Skip to main content

Legal Formalism, Procedural Principles, and Judicial Constraint in American Adjudication

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
General Principles of Law - The Role of the Judiciary

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 46))

Abstract

American proponents of legal formalism, such as Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia, worry (quite reasonably) that unfettered judicial discretion poses a threat to democratic legitimacy, and they offer formalism—the mechanical implementation of determinate legal rules—as a solution to this threat. I argue here, however, that formalist interpretive techniques are neither sufficient nor necessary to impose meaningful constraint on judges. Both the text and the “original meaning” of legal rules are endemically under-determinate, leaving much room for judicial discretion in the decision of cases. But meaningful judicial constraint can and does flow from other sources in American adjudication. Judges are constrained by the dispute-resolving posture of their task, which requires that they be impartial as between the litigants and responsive to the litigants’ participatory efforts. And they are constrained by the need to be faithful to the substantive principles that justify legal rules, even when those rules themselves are indeterminate. Judicial constraint in the American system thus stems not primarily from formalist interpretative methods, but rather from largely unwritten procedural principles of judicial impartiality, responsiveness, and faithfulness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Scalia (1989a), pp. 863–864.

  2. 2.

    In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle (1941) wrote: “[A]ll law is universal but about some things it is not possible to make a universal statement which shall be correct. In those cases, then, in which it is necessary to speak universally, but not possible to do so correctly, the law takes the usual case, though it is not ignorant of the possibility of error. And it is none the less correct; for the error is not in the law nor in the legislator but in the nature of the thing, since the matter of practical affairs is of this kind from the start” (p. 1020).

  3. 3.

    For an argument to this effect, focused on judicial application of rules gleaned from precedent, see Hellman (2014).

  4. 4.

    See, for example, Scalia (1989b), p. 1179.

  5. 5.

    Sunstein (1997), p. 530.

  6. 6.

    See United States Constitution, Article III(1): “The Judges, both of the supreme and inferior Courts, shall hold their Offices during good Behaviour, and shall, at stated Times, receive for their Services a Compensation, which shall not be diminished during their Continuance in Office”.

  7. 7.

    The obvious apparent exception is the prior judges whose decisions often are applied as precedents by current judges. Where these precedents interpret the work of institutions that are politically accountable to current majorities—statutes enacted by legislatures and regulations adopted by administrative agencies—their continued existence might be seen as implicit acquiescence in their substance by these accountable institutions (the legislature could simply overturn incorrect interpretations of its statutes by amending the statute in question). On this theory, respect for prior judicial decisions might be understood as a form of subservience to democratically more-accountable institutions. Matters are more obscure where the judicial precedent interprets a constitutional provision and thus is very difficult to correct by means of constitutional amendment. Many formalists thus distrust the presumptive American practice of adhering to constitutional precedent (see Peters (2014), pp. 189–198), although Justice Scalia himself professes to accept the practice (see Scalia (1989a), p. 861): “[A]lmost every originalist would adulterate [originalism] with the doctrine of stare decisis”.

  8. 8.

    See Hart (1958), p. 607 and Fuller (1958), pp. 662–663.

  9. 9.

    Hart (1958), p. 607.

  10. 10.

    Ibid.

  11. 11.

    Fuller (1958), p. 663.

  12. 12.

    Hart (1958), p. 607.

  13. 13.

    Scalia (1997), pp. 23–24.

  14. 14.

    18 USC § 924(c) (1).

  15. 15.

    508 US 223, 241, 242 (1993) (Scalia, J., dissenting).

  16. 16.

    The decision in question is United States v. Windsor, 133 S. Ct. 2675 (2013).

  17. 17.

    Scalia (1989a; 1997).

  18. 18.

    For an originalist’s account of the general rejection, among originalists, of “original intent” originalism in favor of “original public meaning” originalism, see Solum (2011), pp. 6–17. For influential critiques of “original intent” originalism as indeterminate, see Brest (1980); Dworkin (1985), pp. 34–57.

  19. 19.

    See Urofsky and Finkelman (2011), pp. 201–205.

  20. 20.

    Ibid., p. 204. See also Ellis (2001), pp. 198–201.

  21. 21.

    Ellis (2001), p. 191.

  22. 22.

    Scalia (1989a), pp. 856–857.

  23. 23.

    See Barnett (2004), pp. 118–130 and Solum (2010).

  24. 24.

    Barnett (2004), p. 121.

  25. 25.

    Ibid., p. 120.

  26. 26.

    The discussion in this section is drawn from Peters (2011), pp. 155–160 and 310–328; see also Peters (1997), pp. 347–60.

  27. 27.

    See, e.g., Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife, 504 US 555 (1992); Allen v. Wright, 468 US 737 (1984).

  28. 28.

    The Seventh Amendment to the federal Constitution guarantees the right to a jury trial in many civil cases in federal court, but this right may be waived by the parties. In both federal and State courts, the litigants typically participate in the process of choosing jurors, known as voir dire, by asking questions of prospective jurors (either directly or by submitting them to the judge), by moving to exclude prospective jurors “for cause”, and by exercising “peremptory challenges” to strike a certain number of jurors without cause.

  29. 29.

    In fact, procedural rules and statutes in the United States increasingly encourage out-of-court settlement of disputes, and far more cases “settle” than go to trial in American courts. See Galanter and Cahill (1994). There are exceptions, however, to the baseline principle that judicial approval is not required for settlement, such as class-action lawsuits, where judicial approval is required in order to protect the interests of absent class members. See Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 23. And while the terms of settlements rarely require judicial approval, it is commonplace that judges use various means to encourage the litigants to settle. See Galanter and Cahill (1994).

  30. 30.

    In the federal court system, the requirement of a final judgment as a condition of appeal is codified in 28 USC § 1291. There are a number of exceptions to this requirement, one of which allows the trial judge, of her own accord, to “certify” certain issues for immediate appeal. See 28 USC § 1292(b). The “final judgment” requirement for appeal is less stringent in many State court systems. In the federal courts, the requirement that an appeal from a final judgment may be taken only by an aggrieved party has been held to be at least partly constitutional in stature, flowing from Article III’s grant of the federal judicial power to decide only “cases” and “controversies”. See Hollingsworth v. Perry, 133 S. Ct. 2652 (2013); United States v. Windsor, 133 S. Ct. 2675, 2684-2689 (2013).

  31. 31.

    Such as Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 52, which requires federal judges who serve as triers of fact to write opinions justifying their decisions on both factual and legal grounds.

  32. 32.

    Formalists often recognize the practical constraint imposed by the American adversary model of adjudication. Justice Scalia, for example, advocates strict adherence to justiciability requirements as a way to limit judicial power. See United States v. Windsor cit. (Scalia, J., dissenting) (criticizing the majority’s willingness to recognize standing to appeal in the case as reflecting “an exalted conception of the role of [the Supreme Court] in America”). This recognition sits somewhat uneasily alongside the professed belief that formalist interpretive techniques can meaningfully constrain judges. If formalism imposes significant constraint, it is unclear why the additional measure of strict justiciability limitations is necessary.

  33. 33.

    Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 US 306 (2003); Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 US 244 (2003).

  34. 34.

    “No State shall … deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws”.

  35. 35.

    See Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School District No. 1, 555 US 701 (2007). Between 2003 (when Grutter and Gratz were decided) and 2007, Justice O’Connor had left the Court, replaced by the more-conservative Justice Samuel Alito (who voted with the majority in Parents Involved). In addition, Chief Justice Rehnquist had died and been replaced by John Roberts, but that change did not affect the Court’s attitude toward race-conscious affirmative action, which both Rehnquist and Roberts opposed.

  36. 36.

    See Parents Involved cit., at 723 (“In upholding the admissions plan in Grutter, … this Court relied upon considerations unique to institutions of higher education …”).

  37. 37.

    Grutter v. Bollinger, 127 F. Supp. 2d 821 (E.D. Mich. 2001). Federal district (trial) court judges are required by rule to expressly state the findings of fact and the rulings of law upon which their final judgments are based. See Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 52.

  38. 38.

    Gratz v. Bollinger cit., 282 (Stevens, J., dissenting).

  39. 39.

    Dworkin (1978), pp. 22–28.

  40. 40.

    Ibid., p. 24.

  41. 41.

    Ibid., p. 26.

  42. 42.

    Ibid.

  43. 43.

    Ibid., p. 22.

  44. 44.

    The discussion that follows is drawn from Peters (2011), pp. 176–181.

  45. 45.

    Hart (1958), p. 607.

  46. 46.

    Cf. Hart and Sacks (1994), p. 1378: “Why would reasonable men, confronted with the law as it was, have enacted this new law to replace it? The most reliable guides to an answer will be found in the instances of unquestioned application of the statute”.

  47. 47.

    Dworkin probably would refer to it more specifically as a “policy”—“a kind of standard that sets out a goal to be reached, generally an improvement in some economic, political, or social feature of the community”. See Dworkin (1978), p. 22. Or it might be called the “purpose” behind the ordinance: “the set of reasons for making those words a fixed part of the body of the law”. See Wellman (1987), p. 463.

  48. 48.

    Dworkin (1978), p. 26.

  49. 49.

    See Peters (2011), pp. 78–81.

  50. 50.

    28 USC § 455(a).

  51. 51.

    A ban on comment about active legal issues imposed on judicial nominees or candidates might run afoul of the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. The Supreme Court has invalidated on First Amendment grounds a state law forbidding an elective judicial candidate to “announce his or her views on disputed legal or political issues”. See Republican Party of Minnesota v. White, 536 US 765 (2002).

  52. 52.

    Ibid., at 778 (emphases in original). The Court in White acknowledged that preserving judicial impartiality in this sense might be a compelling state interest, but it nonetheless invalidated the limitation on judicial-candidate speech in that case on the ground that it was not in fact intended to serve that interest.

  53. 53.

    See Peters (2001), pp. 25–27.

  54. 54.

    Fuller (1978), p. 388.

  55. 55.

    Damaška (1986); Peters (1997), p. 349.

  56. 56.

    Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 52(a).

  57. 57.

    Dworkin (1978; 1986).

  58. 58.

    There is of course much writing by American judges themselves regarding how they understand their duties. For a classic judicial statement of this understanding that accords with the principle of faithfulness, see Cardozo (1921).

References

  • Aristotle. 1941. Nicomachean Ethics. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, 927-1112. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, Randy E. 2004. Restoring the Lost Constitution: The Presumption of Liberty. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brest, Paul. 1980. The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding. Boston University Law Review 60: 204-238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cardozo, Benjamin N. 1921. The Nature of the Judicial Process. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damaška, Mirjan R. 1986. The Faces of Justice and State Authority: A Comparative Approach to the Legal Process. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1985. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, Joseph J. 2001. Founding Brothers: The Revolutionary Generation. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon L. 1958. Positivism and Fidelity to Law – A Reply to Professor Hart. Harvard Law Review 71: 630-672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon L. 1978. The Forms and Limits of Adjudication. Harvard Law Review 92: 353-409.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galanter, Marc, and Mia Cahill. 1994. ‘Most Cases Settle’: Judicial Promotion and Regulation of Settlement. Stanford Law Review 46: 1339-1392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L. A. 1958. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard Law Review 71: 593-629.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Henry M., Jr., and Albert Sacks. 1994. The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law, eds. William N. Eskridge, Jr. and Philip P. Frickey. Westbury: Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, Deborah. 2014. An Epistemic Defense of Precedent. In Precedent in the United States Supreme Court, ed. Christopher J. Peters, 189-226. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Christopher J. 1997. Adjudication as Representation. Columbia Law Review 97: 312-436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Christopher J. 2001, Persuasion: A Model of Majoritarianism as Adjudication. Northwestern University Law Review 96: 1-37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Christopher J. 2011. A Matter of Dispute: Morality, Democracy, and Law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Christopher J. 2014. Originalism, Stare Decisis, and Constitutional Authority. In Precedent in the United States Supreme Court, ed. Christopher J. Peters, 189-226. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia, Antonin G. 1989a. Originalism: The Lesser Evil. University of Cincinnati Law Review 57: 849-865.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia, Antonin G. 1989b. The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules. University of Chicago Law Review 56: 1175-1188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia, Antonin G. 1997. Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws. In A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law, ed. Amy Gutmann, 3-47. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solum, Lawrence B. 2011. What Is Originalism? The Evolution of Contemporary Originalist Theory. http://ssrn.com/abstract=1825543.

  • Solum, Lawrence B. 2010. The Interpretation-Construction Distinction. Constitutional Commentary 27: 95-118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass. 1997. Justice Scalia’s Democratic Formalism. Yale Law Journal 107: 529-68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urofsky, Melvin, and Paul Finkelman. 2011. A March of Liberty: A Constitutional History of the United States, Volume I, From the Founding to 1900. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Vincent. 1987. Dworkin and the Legal Process Tradition: The Legacy of Hart and Sacks. Arizona Law Review 29: 413-474.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher J. Peters .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Peters, C.J. (2015). Legal Formalism, Procedural Principles, and Judicial Constraint in American Adjudication. In: Pineschi, L. (eds) General Principles of Law - The Role of the Judiciary. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 46. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19180-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics