Skip to main content
Top

2018 | OriginalPaper | Chapter

The Possibility and Fruitfulness of a Debate on the Principle of Non-contradiction

Authors : Luis Estrada-González, Maria del Rosario Martínez-Ordaz

Published in: Contradictions, from Consistency to Inconsistency

Publisher: Springer International Publishing

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Five major stances on the problems of the possibility and fruitfulness of a debate on the principle of non-contradiction (PNC) are described: Detractors, Fierce supporters, Demonstrators, Methodologists and Calm supporters. We show what Calm supporters have to say on the other parties wondering about the possibility and fruitfulness of a debate on PNC. The main claim is that one can find all the elements of Calm supporters already in Aristotle’s works. In addition, we argue that the Aristotelian refutative strategy, originally used for dealing with detractors of PNC in Metaphysics, has wider implications for the possibility and fruitfulness of an up-to-date debate on PNC, at least in exhibiting some serious difficulties for the other parties.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Advocators of “anti-exceptionalism about logic” —for example, Williamson ([37, 38]) and Hjortland ([23])— can be regarded as methodologists, and their views surely would have implications for the debate here discussed. Note also that Priest appears as a detractor and a demonstrator, a contradiction that, for him, would show that the debate would be better approached through the methodological principles of rational choice. This would be more extensively discussed in Sects. 6 and 7 below.
 
2
The only caveat was that Aristotle aimed at establishing a version of PNC stronger than his refutations of detractors allowed to conclude but, as we have mentioned, this is not a problem for Calm supporters in general.
 
3
An ancestor of this is found in Plato, Republic [24] 436b: “It is obvious that the same thing will never do or suffer opposites in the same respect in relation to the same thing and at the same time.”
 
4
Also found in Plato. See Republic [24] 602e8-9: “And haven’t we said that it is impossible for the same [person] to think/imagine at once/simultaneously opposite [things] about the same [things]?”
 
5
We do not know a simple expression to name this property, not even in our mother-tongue, and certainly we do not dare piss the owners of English off by inventing one, hence the blank space.
 
6
And it must not be confused with Non-referential gap: There is no truth value describable as neither-true-nor-false. These are independent principles. Bivalence might not hold because, say, there is a third value, but it is not “neither-true-nor-false” but rather, say, “true-and-false”.
 
7
A key ingredient in classical logic is Functionality: (a) Every proposition has one value (b) but only one. In a language with the usual ingredients (conjunction, disjunction, etc. as certain functions) this, together with Bivalence, Falsity of at least one contradictory, No values-gluts and either version of (Interpretational) Non-contradiction, suffices to give all the usual valuations of classical logic.
 
8
For more details on this principle and its importance on Aristotle’s overall argument against Detractors of PNC in Metaphysics \(\varGamma \), see [35], where the principle is taken as saying that the meaning of a term is unique, definite and determinate. Nonetheless, we take the mutual exclusiveness of certain semantic properties as a more appropriate reconstruction of Aristotle’s claims on the uniqueness, definiteness and determinateness of meanings and their role in his refutations.
 
9
For a guided tour on even more versions of PNC, see [16].
 
10
Whereas it can be debated whether Aristotle’s notion of deduction allows reflexivity (A is deducible from A) because of the “something different from [the things] supposed results” clause, demonstration certainly does not allow it: A would have to be both more certain (for it is a premise in the demonstration) and less certain (for it is demonstrated) than itself.
 
11
This was a permanent stance:
No truth does have, and no truth could have, a true negation. Nothing is, and nothing could be, literally both true and false. This we know for certain, and a priori and without any exception for especially perplexing subject matters. (...) That may seem dogmatic. And it is: I am affirming the very thesis that [the foes of the PNC] have called into question and —contrary to the rules of debate— I decline to defend it. Further, I concede that it is indefensible against their challenge. They have called so much into question that I have no foothold on undisputed ground. So much the worse for the demand that philosophers always must be ready to defend their theses under the rules of debate. [21, 101]
And in a letter interceding for the publication of Priest’s In Contradiction:
Many people will think that it is an easy thing to refute Priest’s position, decisively and in accordance with customary rules of debate. It is not an easy thing. I myself think that it is an impossible thing: so much is called into question that debate will bog down into question-begging and deadlock. (Quoted in [27, xix].)
In what follows we will use interchangeably ‘x is debated’, ‘x is disputed’, ‘the possibility that x does not hold is entertained’ and even ‘x is defended’ in this reconstruction.
 
12
Field [14] and Boghossian [6] call a principle “default reasonable” if it is regarded as being good at leading to true beliefs and avoiding error (hence reasonable) and it is done so without first adducing evidence or argument in its favor (hence default). We do not think PNC would be default reasonable in this sense for Lewis: It is not merely good at leading to true beliefs and avoiding errors, but is the sine qua non to draw a distinction between true beliefs and errors at all; also, it is not merely default, but already the distinction between what counts as evidence and an argument in favor of something presupposes it.
 
13
See [9, Ch. 5] for further details.
 
14
Thus, pace Priest [26], we take sides with those who say that some of Aristotle’s refutations establish not necessarily PNC itself or at least its Universality, but something else about it, even if that was not Aristotle’s aim. See [34] for further discussion.
 
15
Priest [26, 14f] does not regard as refutations some arguments where apparently there is no other agent saying anything on the basis that Aristotle required Detractors to say something. This internalization would help to explain the fact that there could be a refutation even if there were nobody saying anything: Detractors’ saying has been internalized in the supporter’s argument.
 
16
We would like to emphasize that the following reconstruction of Aristotle’s refutation strategy is not an attempt to make an exegetically perfect reconstruction —considering, for example, the fact that it is described in terms of a contemporary semantics. The main purpose of this reconstruction is to show in a comprehensive manner how the strategy works. We leave to the Aristotelian scholars to decide whether it matches perfectly the original proposal.
 
17
And at least in one case, Aristotle distinguishes between Heracliteanism and dialetheism because they need to be refuted in different ways, cf. Metaphysics 1008a7-12.
 
18
Whether these views should actually be attributed to the historical Heraclitus is a moot point; see [15, Ch. 5]. However, the interest here lies more in the position itself than in the correctness of Aristotle’s scholarship.
 
19
The problem is that Priest sometimes conflates trivialism —“Everything is true”— with a version of Heracliteanism —’All contradictions are true’— (cf. [28, 131], although sometimes he says that he is aware that the identification depends on certain assumptions, notoriously ‘and’-elimination (see [26, 56]. Aristotle too thought that semantic Heracliteanism could be equated with trivialism, but he was cautious: “The doctrine of Heraclitus, that all things are and are not, seems to make everything true (...)” (Metaphysics1012a25).
 
20
In proof-theoretic terms, Heracliteans would not accept conjunction elimination when the premise is a contradiction, and they would accept conjunction introduction when the conjuncts are not true but only if they are contradictories. In model-theoretic terms, it may be that \(v(A) \ne \top \) or \(v(B) \ne \top \) even if \(v(A\wedge B) = \top \). So, when the conjuncts are contradictories, semantic Heracliteanism’s conjunction resembles the relevance logics’ fusion connective, and thus is not so odd by contemporary lights. Besides, in certain sense, semantic Heracliteanism is dual to non-adjunctivism, which is a thesis found in some paraconsistent logics like the earliest one, Jaśkowski’s: In non-adjunctivism, in general \(v(A\wedge \lnot A) \ne \top \) even if \(v(A) = v(\lnot A) = \top \). Non-adjunctivism was used in some of the earliest attempts to make sense of impossible worlds; see [29].
 
21
An argument similar to this one is presented in Metaphysics K (see 1062b2ff).
 
22
Again according to Aristotle, Cratylus held that even contradictions over-fix reality so they must be altogether false, like their conjuncts. However, he noticed the problem faced by the Heraclitean and did not make the mistake of trying to philosophize about that, so he attempted to threw the ladder out after stating his position and ceased to do virtually any philosophical statement (only “virtually” because he kept denying with his forefinger and that still causes problems). See Metaphysics 1010a10ff.
 
23
Note that according to the Aristotelian argument, the option of describing a language in which all contradictions are true but none of their components is true is open to Heracliteans, provided that in its metalanguage either not all contradictions are true or some of the components of a contradiction are true separately from it.
 
24
That PNC might hold only for restricted versions has been pointed out several times by scholars. Substances and “essential predicates” are the usual candidates for which oPNC certainly holds (cf. [11, 17, 19]), although sometimes a slippery slope from the restricted oPNC about essential predicates to a general oPNC about any predicates is attempted; see for example [33]. Tahko [32] defends that oPNC holds certainly for concreta and its properties in “genuinely possible worlds with macroscopic objects”, but not necessarily for every object of every possible world, not even for every object of every physically possible world. More recently, Coren [10] has recently provided an interpretation like ours, but attempting to show that Aristotle can succeed in defending a principle much stronger than MSPNC.
 
25
See also [30, §19]; [31, Ch. VIII].
 
26
In [27, 241ff], Priest explicitly says that some arithmetical statements (in an inconsistent arithmetic) are both provable and not provable.
 
27
Lewis mentions this:
It is not an easy thing [to refute Priest’s position, decisively and in accordance with customary rules of debate]. I myself think that it is an impossible thing: so much is called into question that debate will bog down into question-begging and deadlock. (On this point, Priest disagrees with me: he thinks that shared principles of methodology might provide enough common ground.) (Quoted in [27, xix].)
 
28
See also [26, 110].
 
29
This reveals that Priest underestimated Aristotle’s remark in Posterior Analytics mentioned in Sect. 4. Aristotle says that whenever one wants to demonstrate something but not also something excluded by it, one has to presuppose PNC. If it is presupposed in no demonstration, one always could demonstrate something but also something else excluded by what was supposedly demonstrated, hence all exclusions could be demonstrated. Given MSPNC, the fact that contradictory propositions can be accepted is irrelevant as to the Indemonstrability of (MS)PNC, although perhaps it counts against some form of Universality for especially stronger versions of it.
 
30
To be fair, dialetheists and other detractors are right in questioning stronger forms of PNC, like “any sentence of the form \(A\wedge \lnot A\) is untrue in any valuation”, and their assimilation to weaker forms like MSPNC.
 
31
Cf. the reconstruction of the debates in [8, 170–173].
 
Literature
1.
go back to reference Aristotle: Metaphysics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. J Barnes (vol. 2). Princeton N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984. Aristotle: Metaphysics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. J Barnes (vol. 2). Princeton N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984.
2.
go back to reference Aristotle: Posterior Analytics, edited and translated with a commentary by Jonathan Barnes, Oxford: Clarendon Press, second edition, 1994. Aristotle: Posterior Analytics, edited and translated with a commentary by Jonathan Barnes, Oxford: Clarendon Press, second edition, 1994.
3.
go back to reference Aristotle: Prior Analytics, Robert Smith (trans.), Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989. Aristotle: Prior Analytics, Robert Smith (trans.), Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989.
4.
go back to reference Berto, Francesco. 2008. Adynaton and material exclusion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2): 165–190. Berto, Francesco. 2008. Adynaton and material exclusion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2): 165–190.
5.
go back to reference Berto, Francesco. 2012. How to rule out things with words. In New Waves in Philosophical Logic, ed. Greg Restall, and Gillian Russell, 169–189. Great Britain: Palgrave Macmillan. Berto, Francesco. 2012. How to rule out things with words. In New Waves in Philosophical Logic, ed. Greg Restall, and Gillian Russell, 169–189. Great Britain: Palgrave Macmillan.
6.
go back to reference Boghossian, Paul. 2000. Knowledge of logic. In New Essays on the A Priori, ed. Paul Boghossian, and Christopher Peacocke, 229–254. New York: Oxford University Press. Boghossian, Paul. 2000. Knowledge of logic. In New Essays on the A Priori, ed. Paul Boghossian, and Christopher Peacocke, 229–254. New York: Oxford University Press.
7.
go back to reference Boole, George. 1854. An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on which are founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Boole, George. 1854. An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on which are founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
8.
go back to reference Bueno, Otávio, and Mark Colyvan. 2004. Logical non-apriorism and the "law" of non-contradiction. In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Jc Beall, Graham Priest, and Bradley Armour-Garb, 156–175. New York: Oxford University Press. Bueno, Otávio, and Mark Colyvan. 2004. Logical non-apriorism and the "law" of non-contradiction. In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Jc Beall, Graham Priest, and Bradley Armour-Garb, 156–175. New York: Oxford University Press.
9.
go back to reference Castagnoli, Luca. 2010. Ancient Self-Refutation: The Logic and History of the Self-Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Castagnoli, Luca. 2010. Ancient Self-Refutation: The Logic and History of the Self-Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
10.
go back to reference Coren, Daniel. 2018. Why does Aristotle defend the principle of noncontradiction against its contrary? Philosophical Forum 49 (1): 39–59. Coren, Daniel. 2018. Why does Aristotle defend the principle of noncontradiction against its contrary? Philosophical Forum 49 (1): 39–59.
11.
go back to reference Cresswell, Maxwell. 2004. Non-contradiction and substantial predication. Theoria 70: 166–183. Cresswell, Maxwell. 2004. Non-contradiction and substantial predication. Theoria 70: 166–183.
12.
go back to reference Dancy, Russell M. 1975. Sense and Contradiction: A Study in Aristotle. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRef Dancy, Russell M. 1975. Sense and Contradiction: A Study in Aristotle. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRef
13.
go back to reference Dutilh Novaes, Catarina. 2012. Formal Languages in Logic -A Philosophical and Cognitive Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dutilh Novaes, Catarina. 2012. Formal Languages in Logic -A Philosophical and Cognitive Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
14.
go back to reference Field, Hartry. 2000. Apriority as an evaluative notion. In New Essays on the A Priori, ed. Paul Boghossian, and Christopher Peacocke, 117–149. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Field, Hartry. 2000. Apriority as an evaluative notion. In New Essays on the A Priori, ed. Paul Boghossian, and Christopher Peacocke, 117–149. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
15.
go back to reference Graham, Daniel. 2006. Explaining the Cosmos: The Ionian Tradition of Scientific Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Graham, Daniel. 2006. Explaining the Cosmos: The Ionian Tradition of Scientific Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
16.
go back to reference Grim, Patrick. 2004. What is a contradiction? In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Jc Beall Graham Priest, and Bradley Armour-Garb, 49–72. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Grim, Patrick. 2004. What is a contradiction? In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Jc Beall Graham Priest, and Bradley Armour-Garb, 49–72. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
17.
go back to reference Irwin, Terence. 2006. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Irwin, Terence. 2006. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
18.
go back to reference Kant, Immanuel. 1755. Concerning the principle of contradiction. In Kant. Theoretical Philosophy 1755-1770, ed. David Walford, and Ralf Meerbote, 6–10. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1755. Concerning the principle of contradiction. In Kant. Theoretical Philosophy 1755-1770, ed. David Walford, and Ralf Meerbote, 6–10. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
19.
go back to reference Kirwan, Christopher. 1993. Aristotle, Metaphysics (Books $\Gamma $, $\Delta $, E), 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kirwan, Christopher. 1993. Aristotle, Metaphysics (Books $\Gamma $, $\Delta $, E), 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
20.
go back to reference Lear, Jonathan. 1988. Aristotle: The Desire to Understand. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Lear, Jonathan. 1988. Aristotle: The Desire to Understand. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
21.
go back to reference Lewis, David. 1982. Logic for equivocators. Noûs 16 (3): 431–441; Reprinted as Chapter 7 of Lewis. 1998. Papers in Philosophical Logic, 97–110, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lewis, David. 1982. Logic for equivocators. Noûs 16 (3): 431–441; Reprinted as Chapter 7 of Lewis. 1998. Papers in Philosophical Logic, 97–110, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
22.
go back to reference Lewis, David. 2004. Letters to Beall and Priest. In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Jc Beall Graham Priest, and Bradley Armour-Garb, 176–177. New York: Oxford University Press. Lewis, David. 2004. Letters to Beall and Priest. In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Jc Beall Graham Priest, and Bradley Armour-Garb, 176–177. New York: Oxford University Press.
23.
go back to reference Ole Thomassen Hjortland. 2017. Anti-exceptionalism about logic. Philosophical Studies 174 (3): 631–658.CrossRef Ole Thomassen Hjortland. 2017. Anti-exceptionalism about logic. Philosophical Studies 174 (3): 631–658.CrossRef
24.
go back to reference Plato: The Republic, Desmond Lee (trans.), Penguin Classics, 1955. Plato: The Republic, Desmond Lee (trans.), Penguin Classics, 1955.
25.
go back to reference Priest, Graham. 1989. Reductio ad absurdum et modus tollendo ponens. In Paraconsistent Logic. Essays on the Inconsistent, ed. Richard Routley, Graham Priest, and Jean Norman, 613–626. München: Philosophia Verlag. Priest, Graham. 1989. Reductio ad absurdum et modus tollendo ponens. In Paraconsistent Logic. Essays on the Inconsistent, ed. Richard Routley, Graham Priest, and Jean Norman, 613–626. München: Philosophia Verlag.
26.
go back to reference Priest, Graham. 2006. Doubt Truth to be a Liar. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Priest, Graham. 2006. Doubt Truth to be a Liar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
27.
go back to reference Priest, Graham. 2006. In Contradiction, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press.CrossRef Priest, Graham. 2006. In Contradiction, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press.CrossRef
28.
go back to reference Priest, Graham. 2007. Paraconsistency and dialetheism. In The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic, vol. 8, ed. Dov Gabbay, and John Woods, 129–204., Handbook of the History of Logic The Netherlands: Elsevier. Priest, Graham. 2007. Paraconsistency and dialetheism. In The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic, vol. 8, ed. Dov Gabbay, and John Woods, 129–204., Handbook of the History of Logic The Netherlands: Elsevier.
29.
go back to reference Rescher, Nicholas, and Robert Brandom. 1980. The Logic of Inconsistency: A Study in Non-Standard Possible Worlds Semantics and Ontology. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Rescher, Nicholas, and Robert Brandom. 1980. The Logic of Inconsistency: A Study in Non-Standard Possible Worlds Semantics and Ontology. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
30.
go back to reference Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. London and New York: Routledge. Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. London and New York: Routledge.
31.
go back to reference Russell, Bertrand. 1912. The Problems of Philosophy. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Russell, Bertrand. 1912. The Problems of Philosophy. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
32.
go back to reference Tahko, Tuomas E. 2014. The metaphysical interpretation of logical truth. In The Metaphysics of Logic: Logical Realism, Logical Anti-Realism and All Things In Between, ed. Penelope Rush, 233–248. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Tahko, Tuomas E. 2014. The metaphysical interpretation of logical truth. In The Metaphysics of Logic: Logical Realism, Logical Anti-Realism and All Things In Between, ed. Penelope Rush, 233–248. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
33.
go back to reference Wedin, Michael V. 2000. Some logical problems in metaphysics gamma. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 19: 113–162. Wedin, Michael V. 2000. Some logical problems in metaphysics gamma. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 19: 113–162.
34.
go back to reference Wedin, Michael V. 2014. The science and axioms of being. In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Georgios Anagnostopoulos, 123–143. Massachusetts: Wiley-Blackwell. Wedin, Michael V. 2014. The science and axioms of being. In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Georgios Anagnostopoulos, 123–143. Massachusetts: Wiley-Blackwell.
35.
go back to reference Whitaker, Charles W. A. 1996. Aristotle’s De Interpretatione: Contradiction and Dialectic. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press. Whitaker, Charles W. A. 1996. Aristotle’s De Interpretatione: Contradiction and Dialectic. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press.
36.
go back to reference Whitehead, Alfred North, and Bertrand Russell. 1910. Principia Mathematica, vol. I, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Whitehead, Alfred North, and Bertrand Russell. 1910. Principia Mathematica, vol. I, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
37.
go back to reference Williamson, Timothy. 2013. Logic, metalogic and neutrality. Erkenntnis 79 (2): 211–231. Williamson, Timothy. 2013. Logic, metalogic and neutrality. Erkenntnis 79 (2): 211–231.
38.
go back to reference Williamson, Timothy. 2017. Semantic paradoxes and abductive methodology. In Reflections on the Liar, ed. Bradley Armour-Garb, 325–346. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Williamson, Timothy. 2017. Semantic paradoxes and abductive methodology. In Reflections on the Liar, ed. Bradley Armour-Garb, 325–346. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Metadata
Title
The Possibility and Fruitfulness of a Debate on the Principle of Non-contradiction
Authors
Luis Estrada-González
Maria del Rosario Martínez-Ordaz
Copyright Year
2018
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98797-2_3

Premium Partner