) and Bhattacharya et al. (2018) show that the result extends to multiple senders, provided they have extreme agendas (either the same extreme agenda or diametrically opposed agendas).
 
6
Hay and Spier (1997) analyze the allocation of the burden of proof between plaintiff and defendant from the point of view of minimizing litigation costs. Because each party’s submission cost is less than the stake, the trial outcome is always without error. However, litigation expenditures will differ depending on the burden of proof assignment. More distantly related strands of literature deal with costly acquisition of information by the senders or with communication through “fabricated evidence”. See, e.g., Dewatripont and Tirole (1999), Gerardi and Yariv (2008), and Kim (2014) on the first issue; Kartik (2009) and Emons and Fluet (2009, 2019) on the second.
 
7
Sher’s (2011) condition for the irrelevance of commitment in one-sender games is that the decision maker’s utility function is a concave transformation of the sender’s utility function. This is satisfied here with respect to both senders with \(u_{J}(y,x)=-v\left( \left| u_{A}(y)+x\right| \right) =\)\(-v\left( \left| u_{B}(y)-x\right| \right) \).
 
8
Log-concavity of f implies log-concavity of F and is therefore a stronger condition.
 
9
A log-concave f implies that the hazard rate \(f(x)/(1-F(x))\) is increasing. This ensures uniqueness in the sender-A game. The proof is similar to the argument in Bagnoli and Bergstrom (2005).
 
10
To clarify our jargon: If under commitment only one agent reports, we call it a one-sender outcome. Without commitment, when only one party sends a message, be it in the game where both or only one party is allowed to report, we speak of a corner equilibrium.
 
11
With a strictly decreasing f, condition (19) in the proof implies \(\overline{U}_{J}^{\prime }(0)>0\), so \(\hat{y}=0\) cannot be optimal.
 
12
It is obviously never in the adjudicator’s interest to prohibit both parties from reporting.
 
13
Note that the uniform density is log-concave, but nevertheless leads to multiple equilibria in the two-sender game.
 
14
In Table 1, the type of equilibrium is denoted c-A for corner-A, c-B for corner-B, and int for interior.
 
15
Due to the skewness of the distribution, the no-disclosure set of the corner- A equilibrium is about twice the size of the no-disclosure set of the corner-B equilibrium. Yet, the no-disclosure states in the corner-A equilibrium are ex ante very unlikely as compared to the corner-B equilibrium.
 
16
In our examples, the one-sender games always have unique equilibria. Recall that uniqueness obtains when the density f(x) is log-concave, which is the case for \(a\ge 1\) and \(b\ge 1\).
 
17
Equation (16) combines Proposition 1 with the condition in Bhattacharya and Mukherjee (2013) for the case of two opposed experts. Setting \(p_{B}=0\) in (16) yields the equilibrium default decision in the one-sender equilibrium where only A is allowed to report.
 
18
In the corner-B equilibrium reporting costs play no role. Therefore, the optimal default decision under commitment equals the equilibrium default decision without commitment.
 
19
See, e.g., Emons and Fluet (2009, 2019) for such a setup.
 
Literature
go back to reference Bagnoli, M., & Bergstrom, T. (2005). Logconcave probability and its applications. Economic Theory, 26, 445–469.CrossRef Bagnoli, M., & Bergstrom, T. (2005). Logconcave probability and its applications. Economic Theory, 26, 445–469.CrossRef
go back to reference Bhattacharya, S., & Mukherjee, A. (2013). Strategic information revelation when experts compete to influence. RAND Journal of Economics, 44, 522–544.CrossRef Bhattacharya, S., & Mukherjee, A. (2013). Strategic information revelation when experts compete to influence. RAND Journal of Economics, 44, 522–544.CrossRef
go back to reference Bhattacharya, S., Golstman, M., & Mukherjee, A. (2018). On the optimality of diverse expert panels in persuasion games. Games and Economic Behavior, 107, 345–363.CrossRef Bhattacharya, S., Golstman, M., & Mukherjee, A. (2018). On the optimality of diverse expert panels in persuasion games. Games and Economic Behavior, 107, 345–363.CrossRef
go back to reference Cheong, I., & Kim, J.-Y. (2004). Costly information disclosure in oligopoly. Journal of Industrial Economics, 51, 121–132.CrossRef Cheong, I., & Kim, J.-Y. (2004). Costly information disclosure in oligopoly. Journal of Industrial Economics, 51, 121–132.CrossRef
go back to reference Crawford, V. P., & Sobel, J. (1982). Strategic information transmission. Econometrica, 50, 1431–1451.CrossRef Crawford, V. P., & Sobel, J. (1982). Strategic information transmission. Econometrica, 50, 1431–1451.CrossRef
go back to reference Dewatripont, M., & Tirole, J. (1999). Advocates. Journal of Political Economy, 107, 1–39.CrossRef Dewatripont, M., & Tirole, J. (1999). Advocates. Journal of Political Economy, 107, 1–39.CrossRef
go back to reference Dye, R. A. (1985). Disclosure of nonproprietary information. Journal of Accounting Research, 23, 123–145.CrossRef Dye, R. A. (1985). Disclosure of nonproprietary information. Journal of Accounting Research, 23, 123–145.CrossRef
go back to reference Emons, W., & Fluet, C. (2009). Accuracy versus falsification costs: the optimal amount of testimony. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 25, 134–156.CrossRef Emons, W., & Fluet, C. (2009). Accuracy versus falsification costs: the optimal amount of testimony. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 25, 134–156.CrossRef
go back to reference Eső, P., & Galambos, Á. (2013). Disagreement and evidence production in strategic information transmission. International Journal of Game Theory, 42, 263–282.CrossRef Eső, P., & Galambos, Á. (2013). Disagreement and evidence production in strategic information transmission. International Journal of Game Theory, 42, 263–282.CrossRef
go back to reference Gentzkov, M., & Kamenica, E. (2017). Competition in persuasion. Review of Economic Studies, 84, 300–322.CrossRef Gentzkov, M., & Kamenica, E. (2017). Competition in persuasion. Review of Economic Studies, 84, 300–322.CrossRef
go back to reference Gerardi, D. R., & Yariv, L. (2008). Costly Expertise. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 98, 187–193.CrossRef Gerardi, D. R., & Yariv, L. (2008). Costly Expertise. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 98, 187–193.CrossRef
go back to reference Glazer, J., & Rubinstein, A. (2004). On the optimal rules of persuasion. Econometrica, 72, 1715–1736.CrossRef Glazer, J., & Rubinstein, A. (2004). On the optimal rules of persuasion. Econometrica, 72, 1715–1736.CrossRef
go back to reference Glazer, J., & Rubinstein, A. (2006). A study on the pragmatics of persuasion: A game theoretical approach. Theoretical Economics, 1, 395–410. Glazer, J., & Rubinstein, A. (2006). A study on the pragmatics of persuasion: A game theoretical approach. Theoretical Economics, 1, 395–410.
go back to reference Grossman, S. J. (1981). The informational role of warranties and private disclosure abolut product quality. Journal of Law and Economics, 24, 461–483.CrossRef Grossman, S. J. (1981). The informational role of warranties and private disclosure abolut product quality. Journal of Law and Economics, 24, 461–483.CrossRef
go back to reference Grossman, S. J., & Hart, O. D. (1980). Disclosure laws and takeover bids. Journal of Finance, 35, 323–334.CrossRef Grossman, S. J., & Hart, O. D. (1980). Disclosure laws and takeover bids. Journal of Finance, 35, 323–334.CrossRef
go back to reference Hart, S., Kremer, I., & Perry, M. (2017). Evidence games: Truth and commitment. American Economic Review, 107, 690–713.CrossRef Hart, S., Kremer, I., & Perry, M. (2017). Evidence games: Truth and commitment. American Economic Review, 107, 690–713.CrossRef
go back to reference Hay, B. L., & Spier, K. (1997). Burden of proof in civil litigation: An economic perspective. Journal of Legal Studies, 26, 413–431.CrossRef Hay, B. L., & Spier, K. (1997). Burden of proof in civil litigation: An economic perspective. Journal of Legal Studies, 26, 413–431.CrossRef
go back to reference Hedlund, J. (2015). Persuasion with reporting costs. Games and Economic Behavior, 92, 28–40.CrossRef Hedlund, J. (2015). Persuasion with reporting costs. Games and Economic Behavior, 92, 28–40.CrossRef
go back to reference Jolowicz, J. A. (2000). On Civil Procedure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Jolowicz, J. A. (2000). On Civil Procedure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Jovanovic, B. (1982). Truthful disclosure of information. Bell Journal of Economics, 13, 36–44.CrossRef Jovanovic, B. (1982). Truthful disclosure of information. Bell Journal of Economics, 13, 36–44.CrossRef
go back to reference Kartik, N. (2009). Strategic communication with lying costs. Review of Economic Studies, 76, 1359–1395.CrossRef Kartik, N. (2009). Strategic communication with lying costs. Review of Economic Studies, 76, 1359–1395.CrossRef
go back to reference Kartik, N., Lee, F. L., & Suen, W. (2017). Investment in concealable information by biased experts. RAND Journal of Economics, 48, 24–43.CrossRef Kartik, N., Lee, F. L., & Suen, W. (2017). Investment in concealable information by biased experts. RAND Journal of Economics, 48, 24–43.CrossRef
go back to reference Kim, C. (2014). Adversarial and inquisitorial procedure in information acquisition. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 30, 767–803.CrossRef Kim, C. (2014). Adversarial and inquisitorial procedure in information acquisition. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 30, 767–803.CrossRef
go back to reference Lipman, B. L., & Seppi, D. J. (1995). Robust inference in communication games with partial provability. Journal of Economic Theory, 66, 370–405.CrossRef Lipman, B. L., & Seppi, D. J. (1995). Robust inference in communication games with partial provability. Journal of Economic Theory, 66, 370–405.CrossRef
go back to reference Matthis, J. (2008). Full revelation of information in sender-receiver games of persuasion. Journal of Economic Theory, 143, 571–584.CrossRef Matthis, J. (2008). Full revelation of information in sender-receiver games of persuasion. Journal of Economic Theory, 143, 571–584.CrossRef
go back to reference Milgrom, P. (1981). Good news and bad news: Representation theorems and applications. Bell Journal of Economics, 12, 380–391.CrossRef Milgrom, P. (1981). Good news and bad news: Representation theorems and applications. Bell Journal of Economics, 12, 380–391.CrossRef
go back to reference Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1986). Relying on the information of interested parties. RAND Journal of Economics, 17, 18–32.CrossRef Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1986). Relying on the information of interested parties. RAND Journal of Economics, 17, 18–32.CrossRef
go back to reference Shavell, (1989). A note on the incentive to reveal information. Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 14, 66–74.CrossRef Shavell, (1989). A note on the incentive to reveal information. Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 14, 66–74.CrossRef
go back to reference Sher, I. (2011). Credibility and determinism in a game of persuasion. Games and Economic Behavior, 71, 409–419.CrossRef Sher, I. (2011). Credibility and determinism in a game of persuasion. Games and Economic Behavior, 71, 409–419.CrossRef
go back to reference Shin, H. (1994a). News management and the value of firms. RAND Journal of Economics, 25, 58–71.CrossRef Shin, H. (1994a). News management and the value of firms. RAND Journal of Economics, 25, 58–71.CrossRef
go back to reference Shin, (1994b). The burden of proof in a game of persuasion. Journal of Economic Theory, 64, 253–264.CrossRef Shin, (1994b). The burden of proof in a game of persuasion. Journal of Economic Theory, 64, 253–264.CrossRef
go back to reference Shin, H. (1998). Adversarial and inquisitorial procedures in arbitration. RAND Journal of Economics, 29, 378–405.CrossRef Shin, H. (1998). Adversarial and inquisitorial procedures in arbitration. RAND Journal of Economics, 29, 378–405.CrossRef
go back to reference Verrecchia, R. (1983). Discretionary disclosure. Journal of Accounting and Economics, 5, 179–194.CrossRef Verrecchia, R. (1983). Discretionary disclosure. Journal of Accounting and Economics, 5, 179–194.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Strategic communication with reporting costs
Publication date
03-06-2019
Published in
Theory and Decision / Issue 3/2019
Print ISSN: 0040-5833
Electronic ISSN: 1573-7187
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-019-09709-4

Other articles of this Issue 3/2019

Theory and Decision 3/2019 Go to the issue