Skip to main content

2018 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

3. A Critical Realist Perspective on Earnings Management

verfasst von : Bruno Maria Franceschetti

Erschienen in: Financial Crises and Earnings Management Behavior

Verlag: Springer International Publishing

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Prior studies have provided little evidence of earnings management activities although research designs have included the widespread use of strong incentives to manage earnings; i.e., a widespread approach in the earnings management literature is to first identify conditions in which managers’ incentives to manage earnings are likely to be strong, and then test whether patterns of earnings management are observable. Furthermore, the evidence provided by prior studies is often conflicted on what motivates managers to manage earnings. This chapter shifts away from the contradictory conclusions drawn on the causes of earnings management presented by prior positivist research (discussed in Chap. 2). It introduces critical realism as an alternative to the positivist philosophical perspective to investigate the earnings management phenomenon. Finally, it provides a critical realist evaluation of mainstream earnings management literature and related incentives (or identified causes) that have been proposed by prior studies for managing earnings.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
For example, DeAngelo (1986) strongly rejects the hypothesis that managers who propose to take a public corporation private understate the corporation’s earnings prior to the management buyout, and Perry and Williams (1994) indicate that managers manipulate discretionary accruals downward during the year preceding a public announcement of management’s intention to go private.
 
2
For example, an influential article by Teoh et al. (1998b) indicates that during the year that a corporation goes public, initial public offering firms (IPOs) engage in more income-increasing (depreciation) methods. However, contrary to popular belief, Ball and Shivakumar (2008) report that IPOs do not inflate earnings and tend to report more conservatively “in order to meet the market demand for higher quality financials from public firms, and in response to public-firm regulation” (p. 346).
 
3
DeFond (2010) specifies, “abnormal accruals models suffer from the inherent limitation that we are unable to validate the accuracy of their predictions. For example, we are unable to verify whether our estimates of discretionary accruals are the result of management’s opportunistic accounting choices or just an artifact of the particular model we are using” (p. 404).
 
4
David Hume (1711–1776) was a Scottish philosopher, economist and historian during the Age of Enlightenment.
 
5
Collier (2005) provides the following example: “A dog barking may cause a squirrel to run up a tree, but it is not the case that every time a dog barks, a squirrel runs up a tree; there may be no squirrels around, or the squirrel may be blasé about dogs. There is nothing that always follows a dog barking or always precedes a squirrel running up a tree” (p. 328). Collier (2005) suggests that we should express natural laws “not as constant conjunctions—whenever a dog barks, a squirrels runs up a tree-but as tendencies: dogs tend to bark at squirrels, and squirrels tend to run up trees if dogs bark at them” (p. 329).
 
6
Bhaskar (2008a) states, “the real basis of causal laws are provided by the generative mechanisms of nature” (p. 3).
 
7
Bhaskar (2008a) proposed a theory where “statements of laws are tendency statements. Tendencies may be possessed unexercised, exercised unrealised, and realized unperceived (or undetected) by men; they may also be trans-formed” (p. 7).
 
8
As noted by Lawson (1997), “a statement of a tendency, according to its primary usage here, is not about long-run, ‘normal’, usual, or average outcomes at the level of events. Nor is it reducible to a counterfactual claim about events or states of affairs that would occur if the world were different. Indeed, it is not a claim about anything at the level of the actual course of events at all. Rather it is a transfactual statement about the typically non-empirical activity of a structured thing or agent; here transfactuals are not counter-factuals but take us to the level at which things are going on irrespective of the actual outcome. A statement of a tendency, in other words, is […] an unconditional statement about something non-actual and non-empirical. […] a statement of natural necessity without qualifications attached. […] about a power that is being exercised whatever events ensue” (p. 23).
 
9
Bhaskar (2008a) clarifies “that generative mechanisms must exist and sometimes act independently of men and that they must be irreducible to the patterns of events they generate is presupposed by the intelligibility of experimental activity” (p. 42).
 
10
Bhaskar (2008a) explains, “To ascribe a power is to make a statement about possibilities that may not be actualized and that are possessed by the thing whether or not they are known by men; so powers cannot be reduced to their exercise or our ignorance. Now, if powers are possessed by things that act in open systems, their exercise must be normically qualified and they must be seen as tendencies1” (p. 223).
 
11
Bhaskar (2008a) explains, “the cause of a failure of a car to move when the gear is in neutral is not something distinct from and extraneous to the mechanism responsible for its normal motion” (p. 225).
 
12
Hartwig (2007) observe, “tendencies1 are normically qualified powers. Such powers may be possessed unexercised, such that all people have the power to steal, but most refrain from exercising it. Tendency2 is stronger notion of tendency, conveyed in the example: ‘Kleptomaniacs have a tendency to steal’. The second case implies an enduring predisposition towards a certain type of effect or behaviour. Bhaskar argues that in a closed system there is no difference between these two types of tendency: once their intrinsic conditions are satisfied they are enabled, and they then only require some triggering stimulus to be released or put in motion. The crucial difference between the two types of tendency is revealed in open systems. Here the enduring predisposition is related to the pre-existing satisfaction of intrinsic enabling conditions […]. Thus in an open system a tendency1 will need to be stimulated. In other words, it only occurs under a restricted range of conditions” (p. 459).
 
13
“In order to apply any tendency1 or normic statement we must know when the antecedent or stimulus conditions for the mechanism it designates are satisfied. But this does not warrant the prediction of the tendency’s1 fulfilment, i.e. the consequent’s realization, which depends upon the system being closed, and in particular upon the non-intervention of countervailing causes” (Bhaskar 2008a, p. 223).
 
14
Fleetwood (2011) clarified: “of any thing, there is a set of intrinsic properties or intrinsic enabling conditions—denoted icw and icx—that must be satisfied if it is to have an exercised tendency1 to do ø; […]. Of anything, there may be a further set of intrinsic properties or intrinsic enabling conditions—denoted icy and icz—that must be satisfied if it is to have an actualised tendency2 to do ø” (p. 11).
 
15
Bhaskar (2008a) observed, “Offsetting causes are often assumed to be always extrinsic. But the cause of a failure of a car to move when the gear is in neutral is not something distinct from and extraneous to the mechanism responsible for its normal motion…. Now intrinsic offsetting causes may or may not directly interfere with the operation of the mechanism responsible for the satisfaction of the intrinsic enabling conditions. If they do, then we must say that the tendency2 is no longer possessed.” (p. 225).
 
16
Bhaskar refers to tendency6 using different subscripts in different places. Indeed, Bhaskar (2008b) refers to tendency6 as “tendencye” (p. 72) and Bhaskar (2010) refers to tendency6 as “tendencyf” (Bhaskar 2010, p. 62).
 
17
Bhaskar (2000) argues that this tendency is stronger than most of the concepts of tendencies discussed herein; more specifically, from tendency1 to tendency6. In addition, he refers to tendency8 as tendencye*.
 
18
However, Fleetwood (2011) observes that the difference between tendency6, tendency7, and tendency8 “is due to the nature of the systems the tendencies operate in” (p. 13) since all enabling conditions and all stimulating or releasing conditions are satisfied.
 
19
Sayer (2000) uses the following example to demonstrate that the same mechanism can produce different outcomes: the causal mechanism “economic competition can prompt firms to restructure and innovate or to close” (p. 15).
 
20
To demonstrate that different mechanisms can produce the same outcomes, Sayer (2000) explains that one can lose a job for a variety of reasons (p. 15) or to clarify, one can lose a job because of a variety of causal mechanisms.
 
21
For a discussion of the primary causes, see Chap. 2, Sect. 2.​4.
 
22
Here, I argue against the causal law of a constant conjunction model (whenever A occurs, earnings management occurs), although I cannot a priori exclude either the opposite (that earnings management causes something), the presence of other generative mechanisms that may cause something, or the absence of any causal law of a constant conjunction model type.
 
23
In the extant literature, discretionary accruals and earnings management are frequently used as synonyms (Kothari 2001). In alignment with conventional practice (Peasnell et al. 2000), I use the terms “managed accruals,” “discretionary accruals,” “unexpected,” and “abnormal accruals” interchangeably. Similarly, the terms “unmanaged accruals,” “non-discretionary accruals,” “expected,” and “normal accruals” are used interchangeably.
 
24
The Healy (1985), the DeAngelo (1986), the Jones (1991), the Dechow et al. (1995), and the Kothari et al. (2005) models are presented in Chap. 2, Appendix.
 
25
For an overview of the two approaches to calculate total accruals, see Chap. 2, Sect. 2.​3.​1. Precise information regarding cash flows and accruals has become available only after specific accounting principles became effective (Kothari 2001). For example, for US GAAPs, the Statement of Financial Accounting Standards No. 95 (FAS No. 95) issued in 1987 became effective for the annual financial statements of fiscal years ending after July 15, 1988. In 1992, the International Accounting Standards Board issued International Accounting Standard No. 7 (IAS No. 7), which became effective only in 1994 and requires firms to provide cash flow statements. However, local generally accepted accounting principles often do not require a statement of cash flows. Therefore, when investigating, for example, non-listed companies, it will be necessary to extrapolate cash flows from other statements.
 
26
For example, Jones (1991) assumes that nondiscretionary accruals depend on a change in revenues and the level of property, plants, and equipment (Bernard and Skinner 1996, p. 315). The model requires parameters to be estimated during a given period (i.e., the estimation period). Jones (1991) adopted a time-series approach to obtain separate firm-specific estimated parameters for each firm. Jones (1991) consistently excluded firms with less than 14 years of observations and regressed using the longest available time-series of data immediately prior to the “event” year (i.e., the year that earnings management is suspected). However, the Jones (1991) model and other models, such as the modified Jones model employed by Dechow et al. (1995), assumes that during the estimation period, no systematic earnings management is hypothesized. More examples can easily be provided. Healy (1985) assumes that non-discretionary accruals for each firm equal the mean accrual for all other firm-years in his specific portfolio sample. The adapted version of Healy (1985) by Dechow et al. (1995) assumes that non-discretionary accruals for each firm equal the mean of past years’ total accruals. Furthermore, DeAngelo (1986) uses the total accrual of the immediately prior period as a benchmark for the current accrual, absent income manipulation; i.e., the non-manipulated normal accruals value for the current period equals the total accrual value of the prior period.
 
27
Bhaskar (2008a) defines this mistake as the epistemic fallacy, “This consists in the view that statements about being can be reduced to or analysed in terms of statements about knowledge; i.e., that ontological questions can always be transposed into epistemological terms” (p. 26). To clarify, “this consists in confusing the ontological order with the epistemic order, priority in being with priority in deciding claims to being, the question of what has relatively underived (or independent) existence with the question of what entitles us to regard some kinds of statements as grounds for other kinds of statements, etc. In particular, the question of what is capable of independent existence must be distinguished from the question of what must be the case for us to know that something is capable of independent existence” (p. 242).
 
28
For the purpose of this study, however, it is not necessary to extend the analysis beyond tendency5.
 
29
Certain widely accepted definitions were presented in Chap. 2, Sect. 2.​2. Specifically, earnings management can be defined as “a purposeful intervention in the external financial reporting process, with the intent of obtaining some private gain” (Schipper 1989, p. 92); alternatively, earnings management “occurs when managers use judgment in financial reporting and in structuring transactions to alter financial reports to either mislead some stakeholders about the underlying economic performance of the company or to influence contractual outcomes that depend on reported accounting numbers” (Healy and Wahlen 1999).
 
30
More specifically, financial statements are the responsibility of both managers and those responsible for corporate governance.
 
31
Being a manager involves holding a position or performing function within the organization, along with exercising managerial intent, discretion, etc. By virtue of being part of the organization, “management is vested with a set of causal powers that defines its nature” (Tsoukas 1994, p. 297).
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Ackroyd S, Fleetwood S (2005) Realist perspectives on management and organisations. Taylor & Francis, New York Ackroyd S, Fleetwood S (2005) Realist perspectives on management and organisations. Taylor & Francis, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Bartov E (1993) The timing of asset sales and earnings manipulation. Account Rev 68:840–855 Bartov E (1993) The timing of asset sales and earnings manipulation. Account Rev 68:840–855
Zurück zum Zitat Bhaskar R (2008a) A realist theory of science. Taylor & Francis, New York Bhaskar R (2008a) A realist theory of science. Taylor & Francis, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Bhaskar R (2008b) Dialectic: the pulse of freedom. Routledge, New York Bhaskar R (2008b) Dialectic: the pulse of freedom. Routledge, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Bhaskar R (2009) Scientific realism and human emancipation. Taylor & Francis, New York Bhaskar R (2009) Scientific realism and human emancipation. Taylor & Francis, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Bhaskar R (2010) Plato etc: problems of philosophy and their resolution. Routledge, New York Bhaskar R (2010) Plato etc: problems of philosophy and their resolution. Routledge, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Bhaskar R (2011) Reclaiming reality: a critical introduction to contemporary philosophy. Routledge, New York Bhaskar R (2011) Reclaiming reality: a critical introduction to contemporary philosophy. Routledge, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Bisman J (2010) Postpositivism and accounting research: a (personal) primer on critical realism. Australas Account Bus Financ J 4:3–25 Bisman J (2010) Postpositivism and accounting research: a (personal) primer on critical realism. Australas Account Bus Financ J 4:3–25
Zurück zum Zitat Cahan SF (1992) The effect of antitrust investigations on discretionary accruals: a refined test of the political-cost hypothesis. Account Rev 67:77–95 Cahan SF (1992) The effect of antitrust investigations on discretionary accruals: a refined test of the political-cost hypothesis. Account Rev 67:77–95
Zurück zum Zitat Caton GL, Chiyachantana CN, Chua CT, Goh J (2011) Earnings management surrounding seasoned bond offerings: do managers mislead ratings agencies and the bond market? J Financial Quant Anal 46:687–708. doi:10.1017/S0022109011000147 CrossRef Caton GL, Chiyachantana CN, Chua CT, Goh J (2011) Earnings management surrounding seasoned bond offerings: do managers mislead ratings agencies and the bond market? J Financial Quant Anal 46:687–708. doi:10.​1017/​S002210901100014​7 CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Collier A (1994) Critical realism: an introduction to Roy Bhaskar’s philosophy. Verso, London Collier A (1994) Critical realism: an introduction to Roy Bhaskar’s philosophy. Verso, London
Zurück zum Zitat Collier A (2005) Philosophy and critical realism. In: Steintmetz G (ed) The politics of method in the human sciences. Duke University Press, Durham, pp 327–345CrossRef Collier A (2005) Philosophy and critical realism. In: Steintmetz G (ed) The politics of method in the human sciences. Duke University Press, Durham, pp 327–345CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat DeAngelo LE (1986) Accounting numbers as market valuation substitutes: a study of management buyouts of public stockholders. Account Rev 61:400–420 DeAngelo LE (1986) Accounting numbers as market valuation substitutes: a study of management buyouts of public stockholders. Account Rev 61:400–420
Zurück zum Zitat Dechow PM, Sloan RG, Sweeney AP (1995) Detecting earnings management. Account Rev 70:193–225 Dechow PM, Sloan RG, Sweeney AP (1995) Detecting earnings management. Account Rev 70:193–225
Zurück zum Zitat Dyck A, Morse A, Zingales L (2013) How pervasive is corporate fraud. In: Paper presented at the Rotman School of Management. Working Paper No. 2222608 Dyck A, Morse A, Zingales L (2013) How pervasive is corporate fraud. In: Paper presented at the Rotman School of Management. Working Paper No. 2222608
Zurück zum Zitat Eldenburg LG, Gunny KA, Hee KW, Soderstrom N (2011) Earnings management using real activities: evidence from nonprofit hospitals. Account Rev 86:1605–1630. doi:10.2308/accr-10095 CrossRef Eldenburg LG, Gunny KA, Hee KW, Soderstrom N (2011) Earnings management using real activities: evidence from nonprofit hospitals. Account Rev 86:1605–1630. doi:10.​2308/​accr-10095 CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Elder-Vass D (2007) Re-examining Bhaskar’s three ontological domains: the lessons from emergence. Contrib Soc Ontol 15:160 Elder-Vass D (2007) Re-examining Bhaskar’s three ontological domains: the lessons from emergence. Contrib Soc Ontol 15:160
Zurück zum Zitat Harré R, Madden EH (1975) Causal powers: a theory of natural necessity. Blackwell, Oxford Harré R, Madden EH (1975) Causal powers: a theory of natural necessity. Blackwell, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Hartwig M (2007) Dictionary of critical realism. Routledge, London Hartwig M (2007) Dictionary of critical realism. Routledge, London
Zurück zum Zitat Kang E (2008) Director interlocks and spillover effects of reputational penalties from financial reporting fraud. Acad Manage J 51:537–555. doi:10.2307/20159525 CrossRef Kang E (2008) Director interlocks and spillover effects of reputational penalties from financial reporting fraud. Acad Manage J 51:537–555. doi:10.​2307/​20159525 CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kothari S, Mizik N, Roychowdhury S (2015) Managing for the moment: the role of earnings management via real activities versus accruals in SEO valuation. Account Rev 91:559–586. doi:10.2308/accr-51153 CrossRef Kothari S, Mizik N, Roychowdhury S (2015) Managing for the moment: the role of earnings management via real activities versus accruals in SEO valuation. Account Rev 91:559–586. doi:10.​2308/​accr-51153 CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Leach R, Newsom P (2007) Do firms manage their earnings prior to filing for bankruptcy? Acad Account Financ Stud J 11:125–137 Leach R, Newsom P (2007) Do firms manage their earnings prior to filing for bankruptcy? Acad Account Financ Stud J 11:125–137
Zurück zum Zitat Locke J (1690[1999]) An essay concerning human understanding. Electronic classics series. The Pennsylvania State University, Hazleton Locke J (1690[1999]) An essay concerning human understanding. Electronic classics series. The Pennsylvania State University, Hazleton
Zurück zum Zitat McWherter D (2012a) The problem of critical ontology: Bhaskar contra kant. Palgrave Macmillan, New York McWherter D (2012a) The problem of critical ontology: Bhaskar contra kant. Palgrave Macmillan, New York
Zurück zum Zitat McWherter D (2012b) Reconstructing Bhaskar’s transcendental analysis of experimental activity. Cosmos Hist J Nat Soc Philos 8:199–226 McWherter D (2012b) Reconstructing Bhaskar’s transcendental analysis of experimental activity. Cosmos Hist J Nat Soc Philos 8:199–226
Zurück zum Zitat Mingers J, Mutch A, Willcocks L (2013) Critical realism in information systems research. MIS Q 37:795–802 Mingers J, Mutch A, Willcocks L (2013) Critical realism in information systems research. MIS Q 37:795–802
Zurück zum Zitat Modell S (2014) Critical realist accounting research: whence and whither? In: Critical perspectives on accounting conference, Toronto. Ref. CPA2014–2202 Modell S (2014) Critical realist accounting research: whence and whither? In: Critical perspectives on accounting conference, Toronto. Ref. CPA2014–2202
Zurück zum Zitat O’Connor JP, Priem RL, Coombs JE, Gilley KM (2006) Do CEO stock options prevent or promote fraudulent financial reporting? Acad Manage J 49:483–500. doi:10.2307/20159777 CrossRef O’Connor JP, Priem RL, Coombs JE, Gilley KM (2006) Do CEO stock options prevent or promote fraudulent financial reporting? Acad Manage J 49:483–500. doi:10.​2307/​20159777 CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rajgopal S, Venkatachalam M (1998) The association between earnings sensitivity measures and market determined risk exposures: the case of oil price risk for petroleum refiners. Working paper no. 1539, Stanford University Rajgopal S, Venkatachalam M (1998) The association between earnings sensitivity measures and market determined risk exposures: the case of oil price risk for petroleum refiners. Working paper no. 1539, Stanford University
Zurück zum Zitat Sayer RA (1992) Method in social science: a realist approach. Psychology Press, Abingdon, UK Sayer RA (1992) Method in social science: a realist approach. Psychology Press, Abingdon, UK
Zurück zum Zitat Schipper K (1989) Commentary on earnings management. Account Horiz 3:91–102 Schipper K (1989) Commentary on earnings management. Account Horiz 3:91–102
Zurück zum Zitat Sun Y (2013) The use of discretionary expenditures as an earnings management tool: evidence from financial misstatement firms. Working paper, University of California, Berkeley, Berkeley Sun Y (2013) The use of discretionary expenditures as an earnings management tool: evidence from financial misstatement firms. Working paper, University of California, Berkeley, Berkeley
Zurück zum Zitat Zhang X, Bartol KM, Smith KG, Pfarrer MD, Khanin DM (2008) CEOs on the edge: earnings manipulation and stock-based incentive misalignment. Acad Manage J 51:241–258. doi:10.2307/20159507 CrossRef Zhang X, Bartol KM, Smith KG, Pfarrer MD, Khanin DM (2008) CEOs on the edge: earnings manipulation and stock-based incentive misalignment. Acad Manage J 51:241–258. doi:10.​2307/​20159507 CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
A Critical Realist Perspective on Earnings Management
verfasst von
Bruno Maria Franceschetti
Copyright-Jahr
2018
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-54121-1_3