Skip to main content

Modern Democratic Society and the Enlightenment

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

Modern Western and other democratic societies’, including Europe’s and America’s, fundamental values and institutions are, first and foremost, the creations and legacies of the Enlightenment. Their ideals and social structures of liberty, equality, justice, democracy, inclusion, individualism, social progress, secularism, pluralism, scientific and technological rationalism, economic prosperity and freedom, free markets, the pursuit of happiness and well being, dignified humane life, optimism and hope, universalism, and humanism are primarily rooted in, advocated, and advanced by the Enlightenment. The latter is understood as a sort of cultural revolution, starting as an intellectual or philosophical and sociological movement in Western Europe, especially, though not solely, in France, with subsequent partial ramifications and derivations in America and other non-European or non-Western settings during the seventeenth and especially the eighteenth century.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

     Artz (1998:35) observes that “so successful were [the Enlightenment’s ideals] they that at bottom we are still the spiritual children of the eighteenth century.”

  2. 2.

     For example, some US neoconservatives accused liberal opponents and measures, such as the 2009 Congress economic stimulus bill, for the “Europeanization of America” in the apparent belief that American values and institutions are different from and even opposite to those of Western and all Europe. Ironically, this is the virtually same expression that Max Weber used when visiting America in 1904, “Europeanization of the American national character.” Hence, at least from Weber’s standpoint, there are hardly any values and institutions in America that are not of direct or indirect European origins, as epitomized by the twin religious-economic complex of Calvinism cum Puritanism and modern capitalism both, as even patriotic Parsons would admit, transplanted from the “old world” to the “new nation.” On this account, the conservative accusation of “Europeanization of America” is what Weber calls, in the related reference to the “appeal to national [American or other] character,” a “mere confession of ignorance” and thus “entirely untenable.” Such ethnocentric accusations also confirm Cooley’s classic definition of ethnocentrism as the “matter of lack of knowledge” or simply the product of ignorance and (so) arrogance, and eventually aggressive nationalism and militarism, in mutual relation and reinforcement.

  3. 3.

     Artz (1998:35) suggests that “we still believe [in the Enlightenment ideals] that man and his institutions can be changed, that social and political problems can be improved rather than endured, that the goal of human life is maximum self-realization here below, and that the future is a challenge and an opportunity.”

  4. 4.

     Caplan and Cowen (2004:404) that the “rise of [post] medieval society and the Renaissance was, in large part, a process of re-globalization [reviving antiquity], as the West established significant contact with the Chinese and Islamic worlds.”

  5. 5.

     Some may add the Protestant Reformation to these pre-Enlightenment conceptions of freedom. However, the Reformation at best advocated only or mainly theological or religious freedom of conscience rather or more than secular freedoms, and even then it, especially its Calvinist “Second” phase, did not always practice what it had preached, as Weber and other sociologists suggest. At worst, it proved as antagonistic and destructive via, especially Calvinist-Puritan theocracies, to human liberty, including civil and political liberties as medievalist Catholicism and the Vatican Church. After all, the Reformation was, at least in part, an adverse religious cum evangelical reaction to the manifest or latent artistic and other secular freedoms and humanism of what Parsons calls the “humanistic Renaissance,” just as to hegemonic Catholicism as the prime and explicit theological target. For example, Parsons implies that the “men of the humanistic Renaissance” and early Puritans diverged on the matter of artistic and other secular freedom and humanism by agreeing on only on “few points” such as the “negative valuation of ritual.” Furthermore, Pareto observes that in northern Europe the Renaissance was, and thus its secular artistic and other liberties and humanistic values, “halted too soon” by the Reformation as a religious revival seeking and succeeding to supplant what he calls the “Roman [Catholic] theocracy” by a new Protestant version.

  6. 6.

     Eisenstadt (1998:213) adds that for the Enlightenment the “possibility of extending an individual’s mastery over his own destiny, or of gaining his emancipation, implied not just the task of understanding society, but of reconstructing it.”

  7. 7.

     US conservative sociologist Nisbet (1966:9) registers that British “utilitarian liberalism – from Bentham to Spencer – held to a view of church, state, family, moral tradition that did not differ from earlier views of the Enlightenment [i.e.] individual emancipation” in France as well as Great Britain (Hume, Ferguson, etc.).

  8. 8.

     Juergensmeyer (2003:212) remarks that the “idea of a nation based on [‘Christian law and order,’ a ‘Christian Republic’] is on the minds of Christian religious activists [with] the Protestant governments of the early American colonies [grounding] their constitutions in biblical law [as a model] or precedent for a ‘new kind of Christian government.’” He also observes that US fundamentalism “admires the attempts of Muslims in Iran, Sudan, and Afghanistan to create regimes grounded in Islamic law” (Juergensmeyer 2003:212).

  9. 9.

     In passing, in the Enlightenment, liberal universalism in the sense of universal liberty on one hand and cultural relativism and pluralism, just as and individualism, on the other are complementary rather than mutually exclusive principles, simply complements or correlates, and not substitutes or opposites, as epitomized by Kant (Habermas 2001).

  10. 10.

     Byrne (1997:16) comments that “this awareness of the customs and beliefs of other cultures raised crucial issues for Christian theology and the dominant role of the Christian church. If civilizations had existed for thousands of years without hearing of Christ then was revelation insufficient? Christian religion and culture [became] one among many and not as the one, single true religion given by the one and only God.”

  11. 11.

     Parsons states that “probably the primary source of this individualistic cast of European thought lies in Christianity [viz.] the immediacy of the individual soul to God, inherent in [Protestantism],” thus curiously overlooking the Enlightenment and its sociological or secular individualism. To imply, as he does, that Christianity, specifically Protestant theological individualism, was the “primary source of this individualistic cast” of the Enlightenment overlooks that the latter was originally and essentially a non- or post-Christian, though not fully anti- Christian or atheistic, cultural revolution (Artz 1998), notably in France (Voltaire, Diderot) and in part Britain (Hume).

  12. 12.

    Evoking Parsons, Ruggles (2007:969) suggests that “increasing individualism and a growing taste for privacy [is regarded] as a logical outcome of cultural changes set in motion by the Reformation and the Enlightenment,” implicitly conflating the theological individualism and transcendental “privacy,” namely what Weber calls “unprecedented inner loneliness,” in the former with the sociological individualism and societal privacy in the latter.

  13. 13.

     Denying what the US Federal government officially in some obscure documents proclaims as the “existence of divinity” remains a crime of blasphemy. While not punished with death as by New England Puritanism, such a “crime” remains a certain open or tacit disqualification or at least disadvantage and not so “great expectation” for political office in much of America, especially the “Bible Belt” ruled, as Mencken (1982) noted a century ago, by “godly” fundamentalist powers that enforce with what Hume called Puritan-style “wild fanaticism” related proclamations and consequently make “unbelievers need not apply” in politics up to the early twenty-first century, despite such discriminatory practices on the basis of religion being judged unconstitutional by the Supreme Court in the 1960s.

  14. 14.

     Mises explicitly and systematically links “Collectivism” with “Socialism” and only implicitly or sporadically with “reactionary Conservatism,” just as “Individualism” with “Liberalism.” A minimalist interpretation is that if “Individualism” is paradigmatically linked with “Liberalism,” then “Collectivism” is with “Conservatism” as its original and perennial antagonist, and not, as he often seems to contend, only or mainly with “Socialism” as the identified major antiliberal, more precisely, anticapitalist, force.

  15. 15.

     Byrne (1997:24) comments that “whether it was Rousseau’s rather vague idea that somehow power should emanate from the ‘general will’ of the people or the new American ideal of everybody’s right to the pursuit of happiness, it is to the Enlightenment that we owe the Western political principle that everyone in society should have a share in society’s benefits and opportunities.”

  16. 16.

     According to Artz (1998:33), the Enlightenment was the first to posit that “the ability to use their reason makes men equal, laws should accord with popular wishes and should preserve men’s rights, and with the use of reason, progress is sure to come.”

  17. 17.

     Brink (2000:13) adds that this egalitarian and liberal “assumption is based on a post-Enlightenment belief in the reasonableness of human beings [resting] on their capacity to act autonomously,” the term “post-Enlightenment” apparently signifying neo- rather than counter-Enlightenment.

  18. 18.

     Cross (2000:245) comments that “both the cultural Right and Left shared the Enlightenment idea that adults must protect children from the adult world of limitless choice in order to prepare them to enter it with self-restraint.”

  19. 19.

     Byrne (1997:24) proposes that the Enlightenment’s “Western political principle that everyone in society should have a share in society’s benefits and opportunities” probably had its extant and implicit roots in the early “Christian belief in the equality of all in the sight of God,” or as Lucas (2000) puts it, “equally valued by God.”

  20. 20.

     Generally, Weber distinguishes Catholicism or original Christianity as “church” from Protestantism as a “sect” or the polar opposite; also, he somewhat imprecisely describes early Calvinism, including Puritanism, as the “Church militant” in the apparent or logical meaning of sectarian militancy.

  21. 21.

     Protestantism, including Calvinism and even Puritanism, describes itself as a “reformed” and even claims to be the only “true” and “pure church” within Christianity, but strictly speaking is “sect” in Weber’s ideal-typical framework. This is what, after all, his expression “Protestant sectarianism,” adopted by Weberian (Munch 2001) as well as US conservative sociologists (Lipset 1996), indicates. In passing, Weber makes a distinction between Calvinism as “church” or “hierocratic institution” and Puritanism as “sect” to distinguish the former from the latter as its derivative. Still, for Weber Calvinism and even Protestantism as a whole substantively remains a “sect” vs. Catholicism as “church” within the framework of Christianity, as indicated by his detection and emphasis of Calvinist underlying “sectarian” tendencies, generating or culminating into Puritan sects (also, Munch 1981).

  22. 22.

    In a typical misconstruction of the Enlightenment and liberalism (Berry 1997), in so doing Hayek overlooks or denies that Burke’s and any feudal-rooted or protoconservative antiliberalism is either by assumption or in reality anti-individualism, as precisely witnessed in pre-liberal traditionalism or antiliberal conservatism, from medieval despotism to fascism to “born” again fundamentalism and neo-fascism. Thus, it is anything but liberal “individualism” or Mannheim’s “individualistic liberalism.”

  23. 23.

     Friedland (2002:125) observes that “we today confront the apparently premodern specter of religious nationalism.” Also, casting doubt on the prevalent view that nationalism is a “modern phenomenon,” Gorski (2000) identifies, in such Western societies as the Calvinist Netherlands and Puritan England, “medieval roots” in their “nationalist discourses” as “no less nationalistic” than those of the French Revolution.

  24. 24.

     Angel (1994:347) observes that the Enlightenment is the “epoch in which the third line of progress in history, the dismantling of indiscriminate chiefdom [and theocratic] consciousness (i.e.) the damage that chiefdom consciousness has perpetrated in rippling through our social institutions and entrenching ego-consciousness.”

  25. 25.

     In contrast to Weber, Mises states that the Enlightenment “doctrine of human progress was an adaptation of the Christian philosophy of salvation,” by implication to society, by modifying the latter “in order to make it agree with its scientific outlook.” This is a somewhat surprising statement, because Mises, like Weber, typically contrasts and even opposes the Enlightenment to the Christian and other religion, as did and do most representatives of both.

  26. 26.

     Somewhat atypical for most economists, Phelps (2007:555) adopts the “classical theory of what the good life is, a theory that originated in Europe: Aristotle declared that people everywhere wanted to expand their horizons and ‘discover their talents.’ The Renaissance figure Benvenuto Cellini described the joys of creativity and making it in his autobiography. In Baroque times Miguel de Cervantes and William Shakespeare dramatize the individual’s quest – a moral view call[ed] vitalism [also] reflected to a degree by Thomas Jefferson and Voltaire among other Enlightenment figures.” Phelps (2007:555) registers that, in contrast to classical civilization, the Renaissance, and the Enlightenment, “for John Calvin (1536), the good life consisted of hard work and wealth accumulation,” though he and his Calvinist disciples would add (and Weber implied) that the latter was only the means of (attaining knowledge of) salvation (“election”) or religious grace as the ultimate, transcendental definition of the “good life” and human “happiness.”

  27. 27.

     According to Garrard (2003:9), Rousseau’s Calvinist pessimism was “among the most uncompromising in the history of modern thought [vs.] atheism and materialism in France after 1750.” This is indicated by Rousseau’s “pessimistic view of history” “savage,” “barbaric,” “civilized” stages as degeneration and that the “main culprit in the tendency of societies to degenerate into a Hobbesian war of all against all is amour-propre,” asking, for instance, “if Sparta and Rome perished, what State can hope to endure forever?” (Garrard 2003:110–2). As a predictable Calvinist solution, Rousseau suggested that his fellow Genevans (and all societies) should, as they did, “follow the example of the authoritarian Spartans rather than the democratic Athenians [and their] “dangerous innovations” (Garrard 2003:113). In a bizarre or frivolous twist Rousseau’s “pessimistic conservatism” was manifested in arguing “against the introduction of modern theater in Geneva,” apparently a place where Shakespeare “needed not apply” like in Puritan-ruled England. For illustration, “while there, he watched and was impressed by the French plays that Voltaire had been staging.” Rousseau was outraged; he feared that the theater would debase the morals of his innocent compatriots and that Voltaire “would cause a revolution there, and I would find again in my fatherland the tone, the appearance, the morals that were driving me from Paris” (Garrard 2003:113–4). Then, “in a letter to Voltaire in 1760, Rousseau accused him of ‘ruining’ his beloved Geneva – the ‘anti-Paris’ – incontrovertible proof of which came shortly afterward when his native city banned and burned both The Social Contract and Emile. As a consequence of these events, Rousseau renounced his Genevan citizenship ‘forever’ [second time]” (Garrard 2003:114). If anything, the bizarre, if not insane, case of Rousseau was a paradigmatic proof that the Enlightenment and liberalism overall and Calvinism and all ascetic Protestantism were as mutually exclusive and opposites as literally “heaven and earth,” despite some attempts at reconciliation (Sorkin 2005), specifically that his “die hard” Calvinist views literally poisoned or disfigured his actual or potential Enlightenment and liberal-democratic ideas.

  28. 28.

     Fromm (1941) adds that the “most striking expression of this hostility is found” especially in “Calvin’s doctrine [of predestination]” and “concept of God” as a sort of “Oriental despot” (Artz 1998).

  29. 29.

     In this connection, Calvinist Rousseau was an exception that really proved the rule, namely the pattern the Enlightenment as paradigmatic optimism or hope and of Calvinism as exemplary pessimism or “gloom and doom.”

  30. 30.

     Artz (1998:35–6) adds that “the traditional Christian view of man as tainted by original sin, enduring this vale of tears, and hoping for salvation was no longer acceptable (but) the reasonable course for man (was) to forget about sin in the old sense, and to concentrate on his self-development here and now.”

  31. 31.

    Garrard (2003:104) comments that “not only were human beings not tainted with an indelible corruption that always limits progress but, given the empiricism of the French Enlightenment, they were also seen as malleable, and therefore improvable (e.g., Condorcet).”

  32. 32.

    In passing, Weber and Parsons et al. do not consider the Calvinist dogma of divine predestination, unlike the Islamic one of predetermination, fatalism on the grounds of its “elective affinity” with capitalist activity or wealth accumulation as the “proof,” though not the means, of God’s grace, but this is a dubious view, a sort of “deprived mental gymnastics” (Samuelson 1983). Simply, if humans are predestined by the God of Calvinism either to salvation (a few) or damnation (most) absolutely beyond their control, then this is absolute fatalism from their stance, though with respect to what Weber calls the “world beyond,” as distinguished from “this world.” He limits “fatalism” to the latter by relating the Islamic and other doctrines of predetermination to “this world” in contrast to the Calvinist doctrine of predestination related to the “world beyond,” but this distinction is also dubious or fluid. Conceivably, if humans are predestined beyond their control to “heaven” or “hell,” they will likely experience this as fatalistic as being predetermined in “this world,” simply, as “nothing to do about it” as their fate. For most humans the Islamic doctrine of societal predetermination and the Calvinist dogma of “heavenly” predestination, while formally or theologically distinct, eventually have substantively identical social effects of fatalistic resignation or helplessness in relation to suprahuman entities and their self-designed agents as theocrats with “divine rights,” contrary to Weber and Parsons et al. As Fourcade and Healy (2007:296) imply, the “protocapitalist Calvinists” were resigned to or inflicted by the “salvational anxiety their harsh religious doctrines tended to produce,” notably Calvin’s inhumane and antiuniversalistic doctrine of predestination.

  33. 33.

     For instance, during the “war on terror” in the 2000s the Pentagon reportedly included a “Bible quote on the cover page of daily intelligence briefings” for the neoconservative administration, such as “quotes from the books of Psalms and Ephesians and the epistles of Peter.” (“Behold, the eye of the Lord is on those who fear Him. To deliver their soul from death. Therefore put on the full armor of God, so that when the day of evil comes, you may be able to stand your ground, and after you have done everything, to stand”).

  34. 34.

     Referring to the neoconservative war cum “crusade” on terrorism (Heymann 2003:164) comments that the US president “is free, as far as our own courts are concerned, to ignore customary international law, but that has its price; so, too, does an unwillingness to take part in a regime of treaties, or to subject ourselves to new institutions designed to enforce international law.”

  35. 35.

     Angel (1994:346) elaborates that such Enlightenment optimism or pacifism suggests compelling evidence that “people can live out their lives without manifesting the potential for the irrational collective aggressions of large scale wars [i.e.] both in small scale societies and in large scale technologically advanced collectivities there is no overwhelming need for wars [vs.] any neat sociobiological or psychological argument for pessimism.” This leads to the following hypothetical question and answer: “Isn’t it perhaps enough to point to the holocaust [plus ethnic cleansing] to prove the bankruptcy of [the Enlightenment] hopes that collective irrationalist barbarities can be overcome? But it is shortsightedness to think that genocidal irrationalism is an invention of the twentieth century, as though designed by an antirationalist puppeteer to prove the hopelessness of rationalistic human prospects. From the earliest days (there are) records of genocidal intentions and campaigns” (Angel 1994:341). For example, arguably “if the Hebrew Bible can take for granted the acceptability of genocidal campaigns and the pursuit of justice, then our collective horror at the Holocaust shows the degree of moral progress (during) the last several thousand years” (Angel 1994:342).

  36. 36.

     Artz (1998:33) states that the French Enlightenment philosophers “were eminently practical and utilitarian, and aimed to promote happiness and well-being among all classes. [For them] the only justification for the State is for the promotion of the good life for its citizens, men [are] rational, they can conceive the good, can discover means of obtaining it, and should be allowed, if they used reason, to direct their own lives by their knowledge, reason, and experience.”

  37. 37.

     Einolf (2007:109) comments that the critics of the “traditional account of the abolition of torture” claim that the latter “was not abolished due to the spread of Enlightenment ideas, but due to a change in the standards of proof required for a conviction.”

  38. 38.

     Sorokin (1970:426) observes that “at the end of fifth century (420–380 bc) there is a great flaring of the ethics of happiness. It becomes dominant [but] with the beginning of [the Christian] era, it begins to decline, and after fourth century ad it goes underground.” And, in his account the Christian “period from fifth century ad to the end of fifteenth century [is] monolithic again, entirely dominated by the ethics of principles.”

References

  • Abbott, Andrew. 2005. Linked Ecologies: States and Universities as Environments for Professions. Sociological Theory 23, 245–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The Stars Down to Earth and Other Essays in the Irrational in Culture. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. The Missing Motivation in Macroeconomics. American Economic Review 97, 5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Neofunctionalism and After. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Benedict. 1991. Imagined Communities. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angel, Leonard. 1994. Enlightenment East and West. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, Robin. 2001. Secularism and Sectarianism in India and the West: What are the Real Lessons of American History? Economy and Society 30, 273–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Invaluable Goods. Journal of Economic Literature 35, 757–765.

    Google Scholar 

  • Artz, Frederick. 1998 [1968]. The Enlightenment in France. Kent: Kent State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. America. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman, Zygmunt. 1997. Postmodernity and its Discontents. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Community. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The Individualized Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Ulrich. 2000. The Brave New World of Work. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. The Cosmopolitan Society and its Enemies. Theory, Culture and Society 19, 17–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becky, Pettit and Bruce Western. 2004. Mass Imprisonment and the Life Course: Race and Class Inequality in U.S. Incarceration. American Sociological Review 69, 151–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— (ed.) 2002. The Radical Right. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Max Weber. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Force, Fate and Freedom. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, Morris. 2000. The Twilight of American Culture. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berry, Christopher. 1997. Social Theory of the Scottish Enlightenment. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittner, Rüdiger. 1996. What is Enlightenment? In Schmidt James (ed.) What is Enlightenment? (pp. 345–358). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blinkhorn, Martin. 2003. Fascists and Conservatives. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Allan. 1988. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boles, John. 1999. The Southern Way of Religion. Virginia Quarterly Review 75, 226–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, Gary and Axel Ockenfels. 2000. ERC: A Theory of Equity, Reciprocity, and Competition. American Economic Review 90, 166–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, Raymond. 1981. The Logic of Social Action. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Acts of Resistance. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bremer, Francis. 1995. The Puritan Experiment. Hanover: University Press of New England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, Bert van den. 2000. The Tragedy of Liberalism. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, James. 1997. Religion and the Enlightenment. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calhoun, Craig. 1993. Nationalism and Ethnicity. Annual Review of Sociology 19, 211–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, Bryan and Tyler Cowen. 2004. Do we Underestimate the Benefits of Cultural Competition? American Economic Review 94, 402–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cascardi, Anthony. 1999. Consequences of Enlightenment. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Andrew, Paul Frijters and Michael Shields. 2008. Relative Income, Happiness, and Utility: An Explanation for the Easterlin Paradox and Other Puzzles. Journal of Economic Literature 46, 95–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Elizabeth. 1999. Speech for the Soul: Religion, Conscience, and Free Speech in Antebellum America. In McLaren John and Harold Coward (eds.) Religious Conscience, the State, and the Law (pp. 62–76). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clemens, Elisabeth. 2007. Toward a Historicized Sociology: Theorizing Events, Processes, and Emergence. Annual Review of Sociology 33, 527–549.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, Wade. 2005. Sovereignty Relinquished? Explaining Commitment to the International Human Rights Covenants, 1966–1999. American Sociological Review 70, 472–495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Randall. 2000. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Precis. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 30, 157–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, Gary. 2000. An All-Consuming Century. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahrendorf, Ralph. 1959. Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. Life Chances. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darnell, Alfred and Darren Sherkat. 1997. The Impact of Protestant Fundamentalism on Educational Attainment. American Sociological Review 62, 306–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, James. 2005. William Ames’s Calvinist Ambiguity Over Freedom of Conscience. Journal of Religious Ethics 33, 335–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayton, Cornelia. 1999. Excommunicating the Governor’s Wife: Religious Dissent in the Puritan Colonies Before the Era of Rights Consciousness. In McLaren John and Harold Coward (eds.) Religious Conscience, the State, and the Law (pp. 29–45). Albany: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deaton, Angus. 2008. Income, Health, and Well-Being Around the World: Evidence from the Gallup World Poll. Journal of Economic Perspectives 22, 53–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delanty, Gerard. 2000. The Foundations of Social Theory: Origins and Trajectories. In Bryan Turner (ed.) The Blackwell Companion to Social Theory (pp. 21–46). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dessí, Roberta. 2008. Collective Memory, Cultural Transmission, and Investments. American Economic Review 98, 534–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, Michele. 1999. The Authority of the Holy Revisited: Habermas, Religion, and Emancipatory Possibilities. Sociological Theory 17, 290–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dombrowski, Daniel. 2001. Rawls and Religion. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, Charles and David Woodard. 1996. The Conservative Tradition in America. Lanham: Rowan & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgell, Penny, Joseph Gerteis and Douglas Hartmann 2006. Atheists as Other: Moral Boundaries and Cultural Membership in American Society. American Sociological Review 71, 211–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einolf, Christopher. 2007. The Fall and Rise of Torture: A Comparative and Historical Analysis. Sociological Theory 25, 101–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— (ed.) 1986. The Origins and Diversity of Axial Age Civilizations. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. The Paradox of Democratic Regimes: Fragility and Transformability. Sociological Theory 16, 211–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Fundamentalism, Sectarianism, and Revolution. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Comparative Civilizations and Multiple Modernities. Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenstadt, Shmuel and Sachsenmaier Dominic (eds.) 2002. Reflections on Multiple Modernities. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, John and Michael Evans. 2008. Religion and Science: Beyond the Epistemological Conflict Narrative. Annual Review of Sociology 34, 87–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, Martin. 1999. Enlightenment and Conscience. In McLaren John and Harold Coward (eds.) Religious Conscience, the State, and the Law (pp. 46–61). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fourcade, Marion and Kieran Healy. 2007. Moral Views of Market Society. Annual Review of Sociology 33, 285–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey, Bruno and Felix Oberholzer-Gee. 1997. The Cost of Price Incentives: An Empirical Analysis of Motivation Crowing-Out. American Economic Review 87, 746–755.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey, Bruno and Alois Stutzer. 2002. What Can Economists Learn from Happiness Research? Journal of Economic Literature 40, 402–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Money, Sex, and God: The Erotic Logic of Religious Nationalism. Sociological Theory 20, 381–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Milton. 1982. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm, Erich. 1941. Escape from Freedom. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrard, Graeme. 2003. Rousseau’s Counter-Enlightenment. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • German, James. 1995. The Social Utility of Wicked Self-Love: Calvinism, Capitalism, and Public Policy in Revolutionary New England. Journal of American History 82, 965–998.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. The Constitution of Society. Berkeley: University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. The Third Way and its Critics. London: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. The Mosaic Moment: An Early Modernist Critique of Modernist Theories of Nationalism. American Journal of Sociology 105, 1428–1468.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. The Disciplinary Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, Philip. 1996. Covenant and Republic. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989a. The New Conservatism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of its Voices. In Schmidt James (ed.) What is Enlightenment? (pp. 399–425). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The Postnational Constellation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, Gary. 1994. Civilizations and the Organization of Economics. In Neil Smelser and Richard Swedberg (eds.) The Handbook of Economic Sociology (pp. 166–180). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1948. Individualism and Economic Order. London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, Henry. 1986. The Conquest of Poverty. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heymann, Philip. 2003. Terrorism, Freedom, and Security. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Steven. 2002. Fixing Elections. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinchman, Lewis. 1984. Hegel’s Critique of the Enlightenment. Gainesville: University Presses of Florida.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinson, Keith. 1997. Calvinism Resurging Among SBC’s Young Elites. Christianity Today 41, 86–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman, Albert. 1977. The Passions and the Interests. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982. Rival Interpretations of Market Society: Civilizing, Destructive, or Feeble? Journal of Economic Literature 20, 1463–1484.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Exit, Voice, and the Fate of the German Democratic Republic: An Essay in Conceptual History. World Politics 45, 173–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, Geoffrey. 1999. Economics and Utopia. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max and Theodor Adorno. 1993. Dialectic of Enlightenment. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglehart, Ronald (ed.) 2004. Human Beliefs and Values. México: Siglo XXI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, David, Jason Carmichael and Stephanie Kent. 2005. Vigilantism, Current Racial Threat, and Death Sentences. American Sociological Review 70, 656–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jepperson, Ronald. 2002. Political Modernities: Disentangling Two Underlying Dimensions of Institutional Differentiation. Sociological Theory 20, 61–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Terror in the Mind of God. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, Desmond. 1999. In the Name of Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kloppenberg, James. 1998. The Virtues of Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, Robert. 2000. The Loss of Happiness in Market Democracies. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. The Might Have Been and Could be of Religion in Social Theory. Sociological Theory 17, 240–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Societal Taxonomies: Mapping the Social Universe. Annual Review of Sociology 20, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, Michael. 2008. Evangelicals in the Power Elite: Elite Cohesion Advancing a Movement. American Sociological Review 73, 60–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linton, Marisa. 2001. The Politics of Virtue in Enlightenment France. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipset, Seymour. 1955. The Radical Right: A Problem for American Democracy. The British Journal of Sociology 6, 176–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. American Exceptionalism. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipset, Seymour and Gary Marks. 2000. It Didn’t Happen Here. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, Robert. 2000. Some Macroeconomics for the 21st Century. Journal of Economic Perspectives 14, 159–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manent, Pierre. 1998. Modern Liberty and its Discontents. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The Dark Side of Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannheim, Karl. 1936. Ideology and Utopia. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967. Essays on the Sociology of Culture. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Conservatism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansbach, Richard. 2006. Calvinism as a Precedent for Islamic Radicalism. Brown Journal of World Affairs 12, 103–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayway, Leon. 1984. In Defense of Modernity: Talcott Parsons and the Utilitarian Tradition. American Journal of Sociology 89, 1273–1305.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCann, Sean. 2000. Gumshoe America. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaren, John and Harold Coward (eds.) 1999. Religious Conscience, the State, and the Law. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, Neil. 1996. Nazism, Nationalism, and the Sociology of Emotions: Escape from Freedom Revisited. Sociological Theory 14, 241–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mencken, H. L. 1982. A Mencken Chrestomathy. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merrill, Louis. 1945. The Puritan Policeman. American Sociological Review 10, 766–776.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1968. Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises, Ludwig von. 1950. Socialism. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1957. Theory and History. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. Human Action. Chicago: Henry Regnery.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mokyr, Joel. 2009. Intellectual Property Rights, the Industrial Revolution, and the Beginnings of Modern Economic Growth. American Economic Review 99, 349–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, Lewis. 1944. The Condition of Man. London: Secker and Warburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munch, Richard. 1981. Talcott Parsons and the Theory of Action. American Journal of Sociology 86, 709–739.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Sociological Theory. Chicago: Nelson-Hall Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The Ethics of Modernity. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. The Sociological Tradition. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nischan, Bodo. 1994. Prince, People, and Confession. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, Pippa and Ronald Inglehart. 2004. Sacred and Secular. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pager, Devah. 2003. The Mark of a Criminal Record. American Journal of Sociology 108, 937–975.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967a. The Structure of Social Action. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967b. Sociological Theory and Modern Society. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patell, Cyrus. 2001. Negative Liberties. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, Edmund. 2007. Macroeconomics for a Modern Economy. American Economic Review 97, 543–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. The Open Society and its Enemies. Vol. 2. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling Alone. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiman, Jeffrey. 1997. Critical Moral Liberalism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuter, Peter. 2005. Review of Jeffrey Miron. Drug War Crimes. Oakland: Independent Institute. Journal of Economic Literature 43, 1075–1077.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruggles, Steven. 2007. The Decline of Intergenerational Coresidence in the United States, 1850 to 2000. American Sociological Review 72, 964–989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, Paul. 1983. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, Thomas. 2006. An Astonishing Sixty Years: The Legacy of Hiroshima. American Economic Review 96, 929–937.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, James (ed.) (1996). What is Enlightenment?. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, Julia. 1995. Mass Enlightenment. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, Barry. 2000. Introduction – Postmodern Traces. In Turner Bryan (ed.) The Blackwell Companion to Social Theory (pp. 447–480). Malden: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Christian. 2000. Christian America? Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorkin, David. 2005. Geneva’s Enlightened Orthodoxy: The Middle Way of Jacob Vernet (1698–1789). Church History 74, 286–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorokin, Pitirim. 1970. Social & Cultural Dynamics. Boston: Porter Sargent Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinmetz, George. 2005. Return to Empire: The New US Imperialism in Comparative Historical Perspective. Sociological Theory 23, 339–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stivers, Richard.  1994. The Culture of Cynicism. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steensland, Brian. 2006. Cultural Categories and the American Welfare State: The Case of Guaranteed Income Policy. American Journal of Sociology 111, 1273–1326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2004. The Political Economy of Imprisonment in Affluent Western Democracies, 1960–1990. American Sociological Review 69, 170–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tawney, Richard. 1962. Religion and the Rise of Capitalism. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiryakian, Edward. 2002. Review of Richard Munch. The Ethics of Modernity. American Journal of Sociology 107, 1629–1631.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trey, George. 1998. Solidarity and Difference. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, Bryan. 2002. Sovereignty and Emergency: Political Theology, Islam and American Conservatism. Theory, Culture & Society 19, 103–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uggen, Christopher and Jeff Manza. 2002. Democratic Contraction? Political Consequences of Felon Disenfranchisement in the United States. American Sociological Review 67, 777–803.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dyke, Vernon. 1995. Ideology and Political Choice. Chatham: Chatham House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisbrod, Carol. 1999. The Law and Reconstituted Christianity: The Case of the Mormons. In McLaren John and Harold Coward (eds.) Religious Conscience, the State, and the Law (pp. 136–153). Albany: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuthnow, Robert. 1998. After Heaven. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yang, Yang. 2008. Social Inequalities in Happiness in the United States, 1972 to 2004: An Age-Period-Cohort Analysis. American Sociological Review 73, 204–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaret, David. 1989. Religion and the Rise of Liberal-Democratic Ideology in 17th Century England. American Sociological Review 54, 163–179.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Milan Zafirovski .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zafirovski, M. (2011). Modern Democratic Society and the Enlightenment. In: The Enlightenment and Its Effects on Modern Society. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-7387-0_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics