Skip to main content

Liability in Cases of Damage Resulting from GMOs: an Economic Perspective

  • Chapter
Economic Loss Caused by Genetically Modified Organisms

Part of the book series: Tort and Insurance Law ((TIL,volume 24))

Abstract

The problems sketched in the introduction to this research project, being what the role of liability rules could be in case there is a presence of genetically modified organisms (GMOs) in non-genetically modified crops is certainly a question that merits to be analysed from an economic perspective as well. Economic analysis of law or, as it sometimes shortly referred to “ law and economics” has paid a lot of attention generally to the question of how legal rules can be designed in such a way as to increase social welfare.1 In this respect, some attention has been paid to the use of GMOs generally. That literature more particularly focuses on the uncertainties inherent in the use of GMOs. Increasingly, economic analysis also deals with the question of how the law should react to risk and uncertainty. Hence, economists also provide an economic perspective of the precautionary principle. In that respect, economists have also paid attention to the question whether risky activities that have benefits to society but may also have uncertain negative consequences should still be allowed to take place or not. Traditional cost-benefit analysis has been supplemented with insights from behavioural law and economics to tackle these complicated issues. In that respect, law and economics has paid some attention to the acceptability of GMOs, but that is obviously not the focus of this study.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. The standard handbook in this respect is still from R. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (6th ed. 2003). But see equally R. Cooter/T. Ulen, Law and Economics (4th ed. 2004) and S. Shavell, Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Of course, it should be noted that the issue of co-mingling between non-GM and GM crops is not the only concern that might result from a deliberate release of GMOs to the environment. For example, genes of GM crops designed to be tolerant for the application of certain herbicides (herbicide-tolerant crops) have a potential to flow to their weedy relatives or other plants resulting in the development of herbicide resistant hybrids. The development of herbicide-tolerant weeds could increase the costs of weeds control and pressure to the environment as farmers are forced to resort to chemicals that are possibly more toxic. Concerns have also been pointed to other types of GM crops, namely insect-resistant crops that are designed to produce a certain type of pesticides. Some crops have been genetically modified with genes from Bacillus thuringiensis, referred to as Bt crops, in such a way that insects eating these crops will be killed. Such self-producing pesticides plants might create several environmental problems. It has been argued that Bt crops could make the development of pest-resistance faster. The development of Bt-resistant pests will not only reduce the economic value of Bt crops, but also create a significant loss for organic farmers as Bt is one of most effective pesticides allowed for organic farming. Finally, the release of GMOs into the environment might also create impacts on non-target and beneficial species, such as monarch butterfly. See: D.E. Ervin et al., Towards an Ecological Systems Approach in Public Research for Environmental Regulation of Transgenic Crops, [2003] Agriculture, Ecosystems and Environment 99, 1–14; S.S. Batie, The Environmental Impacts of Genetically Modified Plants: Challenges to Decision Making, [2003] American Journal of Agricultural Economics 85, 1107–111. Readers interested in more scientific evidence about various environmental impacts of GMOs could see, for example: L.L. Wolfenbarger/P.R. Phifer, The Ecological Risks and Benefits of Genetically Engineered Plants, [December 2000] Science 290, 2088–2092; and D.A. Andow/C. Zwahlen, Assessing Environmental Risks of Transgenic Plants, [2006] Ecology Letters 9, 196–214.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See for a summary of this literature M. Faure (ed.), Deterrence, Insurability, and Compensation in Environmental Liability. Future Developments in the European Union (2003).

    Google Scholar 

  4. See M. Faure, Product Liability and Product Safety in Europe: Harmonization or Differentiation? [2000] Kyklos, 467–508.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Indeed, some may doubt whether the mixture between GMOs and non-GM crops does constitute damage at all. It has been argued, for example, that the only damage for organic farmers is their loss of organic certification, due to the presence of GMOs in their products. However, Kershen challenges this possibility of losing organic certification because the mere presence of transgenic crops does not necessarily violate the standards of organic certification. The author argues that according to official standards for organic crops in the USA, organic crops may contain transgenic crops without losing organic certification. In this regard, the co-mingling between GM and non-GM crops does not necessarily create economic damage for organic farmers. See: D.L. Kershen, Legal Liability Issues in Agricultural Biotechnology, [2004] Crop Science 44, 457. For the purpose of this study, however, we assume that the admixture will create damage for the victim, i.e. the farmers that plant non-GM crops. More detailed information about the possible damage of these farmers will be discussed in section V.

    Google Scholar 

  6. R.H. Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, [1960] Journal of Law and Economics (JLE) 1–44.

    Google Scholar 

  7. W. Oi, The Economics of Product Safety, [1973] Bell Journal of Economics (Bell J. Econ.) 4, 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. See V.P. Goldberg, The Economics of Product Safety and Imperfect Information, [1974] Bell J. Econ. 5, 683–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. For an overview of the economics of contract law see S. Shavell, Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law, 291–385 and A.T. Kronman, Mistake, Disclosure, Information, and the Law of Contracts, [1978] Journal of Legal Studies (JLS) 7, 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  10. tOf course, in the economics of contract law, there is a wide literature dealing with interesting problems such as e.g. whether there should still be a right to specific performance even if that may meanwhile have become inefficient or whether parties can still claim the execution of the contract even if the factual conditions have changed. It would lead us too far to discuss these issues in any detail here. See S. Shavell, Contracts, in: P. Newman (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law (1998) 436–445.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For excellent overviews of the role of liability and insurability as “engineering instruments” see A. Endres/ B. Staiger, Ökonomische Aspekte des Umwelthaftungsrechts, in: M. Ahrens/ J. Simon (eds.), Umwelthaftung, Risikosteuerung und Versicherung (1996) 79–93; G. Wagner, Haftung und Versicherung als Instrumente der Techniksteuerung, [1999] Versicherungsrecht (VR) 1441–1480; A. Monti, Environmental Risk: A Comparative Law and Economics Approach to Liability and Insurance, [2001] European Review of Private Law (ERPL) 51–79 and M. Gimpel-Hinteregger, Grundfragen der Umwelthaftung (1994) 19–58.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Schwartz showed that rules of tort law may serve both the aims of deterrence and corrective justice: G. Schwartz, Mixed Theories of Tort Law: Affirming both Deterrence and Corrective Justice, [1997] Texas Law Review (Tex. L. Rev.) 75, 1801–1834.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See C.G. Veljanovski, The Economic Theory of Tort Liability — Toward a Corrective Justice Approach, in: P. Burrows/ C.G. Veljanovski (eds.), The Economic Approach to Law (1981) 125–150.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See his seminal article Some Thoughts on Risk Distribution and the Law of Torts, [1961] Yale Law Journal (Yale L.J.) 499–553.

    Google Scholar 

  15. G. Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents. A Legal and Economic Analysis (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Here we refer more particularly to: J.P. Brown, Toward an Economic Theory of Liability, [1973] JLS 323–349; P. Diamond, Single Activity Accidents, [1974] JLS, 107–164; W. Landes/R. Posner, The Positive Economic Theory of Tort Law, [1981] Georgia Law Review (Ga. L. Rev.) 851–924; S. Shavell, Strict Liability versus Negligence, [1980] JLS, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  17. This distinction has been made by S. Shavell, [1980] JLS, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See W. Landes/ R. Posner, [1981] Ga. L. Rev. 870 and A.M. Polinsky, Introduction to Law and Economics (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  19. S. Shavell, [1980] JLS, 8 and G. Calabresi, Optimal Deterrence and Accidents, [1975] Yale L.J. 84, 658.

    Google Scholar 

  20. A.M. Polinsky, Introduction to Law and Economics (1983) 39; S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (1987) 11.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Also, it would provide optimal incentives to take an efficient activity level. See on the importance of the activity level also S. Shavell, [1980] JLS, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  22. One commentator notes that if organic or conventional farmers are forced to prevent gene contamination, they may have to abandon their seed-saving practices and, given resistance of the hybrids, use more toxic herbicides. See: H. Preston, Drift of Patented Genetically Engineered Crops: Rethinking Liability Theories, [2003] Tex. L. Rev. 81, 1159.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Another reason for applying strict liability is the nonreciprocal nature of damage possibly suffered by the organic or conventional farmers. In this case, a farmer who plants GM crops gains benefits from his crops, while at the same time exposing his neighbour to a risk that he is not subjected to, e.g. the risk of losing organic certification. See: A.B. Endres, “GMO”: Genetically Modified Organism or Gigantic Monetary Obligation? The Liability Schemes for GMO Damage in the United States and the European Union, [2000] Loyola L.A. International and Comparativ Law Review 22, 491. A rationale behind this argument is probably related to the issue of the distribution of risk and benefit, in which those who gain benefits, while at the same time subjecting others to risks, should pay the damages if those risks materialize.

    Google Scholar 

  24. The interested reader can see for further information on possible defences for instance in the related area of environmental liability M. Faure/ D. Grimeaud, Financial Assurance Issues of Environmental Liability, in: M. Faure (ed.), Deterrence, Insurability and Compensation in Environmental Liability. Future Developments in the European Union (2003) 52–67.

    Google Scholar 

  25. H. Vandenberghe/ M. Van Quickenborne/ P. Hamelink, Overzicht van rechtspraak. Aansprakelijkheid uit onrechtmatige daad (1964–1978), [1980] Tijdschrift voor Privaatrecht (TPR) 1170–1171.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ellstrand has provided several conclusions with regard to gene flow from GM to non-GM crops. First, mating between crops and their wild relatives is common. In this case, mating between GM crops and non-GM relatives is also possible. Second, gene flow does not necessarily lead to serious impacts. Third, natural hybridizations may lead to the problems of increased weediness and invasiveness of some unwanted plants. Fourth, natural hybridizations may also lead to the risk of extinction of wild relatives. Fifth, gene flow varies both between species and within species. Sixth, gene flow may occur at high rates and over high distances. See for more detailed information in: N.C. Ellstrand, Current Knowledge of Gene Flow in Plants: Implications for Transgene Flow, [2003] Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences, Vol. 358, No. 1434, 1166–1168.

    Google Scholar 

  27. R.A. Repp, Biotech Pollution: Assessing Liability for Genetically Modified Crop Production and Genetic Drift, [2000] Idaho Law Review 36, 615A. Similar opinion has been advanced by Endres, who argues that the possibility of cross-pollination is supported by some studies showing that transgenic pollen may be carried by vectors to a great distance even beyond the buffer zone. See: A.B. Endres (supra fn. 25) 487. Lewis also shares this opinion by arguing that when released into the environment, GM crops may cross-pollinate with other plants due to wind or animal pollinators; therefore, so the author argues, the risk of cross-pollination “is almost guaranteed”.S.K. Lewis, Attack of the Killer Tomatoes? Corporate Liability for the International Propagation of Genetically Altered Agricultural Products, [1997] Transnational Lawyer 10, 186.

    Google Scholar 

  28. This point is discussed in S. Shavell, Liability and the Incentive to obtain Information about Risk, [1992] JLS, 259–270; see also L.T. Visscher/H.O. Kerkmeester, Kenbaarheidsvereiste en gewoonte als verweren tegen een aansprakelijkheidsactie: een rechtseconomische benadering, [1996] Tijdschrift voor Milieuschade en Aansprakelijkheidsrecht (TMA) 48–57.

    Google Scholar 

  29. This argument has been powerfully stressed by C. Ott/ H.B. Schäfer, Negligence as Untaken Precaution, Limited Information and Efficient Standard Formation in the Civil Liability System, [1997] International Review of Law and Economics (IRLE) 15–29.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See Bundesgerichtshof, 23 October 1984, [1985] Neue Juristische Wochenschrift (NJW) 16–20 and Bundesgerichtshof, 14 March 1995, [1985] NJW, 26–31.

    Google Scholar 

  31. This has been defended in the Dutch legal literature by J. Drion, Stare Decisis. Het gezag van precedenten (1950) and by O. Haazen, De temporele werking van een rechterlijke uitspraak, in: H.G. Schermers/ Th. L. Bellekom/ P.T.C. Van Kampen (eds.), De rol van de rechter in de moderne Westerse samenleving (1993) 171–207.

    Google Scholar 

  32. A similar — balanced — conclusion concerning the efficiency of a development risk defence is reached by G. Wagner, [1999] VR, 1450.

    Google Scholar 

  33. The state-of-the-art defence has also been addressed in the American context by J. Boyd/ D. Ingberman, [1997] JLS, 433–473. They show that the “customary practice test” tends to induce inadequate safety, whereas the “technological advancement test” tends to induce excessive safety.

    Google Scholar 

  34. And by Spain for food on medical products as well as by France for products derived from the human body. See the overview of the transposition in domestic law, provided in the Green paper on the liability for defective products (COM (1999) 396 final of 28.7.1999) 35–36. The issue of foreseeability defence will be discussed further in section III.

    Google Scholar 

  35. J.P. Brown, [1973] JLS, 340–342; G. Calabresi, [1975] Yale L.J., 663; W. Landes/R. Posner, [1981] Ga. L. Rev., 880–882.

    Google Scholar 

  36. D. Haddock/ C. Curran, An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence, [1985] JLS 14, 59–63.

    Google Scholar 

  37. D. Haddock/ C. Curran, [1985] JLS, 59–63.

    Google Scholar 

  38. R. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (1998) 187–189.

    Google Scholar 

  39. A contributory negligence defence may arise, for example, in the form of the infringement of patent right of a GM crops producer. We could refer to the Monsanto v. Schmeiser case, in which the defendant was found guilty of the infringement of Monsanto’s patent rights for herbicideresistant canola. See: J.L. Fox, Canadian Farmer Found Guilty of Monsanto Canola Patent Infringement, [May 2001] Nature Biotechnology 19, 396–397. The ruling of the court of this case has, however, been severely criticized as the court ignored the fact that the defendant did not use glyphosate, a herbicide to which the patented GM canola is supposed to resist. Some authors argue that if the possession of hybrids containing the patented gene is already a sufficient ground for defendant liability for the infringement of a patent right, then the question of the defendant’s intention should be seriously considered by the court. Otherwise, a farmer whose land has been contaminated by GM crops and, hence, unwillingly grows the hybrids, will be found guilty for the patent infringement. See: M. Lee/R. Burrell, Liability for the Escape of GM Seeds: Pursuing the ‘Victim’?, [2002]Modern Law Review (MLR) 65, 523–525; also: H. Preston (supra fn. 24) 1167–1169.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See e.g. R. Cooter/ T. Ulen (supra fn. 1) 170–185.

    Google Scholar 

  41. D. Wittman, First come, First Served: an Economic Analysis of ‘Coming to Nuisance’, [1980] JLS, 557–568. See also R. Epstein, Nuisance Law: Corrective Justice and its Utilitarian Constraints, [1979] JLS, 72–73; D. Dewees, Tort Law and the Deterrence of Environmental Pollution, in: T.H. Tietenberg (ed.), Innovation in Environmental Policy, Economic and Legal Aspects of Recent Developments in Environmental Enforcement of Liability (1992) 139 and T. Merrill, Trespass, Nuisance and the Costs of Determining Property Rights, [1985] JLS, 13–48.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Compare D. Wittman, [1980] JLS, 567–568.

    Google Scholar 

  43. D.L. Kershen (supra fn. 5) 459.

    Google Scholar 

  44. J.M. Glenn, Footloose: Civil Responsibility for GMO Gene Wandering in Canada, [2004] Washburn Law Journal (Washburn L.J.) 43, 556–557.

    Google Scholar 

  45. See S. Shavell, Liability for Harm versus Regulation of Safety, [1984] JLS, 357–374; S. Shavell, A Model of the Optimal use of Liability and Safety Regulation, [1984] Rand Journal of Economics (Rand J. Econ.) 271–280.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See H. Hansman/ R.H. Kraakman, Toward Unlimited Shareholder Liability for Corporate Torts, [1999] Yale L.J. 100, 1879–1939. Because of this danger of using the corporate structure for externalizing harm to involuntary creditors Hansman and Kraakman plead in favour of unlimited shareholder liability for corporate torts.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. See for instance K.S. Abraham, The Relation between Civil Liability and Environmental Regulation: An Analytical Overview, [2002] Washburn L.J. 41, 379–398.

    Google Scholar 

  48. C.P. Rodgers, Liability for the Release of GMOs into the Environment: Expliring the Boundaries of Nuisance, [2002] Cambridge Law Journal (C.L.J.) 62(2) 390 and 400. However, the author argues that the authorization itself does not constitute a defence. A firmer rejection of the idea of holding an injurer liable for unforeseeable damage is given by Bergkamp. The author argues that deliberate release of GMOs undertaken in compliance with regulations and conditions prior to authorization is quite unlikely to create foreseeable and significant risks. Accordingly, only “non-compliant GMOs or activities involving GMOs conducted in an irresponsible way” that could pose the risks should hence be subjected to liability. L. Bergkamp, Allocating Unknown Risk: Liability for Environmental Damages Caused by Deliberately Released Genetically Modified Organisms, [2000], available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=223068,25. The author goes on by refusing the proposal of singling out biotechnology in a specific liability system. He argues that concerns about environmental impacts of GMOs have been triggered by the fear of the unknown, unforeseeable, and even non-existent risks of GMOs, which cannot be adequately dealt with by a specific liability system. Ibid., 28–29.

    Google Scholar 

  49. S. Smyth/ G.C. Khachatourians/ P.W.B. Phillips, Liabilities and Economics of Transgenic Crops, [June 2002] Nature Biotechnology 20, 537–538. As quoted by Endres, a study conducted in the UK found pollen from GM crops have been carried by bees 4.5 kilometres away from the test field. A.B. Endres (supra fn. 25) 456.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Khoury and Smyth argue that although a risk assessment prior to an authorization of GM crops revealed the remoteness of risks, these risks could still be considered as foreseeable based on public concerns. This is because, as the authors argue, the absence of knowledge does not mean the absence of public concerns about possible risks. As a result, the injurer will still be held liable if these risks materialize in the future. To support this argument, the authors resort to the precautionary principle, by which the injurer is liable when the uncertain risks of serious magnitude materialize in the future. L. Khoury/ S. Smyth, Reasonable Foreseeability and Liability in Relation to Genetically Modified Organisms, in: The 9th ICABR International Conference on Agricultural Biotechnology: Ten Years Later (2005) 20–21.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Some countries may have even not only minimum, but also sub-optimal regulatory standards for GMOs. See for example the critics of Bratspies concerning the US regulation on the commercialization of Bt crops. He argues that the agencies responsible for the release of Bt crops have abandoned the precautionary principle, and instead used the most optimistic estimates as the basis of their decision. In addition, there is no clear mechanism to ensure the growers’ compliance with the requirement set by the seed companies, as it could be assumed that it is not in the companies’ interest to enforce their requirement. See: R. Bratspies, The Illision of Care: Regulation, Uncertainty, and Genetically Modified Food Crops, [2002] New York University Environmental Law Journal (NYU Env. L. J.) 10, 346. Assuming that this allegation is true, releasing an injurer just because he has followed such a non-optimal regulatory standard, may create too much harm for society, in which case the price of GM products does not represent the true social costs.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Compare P. Burrows, Combining Regulation and Liability for the Control of External Costs, [1999] International Review of Law and Economics (IRLE) 19, 227–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. See G. Calabresi, Concerning Cause and the Law of Torts, [1975] University of Chicago Law Review (U. Chi. L. Rev.) 69–108; S. Shavell, An Analysis of Causation and the Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts, [1980] JLS, 463–516 and W. Landes/R. Posner, Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach, [1983] JLS, 109–134.

    Google Scholar 

  54. See S. Shavell, Uncertainty over Causation and the Determination of Civil Liability, [1985] JLE, 587–609 and S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law, 108.

    Google Scholar 

  55. In the absence of a speficic liability system for GMOs, the victim should resort to one of several liability rules, namely tresspass, private nuisance, negligence, strict liability, or product liability. Each of these rules has its own elements that should be proven by the victim. For a brief summary about the elements of nuisance, negligence, and strict liability, readers may consult: T.N. Vollendorf, Genetically Modified Organisms: Someone is in the Kitchen with DNA, Who is Responsible when Someone Gets Burned?, [2001] Mississippi College Law Review 21, 48–53.

    Google Scholar 

  56. The burden of proof borne by the victim might be reduced if GM products are required to be labelled with their genetic markers, as it has been proposed in Europe. See: A.B. Endres (supra fn. 25) 487.

    Google Scholar 

  57. D. Rosenberg, The Causal Connection in Mass Exposure Cases: ‘Public Law’ Vision of the Tort System, [1984], Harvard Law Review (Harv. L. Rev.) 851–929.

    Google Scholar 

  58. D. Kaye, The Limits of the Preponderance of the Evidence Standard: Justifiably Naked Statistical Evidence and Multiple Causation, [1982] American Bar Foundation Research Journal (Am. B. Found. Res. J.) 487–516 and see S. Gold, Causation in Toxic Torts: Burdens of Proof, Standards of Persuasion, and Statistical Evidence, [1986] Yale L.J. 376–402.

    Google Scholar 

  59. S. Shavell, Uncertainty over Causation and the Determination of Civil Liability, [1985] JLE 587–609.

    Google Scholar 

  60. So S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (1987) 116.

    Google Scholar 

  61. So L. Bergkamp, Liability and Environment (2001) 290–291.

    Google Scholar 

  62. See on this proportionate liability J. Makdisi, Proportional Liability: A Comprehensive Rule to Apportion Tort Damages Based on Probability, [1989] North Carolina Law Review, 1063; W. Landes/R. Posner, Tort Law as a Regulatory Regime for Catastrophic Personal Injuries, [1984] JLS, 417–34 and G. Robinson, Probabilistic Causation and Compensation for Tortious Risk, [1985] JLS, 797–798. For a discussion of the possible legal foundation of a proportionate liability rule see A.J. Akkermans, Grondslagen voor proportionele aansprakelijkheid bij onzeker causaal verband, in: W.H. van Boom/C.E.C. Jansen/J.G.A. Linssen (eds.), Tussen ‘Alles’ en ‘Niets’. Van toedeling naar verdeling van nadeel (1997) 105–115.

    Google Scholar 

  63. See G. Brüggemeier, Liability for Water Pollution under German Law: Fault or Strict Liability, in: J. van Dunné (ed.), Transboundary Pollution and Liability: The Case of the River Rhine (1991) 88–91.

    Google Scholar 

  64. G. Robinson, Probabilistic Causation and Compensation for Tortious Risk, [1985] JLS, 798.

    Google Scholar 

  65. See also P. Widmer, Causation under Swiss Law, in: J. Spier (ed.), Unification of Tort Law: Causation (2000) 112–113.

    Google Scholar 

  66. For a detailed analysis of joint and several liability when all defendants are fully solvent see L. Kornhauser/ R. Revesz, Sharing Damages Among Multiple Tort Feasors, [1989] Yale L.J. 831–884 and for the analysis in case of limited solvency see L. Kornhauser/R. Revesz, Apportioning Damages Among Potentially Insolvent Actors, [1990] JLS, 617–651.

    Google Scholar 

  67. An argument in that direction is made by T. Tietenberg (supra fn. 45).

    Google Scholar 

  68. For an excellent analysis of the effects of various systems of extended liability see the recent paper by Boyd and Ingberman who argue that under certain conditions extended liability may promote cost internalisation, but that there are serious drawbacks as well. Hence, they argue that other solutions should be examined to cure the problem of undercapitalisation: J. Boyd/ D. Ingbergman, The Vertical Extension of Environmental Liability through Claims of Ownership, Contact and Supply, in: A. Heyes (ed.), The Law and Economics of the Environment (2001) 44–70.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Then joint and several liability would lead to over-deterrence, so Bergkamp rightly argues: L. Bergkamp (supra fn. 66) 301.

    Google Scholar 

  70. See equally L. Bergkamp (supra fn. 66) 153–154 who argues that joint and several liability may be unfair and may lead to over-deterrence.

    Google Scholar 

  71. For a critical economic analysis of the channelling of nuclear liability see T. Vanden Borre, Transplantatie van ‘kanalisatie van aansprakelijkheid’ van het kernenergierecht naar het milieu (aansprakelijkheids)recht: een goede of een gebrekkige zaak?, in: M. Faure/ K. Deketelaere (eds.), Ius Commune en Milieurecht, Actualia in het Milieurecht in België en Nederland (1997) 329–382.

    Google Scholar 

  72. See M. Trebilcock/ R. Winter, The Economics of Nuclear Accident Law, [1997] IRLE, 232–235.

    Google Scholar 

  73. R.A. Repp (supra fn. 30) 594–595.

    Google Scholar 

  74. As long as such segregations exist, hence there also exist markets for non-GM products, the risks of damage from co-mingling will not be entirely removed. The risk of losing the entire organic market due to co-mingling has motivated Canadian groups of organic farmers to sue two giant GMO producers, Monsanto and Aventis. The farmers argue that the entire organic market for wheat, worth as much as $17.5 million, is threatened due to the commercialization of GM wheat in Canada. See: A. Bouchie, [March 2002] Nature Biotechnology 20, 210.

    Google Scholar 

  75. L. Khoury/ S. Smyth (supra fn. 54) 12. See also: S. Smyth/G.C. Khachatourians/P.W.B. Phillips (supra fn. 53) 539.

    Google Scholar 

  76. R.A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (6th ed. 2003) 192.

    Google Scholar 

  77. R.A. Posner (supra fn. 81) 192.

    Google Scholar 

  78. So S. Shavell, Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law (2004) 236.

    Google Scholar 

  79. S. Shavell (supra fn. 83) 237.

    Google Scholar 

  80. See further R.A. Posner (supra fn. 81) 118.

    Google Scholar 

  81. S. Shavell (supra fn. 83) 304 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  82. R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen, Law and Economics (4th ed. 2004) 239.

    Google Scholar 

  83. See R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen (supra fn. 87) 241.

    Google Scholar 

  84. R.A. Posner (supra fn. 81) 127–128.

    Google Scholar 

  85. R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen (supra fn. 87) 242.

    Google Scholar 

  86. An excellent overview of the literature in this respect is provided by G. Dari Mattiacci, The Economics of Pure Economic Loss and the Internalization of Multiple Externalities, in: W.H. van Boom/ H. Koziol/ Chr.A. Witting (eds.), Pure Economic Loss (2004) 167–190.

    Google Scholar 

  87. So G. Dari Mattiaci H. Koziol/ Chr.A. Witting (eds.), Pure Economic Loss (2004) (supra fn. 91) 169.

    Google Scholar 

  88. See M. Bussani, V. Palmer and F. Parisi, Liability for Pure Financial Loss in Europe: An Economic Restatement, [2003] American Journal of Comparative Law (Am. J. Comp. Law) 51, 113–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  89. For a comprehensive analysis of the problem of pure economic loss in tort see G. Dari Mattiaci H. Koziol/ Chr.A. Witting (eds.), Pure Economic Loss (2004) (supra fn. 91) 167–190.

    Google Scholar 

  90. See R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen (supra fn. 87) 100.

    Google Scholar 

  91. R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen (supra fn. 87) 104.

    Google Scholar 

  92. G. Calabresi/Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules and Ineliability: One View of the Cathedral, [1972] Harv. L. Rev. 85, 1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  93. See for a summary of Calabresi/ Melamed, R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen (supra fn. 87) 104–107.

    Google Scholar 

  94. R. Cooter/ Th. Ulen (supra fn. 87) 168–169.

    Google Scholar 

  95. S. Shavell, Strict Liability versus Negligence, [1980] JLS, 11 and S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (1987) 8.

    Google Scholar 

  96. See M. Faure, Economic Models of Compensation for Damage Caused by Nuclear Accidents: Some Lessons for the Revision of the Paris and Vienna Conventions, [1995] European Journal of Law and Economics (EJLE) 21–43.

    Google Scholar 

  97. This point has been made by S. Rea, Non-pecuniary Loss and Breach of Contract, [1982] JLS, 50–52, but also by M. Adams, Warum kein Ersatz von Nichtvermögensschäden, in: C. Ott/H.B. Schäfer (eds.), Allokationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, 214; and by C. Ott/H.B. Schäfer, Schmerzensgeld bei Körperverletzungen. Eine ökonomische Analyse, [1990] JZ, 564–565. See also M. Faure, Compensation of Non-pecuniary Loss: An Economic Perspective, in: U. Magnus/J. Spier (eds.), European Tort Law, Liber Amicorum for Helmut Koziol (2000) 143–159.

    Google Scholar 

  98. See M. Faure, Environmental Damage Insurance in the Netherlands, Environmental Liability (2002) 31–41 and M. Faure, Environmental Damage Insurance in Theory and Practice, in: T. Swanson (ed.), An Introduction to the Law and Economics of Environmental Policy: Issues in Institutional Design (2002) 283–328.

    Google Scholar 

  99. This argument is especially advanced by G. Priest, The Current Insurance Crisis and Modern Tort Law, [1987] Yale L.J., 1521–1590.

    Google Scholar 

  100. For a more detailed discussion see M. Faure, Economic Criteria for Compulsory Insurance, [2006] Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance (Geneva Pap Risk Ins) 31, 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  101. More particularly by S. Shavell, The Judgement Proof Problem, [1986] IRLE, 43–58.

    Google Scholar 

  102. P.J. Jost, Limited Liability and the Requirement to Purchase Insurance, [1996] IRLE, 259–276. A similar argument has recently been formulated by M. Polborn, Mandatory Insurance and the Judgement-Proof Problem, [1998] IRLE, 141–146 and by G. Skogh, Mandatory Insurance: Transaction Costs Analysis of Insurance, in: B. Bouckaert/G. De Geest (eds.), Encyclopedia of Law and Economics (2000) 521–537. Skogh has also pointed out that compulsory insurance may save on transaction cost.

    Google Scholar 

  103. See also H. Kunreuther/ P. Freeman, Insurability, Environmental Risks and the Law, in: A. Heyes (ed.), The Law and Economics of the Environment (2001) 316.

    Google Scholar 

  104. M. Faure/ R. Van den Bergh, Restrictions of Competition on Insurance Markets and the Applicability of EC Anti-Trust Law, [1995] Kyklos, 65–85.

    Google Scholar 

  105. See M. Faure/ G. Skogh, Compensation for Damages Caused by Nuclear Accidents: A Convention as Insurance, [1992] Geneva Pap Risk Ins, 499–513 and M. Faure, [1995] EJLE, 21–43.

    Google Scholar 

  106. See T.G. Coghlin, Protection and Indemnity Clubs, [1984] Lloyd’s Maritime and Commercial Law Quarterly (LMCLQ) 403–416.

    Google Scholar 

  107. This argument has been made by G. Skogh, The Transactions Cost Theory of Insurance: Contracting Impediments and Costs, [1989] Journal of Risk and Insurance (JR&I) 726–732.

    Google Scholar 

  108. For a summary of this economic literature see inter alia M. Faure, How Law and Economics may Contribute to the Harmonization of Tort Law in Europe, in: R. Zimmermann (ed.), Grundstrukturen des europäischen Deliktsrechts (2003) 31–82.

    Google Scholar 

  109. See in that respect M. Faure/ K. Desmedt, Harmonization of Environmental Liability Legislation in the European Union, in: A. Marciano/ J.-M. Josselin (eds.), From Economic to Legal Competition. New Perspectives on Law and Institutions in Europe (2003) 45–86.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Bernhard A. Koch

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2008 Springer-Verlag/Wien

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Faure, M., Wibisana, A. (2008). Liability in Cases of Damage Resulting from GMOs: an Economic Perspective. In: Koch, B.A. (eds) Economic Loss Caused by Genetically Modified Organisms. Tort and Insurance Law, vol 24. Springer, Vienna. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-211-77988-0_33

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-211-77988-0_33

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Vienna

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-211-77987-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-211-77988-0

Publish with us

Policies and ethics