Skip to main content

State Sovereignty and International Legal Discourse

  • Chapter
Governance and International Legal Theory

Part of the book series: Nova et Vetera Iuris Gentium ((NVIG,volume 23))

Abstract

The post-Cold War era has witnessed renewed debates on the nature, function and meaning of state sovereignty. Phenomena like global capitalism, international governance and the fragmentation of states have given rise to claims that state sovereignty is “in decline”1 or even “diminished”.2 Others have argued that the institutionalization of human rights and humanitarian law should be regarded as a “move along a trajectory to global humanity”3 and as a “globalized discourse”.4 Yet others have questioned the analytical value of the concept of state sovereignty as such: the meaning of “sovereignty” would be so underdetermined that it can be used to justify or criticize almost any action. Globalization, international governance as well as the fragmentation and integration of states thus raise fundamental questions for international legal theory. The state is, after all, still widely regarded as the primary subject of international law, while the institution of state sovereignty is held to be one of the cornerstones of the international legal order. The aim of this chapter is to take up and discuss some of the above-mentioned challenges to the concept of state sovereignty and so to contribute to a better understanding of the meaning and function of state sovereignty in contemporary international law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. For this claim see M. van Creveld, The Rise and Decline of the State (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 336–421.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. See for a discussion also S. Rosenau, Turbulence in World Politics. A Theory of Change and Continuity (New York, Princeton University Press, 1990)

    Google Scholar 

  3. K. Ohmae, The End of the Nation State. The Rise of Regional Economics (New York, Free Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Similar claims are being discussed by O. Schachter, “The Decline of the Nation-State and Its Implications for International Law”, 36 Colombia Journal of Transnational Law, 1997, 7–23.

    Google Scholar 

  5. V. Cable, The Diminished Nation-State: A Study in the Loss of Economic Power (Daedalus, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  6. R. Robertson, Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture (London, Sage, 1992), p. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Günther Teubner, “The King’s Many Bodies: The Self-Destruction of Law’s Hierarchy”, 31 Law and Society Review, 1997, 763–787, at 770. For an analysis of the role of the state and of non-state actors in relation to the International Criminal Court see the Chapters 6, 7 and 12 of Jensen, Amman and Struett in this volume.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. See also notes 1 and 2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. E. Yardeni, “The Economic Consequences of the Peace”, in Mueller (ed.), The Political Economy of Global Interdependence. (Colorado, Westview Press, 2000), pp. 91–109. V. Cable (note 2), p. 241.

    Google Scholar 

  10. K. Ohmae, The Borderless World (New York, Harper, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  11. J.H. Herz, International Politics in the Atomic Age (New York, Columbia University Press, 1959), p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For similar arguments see Ohmae (note 7), pp. 13, 14. For an overview of some of the arguments regarding the end of the Westphalian state see A. Prakash, J.A. Hart, “Globalization and governance: an introduction”, in Prakash, Hart (eds.), Globalization and Governance (London, Routledge, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  13. For a discussion of this point, see J.A. Scholte, Globalization: a critical introduction (Basingstoke, Macmillan, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  14. M. Jachtenfuchs, “Conceptualizing European Governance”, in Joergenson (ed.), Reflective Approaches to European Governance (London, MacMillan, 1997), pp. 39–50.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In the field of (European) security this blurring of the distinction between internal and external affairs has been set out by, amongst others, M. Anderson, Policing the European Union (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1995)

    Google Scholar 

  16. D. Bigo, “When Two Become One: Internal and External Securitizations in Europe”, in Kelstrup, Williams (eds.), International Relations Theory and the Politics of European Integration (Routledge, London-New York, 2000), pp. 171–204.

    Google Scholar 

  17. For an analysis of failed states in international law see D. Thürer, “The ‘failed State’ and international law”, Revue internationale de la Croix-Rogue (Genève, Comité International de la Croix-Rouge, 1999), p. 731

    Google Scholar 

  18. Wallace-Bruce, N. Lante, “Of Collapsed, Dysfunctional and Disoriented States: Challenges to International Law”, 47 Netherlands International Law Review, 2000, 53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. M. Herdegen, “Der Wegfall effektiver Staatsgewalt im Völkerrecht”, Beachte der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Völkerrrecht (Heildelberg, Müller, 1996), 68.

    Google Scholar 

  20. For the term “quasi-state” see R.H. Jackson, Quasi-States: Sovereignty, International Relations and the Third World (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990). See also R.H. Jackson, “Juridical Statehood In Sub-Saharan Africa”, Journal of Modern Africa Studies, 1992, pp. 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  21. M.N. Shaw, “Territory in International Law”, 13 Netherlands Yearbook of International Law, 1982, 61–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. See R.H. Jackson (note 14). For a criticism on the distinction between empirical and juridical sovereignty see W.G. Werner, J.H. de Wilde, “The Endurance of Sovereignty”, European Journal of International Relations, 2001, 283–315.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Van Creveld (note 1), pp. 336–421.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Van Creveld (note 1), p. 404. Van Creveld bases his argument on N. South, Policing for Profit: the Private Security Sector (London, Sage, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  25. and J. S. Kakalik and S. Wildhorn, The Private Police: Security and Danger (New York, Crane Russak, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  26. S.I. Benn, “The Uses of Sovereignty”, 3 Political Studies, no. 2, 1955, 122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. J. Miller, The World of States (London, Croom Helm, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  28. For a discussion of the several meanings attached to the concept of sovereignty see also Fowler, M.R. and J.M. Bunck, Law Power and the Sovereign State; The Evolution and Application of the Concept of Sovereignty (University Park, PA, Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  29. For the latter see especially Kelsen’s moral call to abandon the use of state sovereignty: “Die Souveränitätsvorstellung freilich muß radikal verdrängt werden. Diese Revolutionierung des Kulturbewußtseins tut vor allem not!... Denn die Vostellung von der Souveränität des eigenes Staates it bisher... allem im Wege gestanden was auf... die Weiterentwicklung der Völkerrechtsgemeinschaft aus ihrem Zustande der Primitivität zu einer civitas maxima... abziet. Als unendliche Aufgabe aber muß solcher Weltstaat als Weltorganization allem politischen Streben gesetzt sein”. Kelsen, Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts (Tübingen, 1920), p. 320.

    Google Scholar 

  30. L. Henkin, International Law: Politics, Values, Functions, 216 Recueil des Cours (1990), pp. 24, 25.

    Google Scholar 

  31. P. Malanczuk, Akehurst’s Modem Intoduction to International Law (London, Routledge, 1997), pp. 17, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  32. E. Lauterpacht, “Sovereignty — Myth or Reality?”, International Affairs, 1997, 137–150 at 141.

    Google Scholar 

  33. For an overview of writers adopting the view that sovereignty is merely a shorthand for a bundle of rights and competences under international law see M. Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia, The Structure of International Legal Argument (Helsinki, Finnish Lawyer’s Publishing Company, 1989), p. 197 and p. 212. See also the position of Ross (sovereignty as a tû-tû concept) referred to by Koskenniemi at p. 202, footnote 38.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Idem, p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See also the importance attached to state sovereignty in UN resolutions like the Friendly Relations Resolution (Resolution 2625 (XXV) of 24 October 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  36. The abovementioned examples are discussed by N.J. Schrijver, “The Changing Nature of Sovereignty”, British Yearbook of International Law, 1999, 65–98 at 85. Note that this chapter was written before the 2003–2004 military interventions in Iraq.

