Skip to main content
Log in

Multiple dimensions of embodiment in medical practices

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I explore the various meanings of embodiment from a patient’s perspective. Resorting to phenomenology of health and medicine, I take the idea of ‘lived experience’ as starting point. On the basis of an analysis of phenomenology’s call for bracketing the natural attitude and its reduction to the transcendental, I will explain, however, that in medical phenomenological literature ‘lived experience’ is commonly one-sidedly interpreted. In my paper, I clarify in what way the idea of ‘lived experience’ should be revisited and, subsequently, what this reconsideration means for phenomenological research on embodiment in health and medicine. The insight that the body is a condition of possibility for world-disclosing yet, at the same time, itself conditioned by this world forces us to not only zoom in on the body’s subject-side, but also on its object-side. I argue that in order to render account for this double body ontology, phenomenology should include empirical sociological analyses as well. I thus argue in favor of the idea of a socio-phenomenology. Drawing on material from my own research project on embodied self-experiences after breast surgery, I show how this approach can be fruitful in interpreting the impact of disfigurements on a person’s embodied agency, or a person’s ‘I can’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The external view on the body is often identified with a third person’s perspective on one’s body (which in the field of health and medicine has become a synonym for a physician’s instrumental and objectifying view). However, an external view on one’s body could also imply a second person’s perspective on one’s body, which, indeed, implies a far less instrumental attitude. This further classification of the notion of external view goes beyond the scope of this paper. I tackle this subject in another paper.

  2. Although the phenomenological approach is mostly used to provide insight in physical orders, it should be noted that the phenomenological conception of ‘embodied being in the world’ is also gaining ascendency in the interpretation of mental disorders. See for this notably the work of Fuchs (2005, 2007), De Haan and Fuchs (2010), and Ratcliffe (2008, 2009).

  3. As I see it, experiences of pain or of discomfort not necessarily result in experiences of self-alienation. In some situations pain can also lead to experiences of self-confirmation. Cole (2004), for instance, describes how people suffering from tetraplegia due to spinal cord injury, and who most of the time cannot feel their own body anymore, can be ‘anchored’ in their body through pain. Pain “is almost my friend” one of his interviewees said, because “it puts me in touch with my body” (p. 89). Conversely, I would not reserve the experience of alienation to negative or pathological experiences such as pain and discomfort only. From a phenomenological point of view, one could also argue that any experience of one’s own body from an external perspective involves self-objectification and thus alienation. In that sense I agree with Ingerslev (2013) who discusses external explicit body experience in terms of ‘self-distance’, and shows that this phenomenon accounts for both pathological and non-pathological bodily self-experiences.

  4. I would like to thank Nicholas Smith for drawing my attention to this text by Ahmed.

  5. In this project I have ‘followed’ 19 women who have undergone breast surgery for a period of 8–10 months by means of multiple interviews. The main question in this research is how women habituate to disfigurements and (if applicable) to the usage of a concealing prosthesis.

  6. In that sense my approach to embodiment is close to the way Mol (2002) analyzes the multiplicity of body ontologies while concentrating on the question how a ‘disease is done’, how a ‘body is done’ in various practices. However, there remains a considerable difference between her ethnographical approach to embodiment and my socio-phenomenological one. Whereas she holds the view that a ‘practice’ is something local, and not generalizable, I believe that a phenomenological exploration of embodiment can identify generalizable forms of embodied self-experiences. This difference amounts to the fact that my philosophy of the body still adheres to the request of bracketing the natural attitude, the call for the reduction, even though a complete reduction or bracketing is never possible.

References

  • Ahmed, S. 2007. A Phenomenology of Whiteness. Feminist Theory 8(2): 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aho, J., and K. Aho. 2009. Body matters: A phenomenology of sickness, disease, and illness. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullington, J. 2013. The expression of the psychosomatic body from a phenomenological perspective. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carel, H. 2008. Illness: The cry of the flesh. Durham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carel, H. 2011. Phenomenology and its application in medicine. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 32(1): 33–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carel, H. 2012. Nursing and medicine. In The Routledge companion to phenomenology, ed. S. Luft, and S. Overgaard, 623–632. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cash, T.F., and M.L. Szymanski. 1995. The development and validation of the Body-Image Ideals Questionnaire. Journal of Personality Assessment 64(3): 466–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J. 2004. Still lives: Narratives of spinal cord injury. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crompvoets, S. 2012. Prosthetic fantasies: Loss, recovery, and the marketing of wholeness after breast cancer. Social Semiotics 22(1): 107–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dahlberg, K., L. Todres, and K. Galvin. 2009. Lifeworld-led healthcare is more than patient-led care: An existential view of well-being. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 12(3): 265–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Haan, S., and T. Fuchs. 2010. The ghost in the machine: Disembodiment in schizophrenia—two case studies. Psychopathology 43(5): 327–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earle, V. 2010. Phenomenology as research method or substantive metaphysics? An overview of phenomenology’s uses in nursing. Nursing Philosophy 11(4): 286–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fanon, F. 1952. Peau noire, masques blancs. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finlay, L. 2011. Phenomenology for therapists: Researching the lived world. New York: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. 2005. Corporealized and disembodied minds: A phenomenological view of the body in melancholia and schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 12(2): 95–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. 2007. The temporal structure of intentionality and its disturbance in schizophrenia. Psychopathology 40(4): 229–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., and D. Zahavi. 2012. The phenomenological mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groven, K. S., Råheim, M., Engelsrud, G. 2013. Dis-appearance and dys-appearance anew: Living with excess skin and intestinal changes following weight loss surgery. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 16(3): 507–523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopwood, P., I. Fletcher, A. Lee, and S. Al Ghazal. 2001. A body image scale for use with cancer patients. European Journal of Cancer 37(2): 189–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1900–1901. Logische Untersuchungen. II/1 (Siebte Auflage, 1993). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

