Skip to main content
Top
Published in: The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2017

03-06-2016

When the Reflective Watch-Dog Barks: Conscience and Self-Deception in Kant

Author: Martin Sticker

Published in: The Journal of Value Inquiry | Issue 1/2017

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Excerpt

Kant’s conception of conscience has recently become a matter of intense interest and debate in the Kant literature.1 I will focus on a problem that has not yet received its due attention. Conscience can warn agents every time they are about to transgress the moral law and it retrospectively reproaches agents for transgressions, yet Kant believes that there is also a natural propensity to self-deception. Self-deception, however, is only possible if agents can successfully hide from themselves the moral implications of some of their actions or present them as morally innocent. I will begin by outlining Kant’s conception of ordinary cognition of duty and of self-deception or rationalizing (sec. 1). I will then provide a brief overview of possible functions of conscience in Kant and explain Kant’s conception of conscience as a reflective watch-dog: Conscience does not judge directly about our duty in concrete cases but it watches over or reflects about how cautiously an agent uses her rational capacities when she reasons about concrete matters of duty (sec. 2). Finally, I will argue that Kant’s model of an internal court of conscience is inadequate to account for the pervasive threat self-deception poses. I will propose a modified model instead, which I call “internal-panel-model” (sec. 3). …

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
For older pieces on conscience see Gerhard Funke, “Gutes Gewissen, falsches Bewußtsein, richtende Vernunft,” Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 25(1971): 226–51, H. J. Paton, “Conscience and Kant,” Kant-Studien 70 (1979): 239–51, Willem Heubült, “Gewissen bei Kant,” Kant-Studien 71 (1980): 445–54 and Hill’s essays reprinted in Thomas Hill JR., Human Welfare and Moral Worth: Kantian Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002). For recent literature see David Velleman, “The Voice of Conscience,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1999): 57–76, Thomas S. Hoffmann, “Gewissen als praktische Apperzeption. Zur Lehre vom Gewissen in Kants Ethik-Vorlesungen,” Kant-Studien 93 (2002): 424–43, Jens Timmermann, “Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,” International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006): 293–308, Dean Moyar, “Unstable Autonomy: Conscience and Judgment in Kant’s Moral Philosophy,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 5 (2008): 327–60, Allen Wood, Kantian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), ch.10, Owen Ware, “The Duty of Self-Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (2009): 671–98, Paul Guyer, “Moral feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals,” in Lara Denis (ed.), Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 130–52, Andrea Esser, “The Inner Court of Conscience, Moral Self-Knowledge, and the roper Object of Duty (TL 6:437–444),” in: Andreas Trampota, Oliver Sensen, Jens Timmermann (eds.), Kant’s “Tugendlehre”. A Comprehensive Commentary (Berlin/Boston; de Gruyter, 2013), 269–93, Marijana Vujošević, “The Judge in the Mirror: Kant on Conscience,” Kantian Review 19 (2014): 449–74, Elke Schmidt, Dieter Schönecker, “Kants Philosophie des Gewissens. Skizze für eine kommentarische Interpretation,” in Mario Egger (ed.), Philosophie nach Kant. Neue Wege zum Verständnis von Kants Transzendental- und Moralphilosophie (Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter, 2014), 279–312, Elke Schmidt, Dieter Schönecker, “Vernunft, Herz und Gewissen. Kants Theorie der Urteilskraft zweiter Stufe als Modell für die Medizinische Ethik,” in Franz-Josef Bormann, Vera Wetzstein (eds.), Gewissen. Dimensionen eines Grundbegriffs medizinischer Ethik (Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter, 2014), 229–50, Oliver Sensen “Kants Begriff des Gewissens,” in Simon Bunke, Katerina Mihaylova (eds.), Gewissen zwischen Gefühl und Vernunft (Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann, 2015), 126–38, Samuel Kahn, “Kant’s Theory of Conscience,” in Pablo Muchnik, Oliver Thorndike (eds.), Rethinking Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, forthcoming).
 
2
See Jens Timmermann, “Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,” International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006): 293–308.
 
3
See Moyar, op. cit.
 
4
See Ware, op. cit.
 
5
See Paul Guyer, “Moral feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals,” in Lara Denis (ed.), Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 130–152.
 
6
Moyar, op. cit., p. 328, by contrast, believes that Kant’s conception of conscience between 1791 and 1797 “shows a remarkable lack of uniformity”. The most notable tension in Kant’s conception of conscience in the 1790s is due to claims Kant makes about conscience as an Aesthetical Preliminary Concept in the Introduction to the Doctrine of Virtue.
 