    Google Scholar 

  37. N. Schrijver (note 26), 65–98.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Arrest Warrant of 11 April 2000 (Democratic Republic of the Congo v. Belgium), Judgment of 14 February 2002, ICJ Reports (2000), p. 3. A clear example of a case where the ICJ discussed the meaning of sovereignty in international law is Case Concerning Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. United States of America), Judgment of 27 June 1986, ICJ Reports (1986), p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Higgins, International Law and the Reasonable Need of Governments to Govern (London, 1982), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  40. I. Brownlie, Principles of Public International Law (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1995), p. 278.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See also Bleckmann, Grundprobleme und Methoden des Völkerrechts, Freibur (München, 1982), p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  42. For an overview see M. Carnoy, M. Castels, S. Cohen and F. Cardoso (eds.), The New Global Economy in the Information Age (Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  43. L. Pauly and S. Reich, “National Structures and Multinational Corporate Behaviour: Enduring Differences in the Age of Globalization”, 51 International Organization, 1, 1997, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. See also G. Soerensen, “Sovereignty: Continuity and Change in a Fundamental Institution”, in R.H. Jackson (ed.), Sovereignty at the Millenium (Oxford, Blackwell, 1999), pp. 168–182.

    Google Scholar 

  45. S. Krasner, Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy (New York, Princeton University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  46. For this argument see also Werner & de Wilde (note 16).

    Google Scholar 

  47. As is the claim of A. James who argues that “International law may and does give rise to what are called sovereign rights, but these are rights given to sovereign states, that is, states which are already sovereign. The position of international law in relation to sovereignty is that it presupposes it. International law makes sense only on the assumption that there are sovereign states to which it can be applied.” A. James, Sovereign Statehood, The Basis of International Society (London, Allen & Unwin, 1986), p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Canadian Supreme Court in the case regarding the secession of Quebec, quoting from H.W.R. Wade, “The Basis of Sovereignty”, Cambridge Law Journal, 1955, 196.

    Google Scholar 

  49. An example of this can be found in Berman’s article on self-determination: “Very different conceptions of international society result depending on whether, and to what extent, law or sovereignty is granted ultimate primacy”. N. Berman, “Sovereignty In Abeyance, Self-Determination and International Law”, 7 Wisconsin International Law Journal, 1986, no 1, 390–443.

    Google Scholar 

  50. S. Barkin, B. Cronin, “The State and the Nation: Changing Norms and the Rules of Sovereignty in International Relations”, in R. Beck, T. Ambrosio (eds.), International Law and the Rise of Nations (New York, Chatham House, 2002), p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  51. In this sense, my argument is related to the tradition of social constructivism in IR-theory. Social constructivism does not take sovereignty as externally given, but rather examines the social practices in which the concept of sovereignty is constructed and reconstructed. For the outlines of the social constructivist argument regarding sovereignty see A. Wendt, “Anarchy is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics”, International Organization, 1992, 391–425; A. Wendt, A Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  52. R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Oxford, Hart, 1986), p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  53. For this see W.G. Werner, “Self-Determination and Civil War”, Journal of Conflict and Security Law, 2001, 171–190.

    Google Scholar 

  54. R.H. Jackson, “Sovereignty in World Politics”, Political Studies, 1999, 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  55. “Out of a loose band of irregular entities, it was set to create a horizontal order of independent, sovereign states which most emphatically rejected any superior power...” A. de Zayas, “Westphalia, Peace of 1648”, in Bernhardt (ed.), Encyclopaedia of Public International Law (1984), p. 537.

    Google Scholar 

  56. A. Eyffinger, “Europe in Balance: An Appraisal of the Westphalian System”, 45 Netherlands International Law Review, 1998, 178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. See for this argument also R.H. Jackson (note 40). An example of the Christian, universal language is the Preamble and the first Article of the Treaty of Westphalia of 24 October 1648 between the Emperor and the King of France. The opening words state that the Treaty is concluded “In the name of the most holy and individual trinity”, whereas the first Article declares that “there shall be a Christian and Universal peace...”.

    Google Scholar 

  58. A. Osiander, “Sovereignty, International Relations and the Westphalian Myth”, 55 International Organization, 2, 2001, 251–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. F. Egger, “Johann Rudolf Wettstein und die internationale Anerkennung der Schweiz als ëuropäischer Staat”, in K. Bussmann, H. Schilling, 1648: Krieg und Frieden in Europa, Textband I: Politik, Recht und Gesellschaft (München, Bruckmann, 1998), pp. 423–432. See also Article LXII of the Treaty of 24 October 1648, which confirms the liberty of the Swiss cantons and their exemption from the empire.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Strictly speaking, the Westphalian Peace Treaties consist of the two treaties signed on 24 October 1648: the Treaty of Münster between the Emperor and the King of France and the Treaty of Osnabrück between the Emperor and the queen of Sweden. For a discussion of the negotiations and the peace treaties see A. Osiander, The States System of Europe, 1640–1990: Peacemaking and the Conditions of International Stability (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  61. For a description of this process, see Van Creveld (note 1). For an analysis of one of the aspects of the monopolization of force see also: M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of Prison (London, Penguin Books, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  62. In the Leviathan, Hobbes introduced the state as an “artificial man” who is distinct from the person of the ruler. See also P. King, The Ideology of Order: A Comparative Analysis of Jean Bodin and Thomas Hobbes (London, Alan and Urwin, London, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  63. Osiander (note 44), p. 278. See also Ruggie’s interpretation of the persistence of weak actors in the European state system in J.G. Ruggie, Winning the Peace: America and World Order in the New Era (New York, Columbia University Press, 1996)

    Google Scholar 

  64. and J.G. Ruggie, Constructing World Polity, Essays on International Institutionalization (London, Routledge, 1998).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  65. Customs Regime Between Germany and Austria, Advisory Opinion, 5 September 1931, PCIJ Reports, Series A/B, no. 41, p. 57. See also the approach towards independence in the Aaland Island case, Report of International Commission of Jurists, League of Nations Official Journal (1920), Special Supplement no. 3, p. 3 or the approach in the Wimbledon case, PCIJ Series A (1923), no. 1, p. 25. See also the Island of Palmas case, discussed below (note 56 infra).

    Google Scholar 

  66. E. de Vattel, The Law of Nations or the Principles of Natural Law, (Washington, 1758, 1916), Introduction, para. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  67. See e.g. J. Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Boston, Harvard University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  68. Koskenniemi (note 23), p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See J.G. Ruggie, “Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity, Towards a Neorealist Synthesis”, World Politics, 1983, 276–279.

    Google Scholar 

  70. H. Patomäki, “State is Not a Person: On the Theoretical and Practical Consequences of State-Antropomorphism”, paper for the 43 Annual International Studies Association, New Orleans, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Island of Palmas case (Netherlands v. United States), Permanent Court of Arbitration (Huber), 2 Reports of International Arbitral Awards (1928), p. 829.

    Google Scholar 

  72. M. Foweler and J. Bunck, “The Nation Neglected: The Organization of International Life in the Classical State Sovereignty Period”, in R. Beck and T. Ambrosio (eds.), International Law and the Rise of Nations (New York, Chatham House Publishers, 2002), pp. 38–60 at 43.

    Google Scholar 

  73. The crucial role of effective control does not mean, of course, that sovereignty and effective control can be regarded as synonyms. Effective control is an important factor that has to be taken into account in determining the coming into existence of a state. There are, however, many examples of states where the government has lost effective control and who yet remain members of the community of sovereign states (e.g. Lebanon in the 1980s or some African states in the 1990s). These examples indicate that, although effective control is the normal context in which the concept of state sovereignty is applied, sovereignty is a scheme of interpretation which can also be used in exceptional situations like civil war, foreign occupation and collapse of central authority. In these situations, the concept of state sovereignty is used to uphold the status quo and to prevent the termination of one of the members of the society of sovereign states. See for this argument also Werner & de Wilde (note 16), 283–313.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Yearbook of the United Nations, 1948–1949, p. 948.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Barcelona Traction, Light and Power Company, Limited (Belgium v. Spain), Judgment of 5 February 1970, ICJ Reports (1970), p. 3, at paras. 33, 35. See also the recognition respect for self-determination as an erga omnes obligation in East Timor (Portugal v. Australia), Judgment of 30 June 1995, ICJ Reports (1995) p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Barcelona Traction (note 60), p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See Malanczuk (note 21), p. 59. For a more detailed analysis of obligations erga omnes see C. Annacker, Die Durchsetzung von erga omnes Verpflichtungen vor dem Internationalen Gerichtshof (Hamburg, Kova, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  78. A.J. de Hoogh, Obligations Erga Omnes and International Crimes: A Theoretical Inquiry into the Implementation and Enforcement of the International Responsibility of States (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1996)

    Google Scholar 

  79. W. Czaplinski, “Concepts of jus cogens and Obligations erga omnes in International Law in the Light of Recent Developments”, Polish Yearbook of International Law, 1997/1998, 87

    Google Scholar 

  80. O. Pegna, “Counterclaims and Obligations Erga Omnes before the International Court of Justice”, 9 European Journal of International Law 1998, 724; M. Byers, “Conceptualizing the Relationship between Jus Cogens’ and ‘Erga Omnes’ Rules”, Nordic Journal of International Law, 1997, 211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  81. Resolution 3061 (XXVIII), 2 November 1973, Yearbook of the United Nations, 1973, 143–147. See also M.N. Shaw, International Law (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 144, 145. Note, however, that the requirement of effectiveness has also been applied less strictly outside colonial contexts. An example is the acceptance of Bosnia-Herzegovina as an independent state although even President Izetbegovic admitted that Bosnia-Herzegovina “could not protect its independence without foreign military aid”.

    Google Scholar 

  82. See Roland Rich, “Recognition of States: The Collapse of Yugoslavia and the Soviet Union”, 4 European Journal of International Law, 1993, 36–65.

    Google Scholar 

  83. See inter alia Security Council Resolutions 217 (1965) and 217 (1966), General Assembly Resolutions 2024 (XX) and 2151 (XXI). For a more general discussion on the position of Rhodesia see J. Crawford, The Creation of States under International Law (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  84. Netherlands Yearbook of International Law, 1971, 141.

    Google Scholar 

  85. See, inter alia, General Assembly Resolution 34/93, UM Chronicle, January 1980, 26. See also Crawford (note 64), pp. 103–106 and 219–227.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Shaw (note 63), p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  87. 165 LNTS, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Department of State Publications, 3263 (1948), p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Yearbook of the United Nations, 1948–1949, p. 948.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Shaw (note 63), pp. 149–155, for example, discusses the fundamental rights and duties of states inter alia on the basis of the Declaration on Principles of International Law (General Assembly Resolution 2625 (XXV), 24 October 1970), as well as on the following cases: Lotus (1927), Island of Palmas (1928), Corfu Channel (1949), Nicaragua (1986) and Nuclear Weapons (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  91. M. Koskenniemi (note 23), pp. 206–261. See also the examples given by D. Kennedy, “Theses about International Law Discourse”, German Yearbook of International Law, 1980, 353–391. See also D. Kennedy, International Legal Structures (Baden-Baden, Nomos, 1987). Some of the other examples mentioned by Koskenniemi are: the Customs Regime Between Germany and Austria case (1931), the Asylum case (1950) the Nuclear Tests case (1974) as well as the problem of trans-border pollution, where one state’s the sovereign right to use one natural resources is countered by another state’s sovereign right to decide what takes place on its territory.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Right of Passage over Indian Territory, Merits, Judgment of 12 April 1960, ICJ Reports (1960), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  94. C.H. Alexandrowicz, “The Theory of Recognition in Fieri”, 34 British Yearbook of International Law, 1958, p. 176.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Arrest Warrant of 11 April 2000 (Democratic Republic of the Congo v. Belgium), Judgment of 14 February 2002, ICJ Reports (2002), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Ibid., Application, pp. 7, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Ibid., Counter Memorial of the Kingdom of Belgium, 28 September 2001, para. 3.3.29. See also the oral pleadings on Thursday 23 November 2000 CR 2000/35, para. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  98. M. Koskenniemi (note 23), pp. 213–214.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Article 2(7) reads as follows: “Nothing contained in the present Charter shall authorize the United Nations to intervene in matters which are essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of any state or shall require the Members to submit such matters to settlement under the present Charter; but this principle shall not prejudice the application of enforcement measures under Chapter VIL” The domestic jurisdiction clause was also included in the Covenant of the League of Nations, Article 15(8).

    Google Scholar 

  100. See Schrijver (note 26), 75.

    Google Scholar 

  101. H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford, Clarendon, 1961), p. 218.

    Google Scholar 

  102. G. Schwarzenberger, E. Brown, Manual of International Law (London, Stevens, 1976), p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  103. See for this argument H. Kelsen, Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts (Tübingen, Mohr, 1920)

    Google Scholar 

  104. and H. Kelsen, Principles of International Law, 2nd ed. (New York, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  105. A. Ross, A Textbook of International Law, General Part (London, Longman, 1947), p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre (Wien, Deuticke, 1960), especially Chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  107. H. Kelsen, General Theory of Norms (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1991), p. 2 (translation of the Allgemeine Theorie der Normen by Michael Hartney).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  108. For such an analysis of legal institutions see A. Ross, “Tû-tû”, 70 Harvard Law Review, 1957, 812–825.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  109. Koskenniemi (note 23), p. 218. Koskenniemi here sketches the consequences of the “legal” or reductionistic approach towards sovereignty.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Hart (note 82), p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  111. For legal positivism see D.N. MacCormick, O. Weinberger, An Institutional Theory of Law (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1986)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  112. D.W.P. Ruiter, Institutional Legal Facts, Legal Powers and Their Effects (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1993)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  113. and D.W. P. Ruiter, Legal Institutions (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 2002).

    Google Scholar 

  114. See for legal semiotics B. Jackson, Law, Fact and Narrative Coherence (Merseyside, Deborah Charles Publications, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  115. For the interpretive school see R. Dworkin (note 38). For an example of the use of a broader conception of the legal order in international law see Jose Alvarez, “Judging the Security Council”, 90 American Journal of International Law, 1996, 31 (on the expressive function of the International Court of Justice).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  116. For the notion of institutions and institutional facts see J.R. Searle, Speech Acts (Cambridge University Press, 1990), 175–198 (reprint from the 1969 edition). For an application of this notion to legal theory see especially Ruiter 1993 and 2002 (note 90).

    Google Scholar 

  117. Dworkin (note 38), pp. 90–96.

    Google Scholar 

  118. R. Vincent, Non-Intervention and International Order (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1974), p. 22. Note, however, that Grotius did not have a separate concept of intervention, apart from a concept of war. For a general discussion of the evolution of the term “intervention” see P. Winfield, “The History of Intervention in International Law”, British Yearbook of International Law, 1922–1923, 130–149.

    Google Scholar 

  119. See also Ann Van Wijnen Thomas, AJ. Thomas, Non-intervention, The Law and Its Import in the Americas (Dallas, Southern Methodist University Press, 1956)

    Google Scholar 

  120. A. Carty, The Decay of International Law? A reappraisal of the limits of legal imagination in international affairs (Manchester, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  121. E. de Vattel, The Law of Nations or the Principles of Natural Law (1758), translation in The Classics of International Law, (Washington D.C., Carnegie Institution of Washington, 1916), Book II, Chapter IV, para. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Case concerning Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. United States of America) (Merits), ICJ Reports (1986), p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Winfield (note 93), 130.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Partly, this form of intervention overlaps with the term “dictatorial intervention”: intervention which involves the threat or use of force “in case the dictates of the intervening power are disregarded”. T.J. Lawrence, Principles of International Law (London, MacMillan, 1913), p. 124.

    Google Scholar 

  125. See for an analysis of the doctrines in the 18th and 19th century especially: I. Brownlie, International Law and the Use of Force by States (Oxford, Clarendon, 1991), pp. 14–51.

    Google Scholar 

  126. See also P. Malanczuk, Humanitarian Intervention and the Legitimacy of the Use of Force (Amsterdam, Spinhuis, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  127. G.F. von Martens, The Law of Nations: Being the Science of National Law, Covenants, Power &c, Founded upon the Treaties and Customs of Modern Nations in Europe (London, Cobbett, 1829), Book III, Chapter II, section 1.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Ibid., Book VI, Chapter VIII, section 1.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Ibid., Book III, Chapter II, section 1.

    Google Scholar 

  130. See Brownlie (note 98), pp. 14–51.

    Google Scholar 

  131. For an analysis of the transformation war after 1900 see K.J. Holsti, The State, War and the State of War (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1996).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  132. For an analysis see Brownlie (note 98); H. McCoubrey, N.D. White, International Law and Armed Conflict (Dartmouth, Aldershot, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  133. The prohibition on the use of force was laid down in Article 1 of the Kellogg-Briand Pact which condemned recourse to war and renounced it as an instrument of national policy (United States Statutes at Large, Vol. 46, Part 2, p. 2343). The prohibition could also be derived from the practice of states as Brownlie (note 98, p. 108) concludes: “If the legal materials and especially the diplomatic correspondence of the years between 1928 and 1939 are examined, it becomes clear that nearly every government in existence had at some time estopped itself from denying the illegality of resort to force except in self-defence”.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Article 2(4) UN Charter determines that “All Members shall refrain in their international relations from the threat or use of force against the territorial integrity or political independence of any state, or in any other manner inconsistent with the Purposes of the United Nations”. Among the several UN Resolutions dealing with the threat or use of force the following are especially worth mentioning: Declaration on Principles of International Law, GA Resolution 2625 (XXV), UN Doc. A/5217 (1970); Declaration on the Inadmissibility of Intervention in Domestic Affairs and Protection of their Independence and Sovereignty, GA Resolution 2131 (XX), 21 December 1965; Resolution on the Definition of Aggression, GA Resolution 3314 (XXIX), 1974. In the Nicaragua case, the International Court of Justice recognized the prohibition on the use of force as a norm of international customary law and concluded moreover that GA Resolutions 2625 (XXV) and 3314 (XXIX) reflect valid customary international law. See Case concerning Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. United States of America), ICJ Reports (1986), paras. 187 to 201.

    Google Scholar 

  135. This formulation of a jus cogens norm is derived from Article 53 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (International legal Materials, 8, 1969, p. 679. For a discussion of the jus coges status of the prohibition of the threat or use of force see A. Cassese, International Law in a Divided World (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  136. See supra note 105.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Van Creveld (note 1).

    Google Scholar 

  138. See for a discussion of this point e.g. Scholte (note 10).

    Google Scholar 

  139. In this context, the much debated report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty is worth mentioning. The Report was titled “The Responsibility to Protect” and emphasized that sovereignty implies responsibility and that the primary responsibility for the protection of human rights lies with the state itself.

    Google Scholar 

  140. In this context Schrijver (note 26), 96, has referred to the 1997 World Bank World Development Report (Washington, 1997) which explicitly recognizes the central role of the state in social and economic development.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Sean Murphy, “Democratic Legitimacy and the Recognition of States and Governments”, 48 The International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 1999, 545

    Google Scholar 

  142. C. Hillgruber, “The Admission of New States to the International Community”, 9 European Journal of International Law, 1998, 491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  143. A. Cassese, Self-determination of peoples, a legal reappraisal (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Ige F. Dekker Wouter G. Werner

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2004 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Werner, W.G. (2004). State Sovereignty and International Legal Discourse. In: Dekker, I.F., Werner, W.G. (eds) Governance and International Legal Theory. Nova et Vetera Iuris Gentium, vol 23. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-6192-5_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-6192-5_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-04-14033-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-6192-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics