Skip to main content
Log in

Mini-publics and Political Meritocracy: Towards a New China Model

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Chinese Political Science Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Confucian political theorists show increasing interest in ‘political meritocracy’, a model that some present as a superior alternative to democracy and a viable path forward for China. But political meritocracy suffers from accusations of authoritarianism and sclerosis: relying upon opaque mechanisms of promotion, current models of political meritocracy struggle to incorporate forms of popular accountability without undermining the overarching logic of the system. This article addresses this problem by adding an institutional innovation to Daniel Bell’s China Model: the use of insular mini-publics (small assemblies of randomly selected citizens) as a way to promote meritocrats. Insular mini-publics allow political meritocracy to include a popular check in the promotion process without politicizing the populace at large, undermining the legitimacy of the model, or creating discord. Forcing meritocrats to account for the people’s fears and demands, mini-publics also incentivize a certain degree of responsiveness. In the first section, I argue that Daniel Bell’s China Model outperforms other accounts of political meritocracy, but suffers from key weaknesses in need of remediation. In the second section, I introduce mini-publics, explain how my proposal differs from other accounts, and describe the details of the institutional arrangement. In the third section, I outline five functions that mini-publics fulfil in this updated model and clarify the role that mini-publics ought to play in political meritocracy’s wider conception of legitimacy. Ultimately, I argue that insular mini-publics inject a necessary form of popular accountability into the China Model, thereby supplying an institutional response to the critics of political meritocracy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that this paper does not even attempt to determine which of these models comes closer to the Confucian ideal. My objective is not to ask what the ‘properly Confucian’ system looks like, but to determine the merits of the institutional proposals of contemporary Confucians on normative grounds. Further, this paper does not provide a philosophical defence of political meritocracy against more democratic models (for such a defence, see Bell 2016; Bai 2019; Chan 2014; Jiang 2013). Rather, taking the fundamental assumptions of Confucian political meritocracy for granted, I rethink the institutions of political meritocracy on its own terms. While necessary for the purposes of this paper, the premise that political meritocracy is worth defending in any form remains contentious (e.g. Mushkat 2021).

  2. From this point onwards, the phrases ‘Confucian meritocrats’ and ‘political meritocrats’ refer to advocates of political meritocracy, and the phrase ‘meritocrats’ refers to rulers in a meritocratic system.

  3. Further, where epistocrats typically apply selection mechanisms to voters—by, for instance, weighing their votes differently or making the ability to vote conditional upon test performance (see Brennan 2016)—meritocrats apply selection mechanisms to officials themselves.

  4. I borrow the input and output legitimacy model from the work of Fritz W. Scharpf on democratic legitimacy in Europe and beyond (Scharpf 1997, 1999).

  5. While crucial, the debate between horizontal and vertical integration lies beyond the scope of this article. In what follows, I provide a rough sketch of key arguments against horizontal integration to justify my focus on Daniel Bell’s vertical model in the rest of the article. Those who seek a more in-depth account should turn to Bell’s own critique (Bell 2016, 151–179), as well as to defences of horizontal integration (e.g. Bai 2019, 83–97; Jiang 2013). Nonetheless, even those who reject the following arguments against horizontal integration may find this article’s contribution useful insofar as the question of meritocratic promotion affects all accounts of political meritocracy, be them vertical or horizontal.

  6. Those who support more democratic models may not find the ‘House of Lords syndrome’ problematic at all. Nonetheless, by depriving meritocrats of political power, this sort of democratization harms political meritocracy on its own terms—terms that Bai, Jiang, and other advocates of bi- or tri-cameral models accept.

  7. In a systematic study of constitutional systems, the Chinese intellectual Kang Youwei came to the same conclusion, holding that democracy works best in small communities such as Switzerland (see Zhang 2011, 118).

  8. For those who may worry about the influence of experts, Landemore reports that participants in mini-publics—in this case, in the French Convention for Climate—tend to detect and dislike experts who try to influence deliberations (Giraudet et al. 2022). Since the promotion of experts and facilitators depends upon the participant’s evaluation of their performance, they have every reason not to take this kind of risk.

  9. One could reply that if mini-publics do refine the views of participants in such a way, they should not merely select but replace meritocrats as decision- and law-makers. While this argument deserves an extended response elsewhere, its implications lie beyond the scope of this paper since my starting point is to improve political meritocracy on its own terms—i.e. taking the fundamental assumptions of political meritocracy for granted. I suspect that a possible response to such an objection would differentiate between the skills and knowledge required to judge the work of others, and the skills and knowledge required to do the work itself. It is presumably easier to evaluate the outcome of policy than to design policy from scratch; we can coherently believe that mini-publics excel at the former but cannot do the latter. Nonetheless, leaving this objection aside for further exploration, I admit that political meritocrats focus their criticism of democracy on ‘one person, one vote’ models without paying enough attention to more deliberative accounts of democracy in which electoral processes play little to no role (e.g. Landemore 2020). While I cannot address Landemore’s comprehensive defence of mini-publics within the limits of this paper, Confucian meritocrats should directly respond to the empirical and philosophical literature on mini-publics in future works.

  10. Responsiveness and epistemic detachment are different, but related challenges. It is precisely because meritocrats now have reasons to learn from the experiences of diverse groups that their perspective will be broadened, which has positive epistemic ramifications.

References

  • Ahlers, Anna L. 2019. Political inclusion in contemporary China. Journal of Chinese Governance 4 (3): 201–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, Vibeke N., and Kasper M. Hansen. 2007. How deliberation makes better citizens: The Danish Deliberative Poll on the Euro. European Journal of Political Research 46: 531–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2006. The epistemology of democracy. Episteme 3 (1–2): 8–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bai, Tongdong. 2019. Against Political Equality: The Confucian Case. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel A. 2006. Beyond Liberal Democracy: Political Thinking for an East Asian Context. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel A. 2016. The China Model: Political Meritocracy and the Limits of Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel A., and Wang Pei. 2020. Just Hierarchy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benson, Jonathan. 2019a. Knowledge and communication in democratic politics: markets forums and systems. Political Studies 67 (2): 422–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benson, Jonathan. 2019b. Deliberative democracy and the problem of tacit knowledge. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 18 (1): 76–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benson, Jonathan. 2021. The epistemic value of deliberative democracy: how far can diversity take us? Synthese 199: 8257–8279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, Jonathan. 2006. Deliberative democracy and the epistemic benefits of diversity. Episteme 3 (3): 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, Bryan. 2007. The Myth of the Rational Voter: Why Democracies Choose Bad Policies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Joseph. 2013. Political Meritocracy and Meritorious Rule: A Confucian Perspective. In The East Asian Challenge for Democracy: Political Meritocracy in Comparative Perspective, ed. Daniel A. Bell and Chenyang Li, 31–54. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Joseph. 2014. Confucian Perfectionism: A Political Philosophy for Modern Times. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ci, Jiwei. 2019. Democracy in China: The Coming Crisis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, Robert A. 1970. After the Revolution: Authority in a Good Society. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doyon, Jérôme., and Barbara Keller Franziska. 2020. Knowing the wrong cadre? Networks and promotions in the Chinese party-state. Political Studies 68 (4): 1036–1053.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esterling, Kevin M., Archon Fung, and Taeku Lee. 2015. How much disagreement is good for democratic deliberation? Political Communication 32: 529–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fan, Ruiping. 2010. Reconstructionist Confucianism: Rethinking Morality after the West. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, James S. 2009. When the People Speak: Deliberative Democracy and Public Consultation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, James S., Baogang He, Robert C. Luskin, and Alice Siu. 2010. Deliberative democracy in an unlikely place: deliberative polling in China. British Journal of Political Science 40: 435–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flinders, Matthew, Katie Ghose, Will Jennings, Edward Molloy, Brenton Prosser, Alan Renwick, Graham Smith, and Paolo Spada. 2016. Democracy Matters: Lessons from the 2015 Citizens’ Assemblies on English Devolution. Sheffield: Democracy Matters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giraudet, Louis-Gaëtan., Bénédicte. Apouey, Hazem Arab, Simon Baeckelandt, Philippe Bégout, Nicolas Berghmans, Nathalie Blanc, Jean-Yves. Boulin, Eric Buge, Dimitri Courant, Amy Dahan, Adrien Fabre, Jean-Michel. Fourniau, Maxime Gaborit, Laurence Granchamp, Hélène. Guillemot, Laurent Jeanpierre, Hélène. Landemore, Jean-François. Laslier, Antonin Macé, Claire Mellier, Sylvain Mounier, Théophile. Pénigaud, Ana Póvoas, Christiane Rafidinarivo, Bernard Reber, Romane Rozencwajg, Philippe Stamenkovic, Selma Tilikete, and Solène Tournus. 2022. “Co-construction” in deliberative democracy: lessons from the French citizens’ convention for climate. Humanities and Social Sciences Communications 9: 207. https://doi.org/10.1057/s41599-022-01212-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert E., and Kai Spiekermann. 2018. An Epistemic Theory of Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grönlund, Kimmo, Maija Setälä, and Kaisa Herne. 2010. Deliberation and civic virtue: lessons from a citizen deliberation experiment. European Political Science Review 2: 95–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grönlund, Kimmo, Kaisa Herne, and Maija Setälä. 2015. Does enclave deliberation polarize opinions? Political Behavior 37: 995–1020.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hankins, James. 2019. Virtue Politics: Soulcraft and Statecraft in Renaissance Italy. Cambridge: An Imprint of Harvard University Press: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, Kasper M., and Vibeke Normann Andersen. 2004. Deliberative democracy and the deliberative poll on the Euro. Scandinavian Political Studies 27: 261–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, Baogang, and Mark E. Warren. 2020. Can meritocracy replace democracy? A conceptual framework. Philosophy & Social Criticism 46 (9): 1093–1112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herring, Cedric. 2009. Does diversity pay? Race, gender, and the business case for diversity. American Sociological Review 74 (2): 208–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, Michael R. 2008. Descriptive Representation in Citizen Assemblies. In Designing Deliberative Democracy: The British Columbia Citizens’ Assembly, ed. Mark E. Warren and Hilary Pearse, 106–126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jiang, Qing. 2013. A Confucian Constitutional Order: How China’s Ancient Past Can Shape Its Political Future. Princeton: Princeton University Press (Translated by Edmund Ryden).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jiang, Junyan, and Muyang Zhang. 2020. Friends with benefits: patronage networks and distributive politics in China. Journal of Public Economics 184: 104–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Sungmoon. 2016. Public Reason Confucianism: Democratic Perfectionism and Constitutionalism in East Asia. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Sungmoon. 2020. The challenge of Confucian political meritocracy: a critical introduction. Philosophy & Social Criticism 46 (9): 1005–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobloch, Katherine, and John Gastil. 2015. Experiencing a civic (re)socialization: the educative effects of deliberative participation. Politics 35: 183–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kwon, Kyung Rok. 2020. Towards Confucian democratic meritocracy. Philosophy & Social Criticism 46 (9): 1053–1075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène. 2013. Democratic Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène. 2017. Beyond the fact of disagreement? The epistemic turn in deliberative democracy. Social Epistemology 31 (3): 277–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène. 2020. Open Democracy: Reinventing Popular Rule for the Twenty-First Century. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leib, Ethan, and He. Baogang. 2010. The Search for Deliberative Democracy in China. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, Chenyang. 2012. Equality and inequality in Confucianism. Dao 11: 295–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mang, Franz. 2020. Political meritocracy and its betrayal. Philosophy & Social Criticism 46 (9): 1113–1126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, Hugo, and Hélène. Landemore. 2012. Reasoning is for arguing: understanding the successes and failures of deliberation. Political Psychology 33: 243–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Min, John B., and James K. Wong. 2018. Epistemic approaches to deliberative democracy. Philosophy Compass 13 (6): e12497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mushkat, Roda. 2021. From China’s “Political Meritocracy” to “Just Hierarchy”: the elusive search for a viable post-democratic governance regime in the era of Coronavirus. European Journal of Comparative Law and Governance 8: 304–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niemeyer, Simon, and John S. Dryzek. 2007. The ends of deliberation: meta-consensus and inter-subjective rationality as ideal outcomes. Swiss Political Science Review 13: 497–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Dwyer, Shaun. 2015. Epistemic elitism, paternalism, and confucian democracy. Dao 14: 33–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richard, Orlando C., B.P.S. Murthi, and Kiran Ismail. 2007. The impact of racial diversity on intermediate and long-term performance: the moderating role of environmental context. Strategic Management Journal 28 (12): 1213–1233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, Matt, and Graham Smith. 2014. Defining Mini-Publics. In Deliberative Mini-Publics: Involving Citizens in the Democratic Process, ed. Kimmo Grönlund, André Bächtiger, and Maija Setälä, 9–26. Colchester: ECPR Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, Fritz W. 1997. Economic integration, democracy and the welfare state. Journal of European Public Policy 4 (1): 18–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, Fritz W. 1999. Governing in Europe: Effective and democratic? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, Gunter. 2009. Village Elections, Citizenship and Regime Legitimacy in Contemporary Rural China. In Regime Legitimacy in Contemporary China: Institutional Change and Stability, ed. Thomas Heberer and Gunter Schubert, 55–79. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzberg, Melissa. 2015. Epistemic democracy and its challenges. Annual Review of Political Science 18: 187–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Somin, Ilya. 2013. Democracy and Political Ignorance. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, John L. 2008. The prospects for democracy in China. Foreign Affairs 87 (1): 2–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urbinati, Nadia. 2014. Democracy Disfigured. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 1995. The wisdom of the multitude: some reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle’s politics. Political Theory 23 (4): 563–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, Mark E., and Hilary Pearse, eds. 2008. Designing Deliberative Democracy: The British Columbia Citizens’ Assembly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yat-sen, Sun. 1953. Fundamentals of National Reconstruction. Taipei: China Cultural Service.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Yongle. 2011. Jiu bang xin zao, 1911–1917 [The Remaking of an Old Country, 1911–1917]. Beijing: Beijing daxue chubanshe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziliotti, Elena. 2020. An epistemic case for Confucian democracy. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2020.1838736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mathis Bitton.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

No competing interests.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bitton, M. Mini-publics and Political Meritocracy: Towards a New China Model. Chin. Polit. Sci. Rev. 9, 152–171 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s41111-022-00228-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s41111-022-00228-2

Keywords

Navigation