Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Human Studies 4/2017

18-09-2017 | Theoretical/Philosophical Paper

Truth and Consciousness

Author: Chris Calvert-Minor

Published in: Human Studies | Issue 4/2017

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Many work on flushing out what our consciousness means in cognitive and phenomenological terms, but no one has yet connected the dots on how consciousness and truth intersect, much less how our phenomenal consciousness can form the ground for most of our models of truth. Here, I connect those dots and argue that the basic structure of our phenomenal consciousness grounds the nature of truth as concordance, to harmonize in agreement, and that most extant theories on truth are well explained in that grounding. Said another way, the unifying and bifurcating intentional structure of phenomenal consciousness is the non-epistemic ground of truth, such that most theories of truth can be explained as particular expressions of concordance based upon the differing aspects of that ground.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
I am grateful to my anonymous reviewers for their time and valuable input on an earlier version of this manuscript.
 
2
While I focus on human consciousness here, this does not mean that other conscious creatures are necessarily excluded. As far as we know, humans are the only conscious creatures to construct theories of truth, and so it makes sense to tailor the analysis to humans. But for the most part, the analysis of consciousness here would apply to other conscious creatures with the exception of reflective consciousness and self-consciousness, which may or may not be present in other species.
 
3
I take the terms “pre-reflective” and “reflective” consciousness from Sartre (1960, 1992).
 
4
The sense of the givenness of experience here does not conflict with Sellars’ (1997) critique of givenness. Sellars’ main point concerns epistemological accounts that grant certain immediacies in experience (e.g., sensing) as non-inferential knowledge by which to ground further knowledge and justifications. Sellars finds these accounts flawed, and I agree, but his interest lies in epistemology and normativity in relation to experience and the “space of reason”. The account of the givenness of experience here is not epistemological; it is merely descriptive. Sellars even appears to be quite content with descriptive accounts of experience (1997: 13).
 
5
I use “representationalist” in the traditional manner of creating conceptual pictures or models in the mind of the experiencing person. More recently, representationalism has a more varied use, such as even allowing for non-conceptual representational content (e.g., Tye 1995; Crane 2003). Discussing how these more recent forms of representationalism match or conflict with the account of phenomenal consciousness I sketch here is beyond the scope of this paper, so I leave them be.
 
6
Heidegger himself eschews talk of consciousness, for the most part, because he is trying to talk instead about the existence of “Da-sein”. He is not supplanting the term “consciousness” with a mere replacement of “Da-sein” (1998a: 283); rather, it is the phenomenon of Da-sein and its openness to beings that makes consciousness possible. “All consciousness presupposes existence, thought as ecstatic, as the essentia of the human being—essentia meaning that as which the being essentially prevails insofar as he is human. But consciousness does not itself create the openness of beings, nor is it consciousness that makes it possible for the human being to stand open for beings” (1998a: 284). If one accepts Heidegger’s point here, it may seem that talk of consciousness is overrated or even wrong, but Heidegger is more concerned with traditional phenomenology’s focus on intentionality than with the holistic aspect of consciousness I am emphasizing at the moment. He writes, “[w]hither and whence and in what free dimension could the intentionality of consciousness move, if in-standing were not the essence of the human being in the first instance?” (1998a: 284f.) Thus, while Heidegger is not smitten with talk about consciousness, it is fair to link this account of the unity of consciousness with Heidegger’s account of the there-ness of being; they amount to the same thing. They are both founded on the pre-reflective, holistic givenness of human existence. Nonetheless, I thereby avoid saddling Heidegger’s concept of Da-sein as another expression of intentional consciousness.
 
7
Even if one directs one’s awareness to oneself such that one attempts to be present to oneself in a positional manner, this is still awareness of an other. One is aware of an objectification of oneself. This is why Sartre says that presence to oneself always implies a duality (1992: 124).
 
8
It is worth noting that Michel Henry disagrees with traditional phenomenology’s insistence on intentionality in a manner akin to Heidegger. Rather than adhere to a phenomenology that only sees transcendence (an orientation towards the other), Henry argues that subjectivity should first be recognized as absolute and immanent, being fully self-sufficient as non-intentional, and hence, non-relational (1975, 2008). The transcendence of subjectivity is only made possible based upon the more originary “radical immanence” of subjectivity (2008: 81). There is no need to assess his claim though. Whether Henry is right that subjectivity sits in primordial, radical immanence, he acknowledges the irreducible facet of intentionality. “Certainly, subjectivity is always a life in the presence of a transcendent being” (1975: 187). So, while Henry argues that the “monistic” approach of traditional phenomenology must be supplanted by a more “dualistic” one to recognize both the immanence and transcendence of subjectivity, that does not discount the indispensability of intentionality in consciousness. Henry weakens the importance given to intentionality, but even if intentionality is derivative, it is still a vital aspect in the phenomenon of consciousness.
 
9
Traditional representationalist theories of consciousness commit the error of only and ever esteeming the disunity in consciousness to the exclusion of any unity, and theorists like Taylor make the opposite error of emphasizing the unity of consciousness over any meaningful measure of disunity. Taylor is so insistent against mediational views that he formulates his “contact” theory in a way that situates humans in the embeddedness and unity of experience without adequate consideration for why such mediational views arise in the first place. In section “Some Implications,” I explain how this causes a problem for Taylor’s understanding of truth.
 
10
I leave unexplained that concordance is sought after, but all theories of truth demonstrate this aspiration, and due to the structure of phenomenal consciousness, it is not surprising how these theories of truth become formulated.
 
11
It may also be possible to list Kierkegaard’s explanation of “truth is subjectivity” (1992) here as a retention theory, but one could say that Heidegger “ontologizes” Kierkegaard’s metaethical account of subjectivity and that this offers a clearer example.
 
12
As a sidenote, it is interesting that what James does differently than correspondence and coherence theories is that he also tries to answer why we want concordance—truth is useful for living. That theories of truth involve harmonizing disparate elements is undeniable, but it is a different matter to ask whether we should really care about concordance or not. This is one of Nietzsche’s questions as he was perplexed by the philosophers’ “will to truth” and asks “why not untruth instead” (2002: 5)? Perhaps the drive for truth as concordance is more of an issue for cultural studies than just philosophy. But as I mention above, I leave the drive for truth as concordance unexplained.
 
13
Heidegger’s developed, though earlier, view of truth here is paradigmatic of a retention theory of truth. Yet, it is interesting to note that in his later years, Heidegger came to walk back this notion of truth, though not the notion of unconcealment. In “The End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking,” he remarks, “[i]n any case, one thing becomes clear: to raise the question of alētheia, of unconcealment as such, is not the same as raising the question of truth. For this reason, it was inadequate and misleading to call alētheia in the sense of opening, truth” (1977: 389).
 
14
This, of course, does not mean that particular theories of truth within the categories are unable to jockey for greater warrant.
 
Literature
go back to reference Albahari, M. (2006). Analytical Buddhism: The two-tiered illusion of the self. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef Albahari, M. (2006). Analytical Buddhism: The two-tiered illusion of the self. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef
go back to reference Austin, J. L. (1950). Truth, part 1. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, Vol. 24, 111–128. Austin, J. L. (1950). Truth, part 1. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, Vol. 24, 111–128.
go back to reference Barnes, H. (1992). Sartre’s ontology: The revealing and making of being. In C. Howells (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Sartre (pp. 13–38). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Barnes, H. (1992). Sartre’s ontology: The revealing and making of being. In C. Howells (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Sartre (pp. 13–38). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Bermúdez, J. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Bermúdez, J. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
go back to reference Blanshard, B. (1941). The nature of thought. New York, NY: Macmillan. Blanshard, B. (1941). The nature of thought. New York, NY: Macmillan.
go back to reference Burge, T. (1998). Two kinds of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, G. Guzeldere, & G. Cambridge (Eds.), The nature of consciousness: Philosophical debates, 2nd part (pp. 427–433). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Burge, T. (1998). Two kinds of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, G. Guzeldere, & G. Cambridge (Eds.), The nature of consciousness: Philosophical debates, 2nd part (pp. 427–433). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
go back to reference Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 33–56). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 33–56). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Davidson, D. (1996). The folly of trying to define truth. Journal of Philosophy, 93(6), 263–278.CrossRef Davidson, D. (1996). The folly of trying to define truth. Journal of Philosophy, 93(6), 263–278.CrossRef
go back to reference Davidson, D. (2005). Truth and predication. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRef Davidson, D. (2005). Truth and predication. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company. Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.
go back to reference Dreyfus, H. (2007). Response to McDowell. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 50(4), 371–377.CrossRef Dreyfus, H. (2007). Response to McDowell. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 50(4), 371–377.CrossRef
go back to reference Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Edey, M. (1997). Subject and object. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(5–6), 526–531. Edey, M. (1997). Subject and object. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(5–6), 526–531.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. (1977). The end of philosophy and the task of thinking. In D. F. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (J. Stambaugh, Trans.) (pp. 373–392). San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco. Heidegger, M. (1977). The end of philosophy and the task of thinking. In D. F. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (J. Stambaugh, Trans.) (pp. 373–392). San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. (1998a). Introduction to “What is metaphysics?”. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (J. Sallis, Trans.) (pp. 277–290). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Heidegger, M. (1998a). Introduction to “What is metaphysics?”. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (J. Sallis, Trans.) (pp. 277–290). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. (1998b). On the essence of truth. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (J. Sallis, Trans.) (pp. 136–154). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Heidegger, M. (1998b). On the essence of truth. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (J. Sallis, Trans.) (pp. 136–154). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Henry, M. (1975). Philosophy and phenomenology of the body (G. Etzkorn, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Henry, M. (1975). Philosophy and phenomenology of the body (G. Etzkorn, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
go back to reference Henry, M. (2008). Material phenomenology (S. Davidson, Trans.). New York, NY: Fordham University Press. Henry, M. (2008). Material phenomenology (S. Davidson, Trans.). New York, NY: Fordham University Press.
go back to reference James, W. (1997). The meaning of truth. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. James, W. (1997). The meaning of truth. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
go back to reference Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Concluding unscientific postscript to philosophical fragments (H. Hong & E. Hong, Trans.) (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Concluding unscientific postscript to philosophical fragments (H. Hong & E. Hong, Trans.) (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Kriegel, U. (2003). Consciousness as intransitive self-consciousness: Two views and an argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33(1), 103–132.CrossRef Kriegel, U. (2003). Consciousness as intransitive self-consciousness: Two views and an argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33(1), 103–132.CrossRef
go back to reference Legrand, D. (2007). Pre-reflective self-as-subject from experiential and empirical perspectives. Consciousness and Cognition, 16, 583–599.CrossRef Legrand, D. (2007). Pre-reflective self-as-subject from experiential and empirical perspectives. Consciousness and Cognition, 16, 583–599.CrossRef
go back to reference Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). New York, NY: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). New York, NY: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.
go back to reference Nietzsche, F. (2002). Beyond good and evil (J. Norman, Trans.). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Nietzsche, F. (2002). Beyond good and evil (J. Norman, Trans.). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Quine, W. V. O. (1986). Philosophy of logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Quine, W. V. O. (1986). Philosophy of logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Ramsey, F. (1927). Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl., 7(1), 153–170.CrossRef Ramsey, F. (1927). Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl., 7(1), 153–170.CrossRef
go back to reference Russell, B. (1964). The problems of philosophy, 10th part. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Russell, B. (1964). The problems of philosophy, 10th part. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Sartre, J.-P. (1960). The transcendence of the ego: An existentialist theory of consciousness (R. Williams & R. Kirkpatrick, Trans.). New York, NY: The Noonday Press. Sartre, J.-P. (1960). The transcendence of the ego: An existentialist theory of consciousness (R. Williams & R. Kirkpatrick, Trans.). New York, NY: The Noonday Press.
go back to reference Sartre, J.-P. (1992). Being and nothingness: A phenomenological essay on ontology (H. Barnes, Trans.). New York, NY: Washington Square Press. Sartre, J.-P. (1992). Being and nothingness: A phenomenological essay on ontology (H. Barnes, Trans.). New York, NY: Washington Square Press.
go back to reference Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Strawson, G. (2005). Real intentionality V. 2: Why intentionality entails consciousness? Synthesis Philosophica, 20(2), 279–297. Strawson, G. (2005). Real intentionality V. 2: Why intentionality entails consciousness? Synthesis Philosophica, 20(2), 279–297.
go back to reference Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth: And the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4(3), 341–376.CrossRef Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth: And the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4(3), 341–376.CrossRef
go back to reference Taylor, C. (2013). Retrieving realism. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell–Dreyfus debate (pp. 61–90). New York, NY: Routledge. Taylor, C. (2013). Retrieving realism. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell–Dreyfus debate (pp. 61–90). New York, NY: Routledge.
go back to reference Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2005a). Intentionality and experience. Synthesis Philosophica, 20(2), 299–318. Zahavi, D. (2005a). Intentionality and experience. Synthesis Philosophica, 20(2), 299–318.
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2005b). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Zahavi, D. (2005b). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2009). Is the self a social construct? Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 52(6), 551–573.CrossRef Zahavi, D. (2009). Is the self a social construct? Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 52(6), 551–573.CrossRef
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2011). Unity of consciousness and the problem of self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 316–335). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Zahavi, D. (2011). Unity of consciousness and the problem of self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 316–335). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2013). Mindedness, mindlessness, and first-person authority. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell–Dreyfus debate (pp. 320–343). New York, NY: Routledge. Zahavi, D. (2013). Mindedness, mindlessness, and first-person authority. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell–Dreyfus debate (pp. 320–343). New York, NY: Routledge.
Metadata
Title
Truth and Consciousness
Author
Chris Calvert-Minor
Publication date
18-09-2017
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Human Studies / Issue 4/2017
Print ISSN: 0163-8548
Electronic ISSN: 1572-851X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9444-6

Other articles of this Issue 4/2017

Human Studies 4/2017 Go to the issue