Skip to main content
Erschienen in: The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2016

31.05.2015

Enkratic Reasoning and Incommensurability of Reasons

verfasst von: Mathea S. Sagdahl

Erschienen in: The Journal of Value Inquiry | Ausgabe 1/2016

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Excerpt

There is fairly wide agreement that in order to provide an adequate theory of agency, we need to account for the central role of enkratic reasoning – the type of practical reasoning where an agent reasons to an intention to F from a belief that the agent ‘ought all things considered’ or has ‘most reason’ to F. Any view that admits of a widespread and systematic incommensurability of reasons, however, seems to have trouble with accounting for the centrality of this type of reasoning. If the reasons that apply to us tend to be incommensurable, then it seems that we cannot assess those reasons together, and so, it seems, neither can we arrive at any conclusion about what we ought all things considered, or have most reason, to do. This seems to leave little room for enkratic reasoning, and so views that admit of a widespread and systematic incommensurability of agency might be accused of not being able to account for our conception of agency. …

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
Raz, Joseph, “Incommensurability and Agency”, in Chang, Ruth (Ed.), Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997), 111.
 
2
Raz is actually concerned with the incommensurability of “value”, but he also says that the fact that an option has a certain value is the paradigmatic reason for action. Raz therefore seems equally committed to the incommensurability of reasons. Ibid., 125.
 
3
Ruth Chang interprets Raz’s claims about incommensurability to represent what she calls “incomparability”. Chang, Ruth, “Introduction”, in Chang, Ruth (Ed.), Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, 10. However, I think that Raz’s remark that “incommensurability is the absence of a common measure” is important, as it may be taken to mean that incommensurability should rather be interpreted as what Chang calls “non-comparability”. With non-comparability, reasons fail to compare for formal reasons, because of an absence of a covering value. At least this seems to be the correct way to understand the other proponents of incommensurability that I discuss here, namely Sidgwick and Copp.
 
4
Broome, John, Rationality Through Reasoning (Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, 2013), 23.
 
5
Ibid.
 
6
Copp, David, “Toward a Pluralist and Teleological Theory of Normativity”, Philosophical Issues 19 (2009): 21–37.
 
7
Normative pluralism is often dismissed due to what is known as the argument from nominal-notable comparisons. I have argued elsewhere that this is in fact not a strong objection against the position. Mathea S. Sagdahl, “The Argument from Nominal-Notable Comparisons”, The Journal of Ethics 18: 405–425. The other major objection to normative pluralism concerns its purported view of practical reasoning, which is the issue I address here.
 
8
Copp, David, “The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason”, in David Copp (Ed.), Morality in a Natural World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 285.
 
9
Frankena, William, “Sidgwick and the History of Ethical Dualism”, in Bart Schultz (Ed.), Essays on Henry Sidgwick (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 194.
 
10
Sidgwick, Henry, The Methods of Ethics (third edition), (Milton Keynes: Lightening Source, 2009), 401–402.
 
11
Parfit, On What Matters vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 132–133.
 
12
Broome, Rationality through Reasoning, 29.
 
13
Interestingly, Copp is only interested in denying that there is ever an overall verdict as to what action is required simpliciter, in situations where morality and self-interest conflicts. He is consistently silent on the status of the plain ought when morality and self-interest do not conflict. The current proposal would allow him to say that while we cannot make a verdict about what action is required simpliciter in the absence of conflict, we can make a verdict about what action one ought to do all things considered.
 
14
By ‘relevant’, I mean a standpoint that is genuinely normative and that takes the choice situation under its domain of adjudication. For example, the ‘aesthetic’ standpoint, if there is any, is arguably only evaluative rather than normative, and does not tell us what we ought to do. There are interesting questions regarding the nature and identification of normative standpoints, but I cannot go into them here.
 
15
The truth of this claim depends on the supposition that we can avoid a hyperinflation of normative standpoints and the number of normative oughts. The more oughts in play, the less agreement will there tend to be. Evan Tiffany’s version of normative pluralism clearly involves such a hyperinflation. Tiffany, Evan, “Deflationary Normative Pluralism”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 37 (2007) Supplement [vol. 33]: 231–262.
 
16
Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning, 152.
 
17
Ibid., 26 and 28.
 
18
Although I have treated the original and the Weak Enkratic requirement as constituting two different requirements of rationality governing two different normative beliefs, an alternative is to think that there is only one enkratic requirement which is neutral with respect to how it represents an ought all things considered belief. On that construal, my proposal instead specifies another way in which that neutral requirement could apply to you. I don’t think anything of importance hangs on how these requirements are to be individuated.
 
19
This emphasis on the will is what seems to have led Chang into labeling Raz’s view as quasi-existentialist. See Chang, “Introduction”, footnote 20, 257.
 
20
Richard Holton, Willing, Wanting, Waiting (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), x and 68.
 
21
Ibid., 60.
 
22
Chang thinks that it is a problem if the difference between equality and incomparability is not “practically marked in some way”. Chang, “Are Hard Choices Cases of Incomparability?”, Philosophical Issues 22 (2012): 106–126, 122. I am not sure why she thinks it would be a problem, but the features I point to can in any case be understood as reflecting that difference.
 
23
Holton, Willing, Wanting, Waiting, 129–133.
 
24
Chang, “Are Hard Choices Cases of Incomparability?”, 114.
 
25
Ibid., 115.
 
26
Regan, Donald, “Value, Comparability, and Choice”, in Ruth Chang (Ed.), Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, 144.
 
27
Chang, “Are Hard Choices cases of Incomparability?”, 117. In Chang’s defence, it should be said that she thinks the classical conception of human agency addresses this worry, but she also rejects this conception of human agency.
 
28
For the distinction between choosing and picking, see Edna Ullmann-Margalit and Sidney Morgenbesser, “Picking and Choosing”, in Social Research 44 (1977): 757–785. With respect to the technical definitions given by the authors, choice between incomparables or incommensurables cannot fall under either category, since the categories are simply defined as choice under more reason or preference to select one option, and choice under equal reason or preference to select either option, respectively.
 
29
For choice as an act, see Holton, Willing, Wanting, Waiting, 54.
 
Metadaten
Titel
Enkratic Reasoning and Incommensurability of Reasons
verfasst von
Mathea S. Sagdahl
Publikationsdatum
31.05.2015
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
The Journal of Value Inquiry / Ausgabe 1/2016
Print ISSN: 0022-5363
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-0492
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-015-9489-6

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2016

The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2016 Zur Ausgabe