  • Husserl, E. (1952). Ideen zur einer reiner Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch, Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Ingerslev, L.R. 2013. My body as an object: self-distance and social experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12(1): 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitzmüller, G., T. Häggström, and K. Asplund. 2013. Living an unfamiliar body: The significance of the long-term influence of bodily changes on the perception of self after stroke. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 16(1): 19–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. 1990. The absent body. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. 1992a. A tale of two bodies: The Cartesian corpse and the lived body. In The body in medical thought and practice, ed. D. Leder. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. 1992b. The body in medical thought and practice. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lorde, A. 1980. The cancer journals. Argyle, NY: Spinsters Ink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martínková, I., and J. Parry. 2011. An introduction to the phenomenological study of sport. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 5(3): 185–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phenomenology of Perception. Trans. C. Smith. 1962. London, New York: Routledge.

  • Mol, A. 2002. The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. Durham and London: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moser, I. 2009. A body that Matters? The role of embodiment in the recomposition of life after a road traffic accident. Scandinavian Journal of Disability Research 11(2): 83–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moustakas, C. 1994. Phenomenological research methods. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, M. 1990. The politics of disablement. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polit, D. F. and C. T. Beck. 2008. Nursing research. Generating and assessing evidence for nursing practice. Philadelphia, Baltimore, New York, London, Buenos Aires, Hong Kong, Sydney, Tokyo: Wolters Kluwer, Lippincott Williams & Wilkins.

  • Ratcliffe, M. 2008. Feelings of being: Phenomenology, psychiatry and the sense of reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. 2009. Existential feeling and psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 16(2): 179–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumsey, N., and D. Harcourt. 2004. Body image and disfigurement: Issues and interventions. Body Image 1(1): 83–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1943). Being and nothingness: An Essay on phenomenological ontology. (trans: Barnes, H.E., 2007). London & New York: Routledge.

  • Scully, J.L. 2008. Disability bioethics: Moral bodies, moral difference. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, M.T. 2012. Face off: Searching for truth and beauty in the clinical encounter. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 15(3): 329–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J.A., P. Flowers, and M. Larkin. 2009. Interpretative phenomenological analysis: Theory, method and research. Los Angeles, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. 2011. Illness as unhomelike being-in-the-world: Heidegger and the phenomenology of medicine. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 14(3): 333–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toombs, S.K. 1988. Illness and the paradigm of lived body. Theoretical Medicine 9(2): 201–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toombs, S.K. 1990. The temporality of illness: Four levels of experience. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 11(3): 227–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toombs, S.K. 1992. The meaning of illness: A phenomenological account of the different perspectives of physician and patient. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Toombs, S.K. 2001. Reflections on bodily change: The lived experience of disability. In Handbook of phenomenology and medicine, ed. S.K. Toombs. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Manen, M. 1990. Researching lived experience: Human science for an action sensitive pedagogy. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Manen, M. 1998. Modalities of body experience in illness and health. Qualitative Health Research 8(1): 7–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, B. 1989. Körper-Leib. In Esprit/Geist: 100 Schlüsselbegriffe für Deutsche und Franzosen, ed. J. Leenhardt, and R. Picht, 342–345. München: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I.M. 1990. Throwing like a girl and other essays in feminist philosophy and social theory. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, R.M. 1981. The context of self: A phenomenological inquiry using medicine as a clue. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeiler, K. 2010. A phenomenological analysis of bodily self-awareness in the experience of pain and pleasure: on dys-appearance and eu-appearance. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13(4): 333–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Annemie Halsema and Marjolein de Boer for their instructive and challenging suggestions on a previous version of this paper. Also thanks to an anonymous reviewer for providing effective comments. This research is funded by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research—NWO (VIDI-Grant 276-20-016).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jenny Slatman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Slatman, J. Multiple dimensions of embodiment in medical practices. Med Health Care and Philos 17, 549–557 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9544-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9544-2

Keywords

Navigation