7
I quote Kant according to Kant’s geammelte Schriften, edited by the Königlich Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin: Georg Reimer). The First Critique is quoted according to the A/B edition. The Kaehler Lecture Notes (LK) are quoted from Werner Stark (ed.), Immanuel Kant. Vorlesung zur Moralphilosophie (Berlin/New York: de Gruyter, 2004). Translations from the Groundwork are from Jens Timmermann, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Translated by Jens Timmermann and Mary Gregor) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011). Other works by Kant are quoted, with occasional modifications, from the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant edited by Paul Guyer and Allan Wood. Translations of untranslated texts are my own.
 
8
There is consensus in the Kant literature that conscience is not primarily concerned with first-order matters. A notable exception is Paul Guyer, “Moral feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals,” in Lara Denis (ed.), Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 130–52, pp. 145–6 who sees conscience as a capacity “to seek and listen to the kind of moral law that applies to particular cases, namely, particular maxims”, i.e., to apply general moral rules to particular cases (seeking) and being motivated to obey these rules (listening). Esser, op. cit., p. 277fn.16 convincingly argues that the idea that conscience is a form of power of judgment, which applies general rules to particular cases, rests on a misinterpretation of a passage in the Religion (VI:186.10–1).
 
9
“I ask myself” (IV:403.3–6), “I just ask myself” (IV:403.21), “he still has enough conscience to ask himself” (IV:422.19), “[y]et he still asks himself” (IV:423.2–5).
 
10
See also IV:421.24–423.35, V:27.22, 36.4–6, 44.2–3, 69.20–70.9.
 
11
The previous two paragraphs are a condensed version of Martin Sticker, “The Moral-Psychology of the Common Agent – A Reply to Ido Geiger,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (2015): 976–89. There I also discuss the moral-epistemological function of humanity or rational nature, which I have to bracket here.
 
12
This is the explanation advanced by Jens Timmermann, “Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,” International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006): 293–308.
 
13
I will follow Jens Timmermann, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Translated by Jens Timmermann and Mary Gregor) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011) and use “rationalizing” as a translation of “Vernünfteln”.
 
14
For exemplary cases of rationalizing see for instance VI:70.fn., 77.26–78.2, 168.8–170.11, 192.1–202.5, 430.19–26, VIII:265.28–266.5, LK:154–7, 192–3. There is a growing interest in rationalizing in the Kant literature. See Dieter Schönecker, “Gemeine sittliche und philosophische Vernunfterkenntnis. Zum ersten Übergang in Kants Grundlegung,” Kant-Studien 88 (1997): 311–33, Paul Guyer, Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), Adrian Piper, Rationality and the Structure of the Self. Volume II: A Kantian Conception (2008) online: http://​www.​adrianpiper.​com/​rss/​index.​shtml, Martin Sticker, “Educating the Common Agent. Kant on the Varieties of Moral Education,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 97 (2015): 358–87, sec. 3, Marcel van Ackeren, Martin Sticker, “Kant and Moral Demandingness,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (2015): 75–89, sec. 3.
 
15
Kant uses the strong “i.e.” [d.i.] [5] “this is” to characterize the relation between the natural dialectic and the propensity to rationalize.
 
16
Again Kant uses the strong “i.e.” [9]. Adapting one’s conception of morality and corruption is identical.
 
17
See also VI:36.1–33, 321.38–9, XXIX:609.34–6, 629.2–5.
 
18
Kant claims that the agent who makes an exception for himself, as opposed to the agent who adopts an immoral rule as his maxim, still “can at the same time detest his transgression” (VI:321.38, see also ibid., 379–380.fn.). I loosely follow J. L. Austin, “A plea for excuses,” in J. L. Austin (ed.), Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), p. 176 distinction between justifications and excuses. In the former case someone accepts responsibility but denies that an action was bad, in the latter case someone accepts that an action was bad but denies full, or even any, responsibility.
 
19
See XVIII:579.4–5, XXVII:613.37–614.9, Moyar, op. cit., p. 350, Vujošević, op. cit.
 
20
See VI:400.30 and Paul Guyer’s, “Moral feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals,” in Lara Denis (ed.), Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 130–52, pp. 145–6 reading of conscience as part of an empirically informed theory of moral motivation. Moyar, op. cit., sec. 6, like Guyer, stresses the authority and motivational role of conscience. He, however, adds the caveat that this stress is a Fichte inspired reading of Kant. Vujošević, op. cit., p. 450 argues that “conscience itself is not a moral motive”, but it “has an inescapable role to play in the process of our motivation to act morally”.
 
21
See for instance Hill, op. cit., p. 280–1. Moyar, op. cit., p. 338 believes that conscience is a reflective capacity “directed at my process of judgment and my grounds for thinking that I have done the best that I possibly can in arriving at my judgment”. Moyar (ibid., p. 345) also argues that Kant “invests conscience with so much authority that the first-order/second-order distinction becomes completely untenable”, or that the question: “Is this the right maxim?” is indistinguishable from: “Do I believe that this is the right action?” (see ibid., p. 346). I do not share this criticism: The two orders only collapse if conscience judges about the certainty of beliefs. Conscience, however, judges about an agent’s way of reasoning (see below). The question conscience asks is rather: “Did I reason about a situation with due caution?”. This is different from the question what maxim or action is right. First- and second-order judgements are about different objects (actions/maxims vs. reasoning) and they employ different methods (universalization tests vs. critical self-examination). See also Jeanine Grenberg, Kant's Defense of Common Moral Experience. A Phenomenological Account (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), p. 180fn.10 who argues convincingly that Kant does not collapse the two questions.
 
22
Moyar, op. cit., has sympathy for this reading. Textual support for such a much more fundamental role of conscience than what the other passages on conscience support is in VI:399.1–403.6.
 
23
Jens Timmermann, “Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,” International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006): 293–308, p. 295 notes that this reflective function of conscience is coherent with the standard Protestant conception of conscience at the time as something more narrow than an agent’s sense of right and wrong. He (ibid., p. 295) argues that conscience is “the power […] – within every human agent – that acknowledges the need to conform to moral standards”. The moral standards themselves are provided by reason, not conscience.
 
24
Jens Timmermann, “Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,” International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006): 293–308, p. 306 believes that the “possibility of objective errors [about my duty in concrete cases] […] seems to undermine the very foundation of Kantian ethics”, namely, the idea that every rational human agent has insight into what she is morally required to do. On Timmermann’s conception agents can fail to act on what they are aware of as obligatory, but they cannot have false beliefs about what their duty is in a concrete situation. My interpretation of conscience, in contrast to Timmermann’s, accommodates mistakes in objective judgements without undermining the foundation of Kant’s ethics. Rational agents always have what it takes to reach the correct judgment in moral matters, namely, the ability to make use of the standard of universality (see sec. 1.1). If they reason incorrectly they can be held morally accountable for it, since it would have been possible and sufficiently easy for them to judge correctly.
 
25
See also VIII:268.7–8. Allen Wood, George Di Giovanni, Religion and Rational Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 203 translate “Behutsamkeit” as “diligence”. “Caution” better preserves the original meaning of the word: to be aware of or to protect oneself of danger (see Johann Christoph Adelung, Grammatisch-kritisches Wörterbuch der hochdeutschen Mundart (1811), online: http://​lexika.​digitale-sammlungen.​de/​adelung/​online/​angebot vol. 1, col. 817–8). I am grateful to Jens Timmermann for suggesting the term “caution”.
 
26
The same is true of the term “conscientious” and the German “gewissenhaft”. Both aptly describe the working of conscience as concerned with the question as to whether agents reached their moral convictions in a reliable way. Oliver Sensen “Kants Begriff des Gewissens,” in Simon Bunke, Katerina Mihaylova (eds.), Gewissen zwischen Gefühl und Vernunft (Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann, 2015), 126–38, pp. 127–8 argues plausibly that being conscientious for Kant means that a moral judgment was “cautiously examined” [sorgfältig geprüft] by the agent (see also ibid., pp. 130–1).
 
27
In the Vigilantius lecture notes from 1793/4 conscientiousness appears as a matter of a “sincere examination” [aufrichtige Prüfung] of what we take to be certain (XXVII:615.19). It is the role of conscience “to obtain consciousness that one has performed the examination with great thought” (XXVII:619.27–8). See also Vujošević, op. cit., p. 465) who believes that conscience assesses “our way of judging whether an action is right or wrong”. Vujošević, however, is not always clear about the object of assessment. She claims that conscience judges our “maxim-formation and adoption” (ibid.) or incentives (ibid., p. 470). The latter seems very different from our way of reasoning.
 
28
In Vigilantius the inquisitor is said to “take himself to be justified” in his deeds (XXVII:615.29).
 
29
Esser, op. cit., p. 283–4 thinks that conscience is not supposed to scrutinize the use of rational capacities, but the motives of actions (see also Vujošević, op. cit., p. 461). This interpretation is contradicted by the inquisitor case. The inquisitor got wrong the question what his duty is. He does not merely lack the right motivation. Elke Schmidt, Dieter Schönecker, “Kants Philosophie des Gewissens. Skizze für eine kommentarische Interpretation,” in Mario Egger (ed.), Philosophie nach Kant. Neue Wege zum Verständnis von Kants Transzendental- und Moralphilosophie (Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter, 2014), 279–312, p. 283 make a very convincing case against the idea that the scrutiny of conscience extends to motivation: If conscience pronounced a verdict about the motives of actions, it should be possible to know whether our actions are morally worthy, something Kant strenuously denies (A/B:278/334, 551/579, VI: 25.5–6, 38.7–12, 51.7–21, 70.1–71.20, 75.8–76.1, VI.451.21–36).
 
30
See explicitly “when it comes, or has come, to a deed, conscience speaks involuntary and unavoidably” (VI:401.15–6). See also XXVII:198.17–24.
 
31
Ware, op. cit., p. 693.
 
32
The standard conception of conscience at the time was that conscience can err. See Baumgarten reprinted in Kant’s Academy Edition (XXVII:781) and Christian August Crusius, Anweisung vernünftig zu leben, Darinen nach Erklärung der Natur des Menschlichen Willens die natürlichen Pflichten und allgemeinen Klugheitslehren im richtigen Zusammenhang vorgetragen werden (Leipzig, 31767), §138–41. In pre-critical lectures Kant himself thought of conscience as fallible (XXVII:42.32–7, 197.36–198.9, 354.39–355.27).
 
33
Paton, op. cit., is very skeptical of Kant’s infallibility claim and argues, correctly I believe, that we can only make sense of it, if we understand conscience as being about second-order matters.
 
34
Hill, op. cit., p. 302–3.fn.50 suggests that conscience judges always correctly, but we might fail to submit an action to the scrutiny of conscience. The claim that conscience cannot err is therefore somewhat “exaggerated” (Hill ibid., p. 241, see also ibid., p. 348). I agree that the claim is exaggerated, but for almost the opposite reason as Hill: The verdict of conscience can err, but an agent cannot be mistaken as to whether she submitted her moral judgement to the scrutiny of conscience.
 
35
Other deflationary readings who rather aim to explain the claim away are Wood, op. cit., pp. 190–1, Ware, op. cit., pp. 692–5. Wood, op. cit., explicitly acknowledges the difficulty of understanding the infallibility claim in the context of self-deception.
 
36
Wanting to serve and praise God without moral sincerity is an “opiate for conscience” and “a cushion” on which conscience is meant to “sleep quietly” (IX:495.13–5). In pre-critical lecture notes, Kant speaks of “numbing” [übertäuben] and “giving leave” [Ferien geben] to our internal judge (LK:135, see also XXVII:357.4–5).
 
37
See VI:400.31–33, 401.10–11, 438.13–23.
 
38
See also VI:38.12–7, 174.27–30, 333.33–4, VIII:268.26–269.1 for examples of agents who falsely deem themselves morally justified. In the Vigilantius lecture notes, Kant calls the attempt to directly deceive conscience “sophistry” and gives a number of short examples (XXVII:619.36–620.8).
 
39
See also V:98.13–28, XXVII:197.19–36, 295.12–36, 351.22–357.5, 572.13–573.24.
 
40
See Sofie Møller, “The Court of Reason in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason,” Kant-Studien 104 (2013): 301–20 for a recent discussion of judicial metaphors in the First Critique.
 
41
See XIX:83.11–35. Baumgarten’s Initia is reprinted in volume XIX of the Academy Edition.
 
42
See Manfred Kuehn, “Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: the history and significance of its deferral,” in Lara Denis (ed.), Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 9–28, sec. 3 for more on Baumgarten’s influence on Kant.
 
43
Kant elaborates on his distinction between the homines elsewhere in the Metaphysics of Morals and in his lectures of the 1790s. See VI:239.21–30, 335.17–22, 418.18, 423.5, 434.22–435.5, 439.30–1, XXIII:398.11–2, XXVII:579.29–30, 593.6–22. Sharon Byrd, Joachim Hruschka, Kant’s Doctrine of Right. A Commentary (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), ch. 14 point to Linné’s Systema Naturae as an important scientific influence on Kant for this distinction, as well as to the traditional Roman law distinction between a thing and a person.
 
44
See VI:239.26, 418.5, 434.32, XXVII:504.29, 505.5, 39, 510.5, 579.17–8. Oliver Sensen, “The moral importance of autonomy,” in Oliver Sensen (ed.), Kant on Moral Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 262–282, p. 269 argues with reference to IV:440, VI:418, XXVII:593, 610, 626 that the homo noumenon “is not an obscure metaphysical being, but what a human being conceives himself to be according to the Categorical Imperative”.
 
45
See Byrd, Hruschka, op. cit., pp. 281–2: “As a thing, the homo phaenomenon has no duties, which in turn means that he has no rights or moral faculties” (ibid., p. 281). However, in the Vigilantius lecture notes, the human being in appearance or homo phaenomenon seems to be able to be morally obligated by one’s rational self (XXVII:579.8–580.22, 593.1–16, 601.30–5). It certainly is an intricate issue to discern how to understand Kant's distinctions between the homines in various places. I will focus on Kant’s official account in the Metaphysics of Morals. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this issue.
 
46
Oliver Sensen, Kant on Human Dignity (Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter, 2011), p. 130 emphasizes that the homo phaenomenon is “the human being as observable in experience” and as such entirely a creature of the phenomenal world. The homo noumenon, by contrast, is “a moral ideal that might not be observed in experience, but that is prescribed by reason”. For the difficult (causal) relation between the homini when it comes to moral actions see Byrd, Hruschka, op. cit., p. 288–9.
 
47
VI:439.fn.35, see also VI:440.20–4, XXVII:197.30–2, 618.23–4, LK:193, 200. In the Collins lecture notes from the 1770s Kant specifies that our “advocate” before the internal court is “self-love”, which “excuses [the agent] and makes many an objection to the accusation” (XXVII:354.20–1).
 
48
Elke Schmidt, Dieter Schönecker, “Kants Philosophie des Gewissens. Skizze für eine kommentarische Interpretation,” in Mario Egger (ed.), Philosophie nach Kant. Neue Wege zum Verständnis von Kants Transzendental- und Moralphilosophie (Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter, 2014), 279–312, pp. 290–1, 301–11, Elke Schmidt, Dieter Schönecker, “Vernunft, Herz und Gewissen. Kants Theorie der Urteilskraft zweiter Stufe als Modell für die Medizinische Ethik,” in Franz-Josef Bormann, Vera Wetzstein (eds.), Gewissen. Dimensionen eines Grundbegriffs medizinischer Ethik (Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter, 2014), 229–250, p. 243 criticise the obscurity of Kant’s judicial metaphors for the functioning of conscience. I am more optimistic than they are that something can be made of Kant’s descriptions if we rationally reconstruct them.
 
49
Self-deception is in any case a violation of the “First Command of all Duties to oneself […] know (scrutinize, fathom) yourself” (VI:441.2–4). See Ware, op. cit., for more on the duty to know oneself and the danger of self-deception.
 
50
Lucas Thorpe, “The Point of Studying Ethics According to Kant,” The Journal of Value Inquiry 40 (2006): 461–74, p. 468.
 
51
See Thorpe, op. cit., p. 469–70.
 
52
This conception is supported by VI:430.27–35 where self-deception is described not as requiring the active interaction of different faculties of an agent’s mind but rather as an agent giving in to biases. In the pre-critical Kaehler/Collins lecture notes it is pointed out that human beings have a tendency to rather “listen” to their internal advocate than to their prosecutor (LK:193, XXVII:354.28–9).
 
53
In the lecture notes Powalski, presumably from around 1782/3, the activity of our internal advocate is explicitly called “sophistry” (XXVII:197.36).
 
54
According to pre-critical lectures, the judgements of conscience are infallible, unless conscience uses a false standard of judgement (LK:193–4, XXVII:354.26–8).
 
55
See also VI:399.4–14. See Jens Timmermann, “Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,” International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006): 293–308, sec. 2–3 for a discussion of the normative status of indirect duty.
 
56
In Collins, Kant calls a conscience that errs on the side of the prosecutor a “melancholic conscience” [schwermütiges Gewissen] (XXVII:356.38).
 
Metadata
Title
When the Reflective Watch-Dog Barks: Conscience and Self-Deception in Kant
Author
Martin Sticker
Publication date
03-06-2016
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
The Journal of Value Inquiry / Issue 1/2017
Print ISSN: 0022-5363
Electronic ISSN: 1573-0492
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-016-9559-4

Other articles of this Issue 1/2017

The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2017 Go to the issue

OriginalPaper

The Right Balance