Skip to main content

The Strange Story of Scientific Method

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Origins: Studies in the Sources of Scientific Creativity ((ORIN,volume 3))

Abstract

Let’s begin with a story—not the full strange story of my title but an early part of it.

One day some philosophers decided to take a walk down through history. They had passed through ancient Greece and Rome, continued on through the Middle Ages and the Renaissance, and had come to the 16th and 17th centuries, where they stumbled upon the Scientific Revolution. “What intricate design these experimental instruments and practices display!” they exclaimed. The philosophers marveled at the intelligent order manifested in the theories and explanations. Where could all this design have come from, of a sudden? They agreed that it was virtually a priori true that there can be no design without an intelligent designer, but who or what could the intelligent designer be in this case? Since the preceding generations of inquirers had done nothing comparable, they concluded that these 17th-century natural philosophers had hit upon some intelligent method of discovery, a tool that amplified their intellect. For how else, short of appealing to a direct revelation from God to the innovators, could they possibly explain this explosion of successful problem-solving activity? How else could they account for the production of so much epistemically interesting design, following upon centuries of sterility?

Now this is a true3 story, or at least an archetype with actual instances! A variant of the story is already true of Descartes, as we shall see, who, along with Bacon, is considered a founder of modern scientific method. Bacon died in 1627 and Descartes in 1650, so neither was in a position to reflect on the later work of Newton, Leibniz, and company.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Altenberg, L. (1994). The evolution of evolvability in genetic programming. In Kinnear, K., editor, Advances in Genetic Programming, pages 47–74. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, H. (1973). The Anxiety of Influence: A Theory of Poetry. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1976). Knowledge and Social Imagery. Routledge, London. Second edition: 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borges, J. L. (1954). The library of babel. In Borges, J. L., editor, Labyrinths, pages 51–58. New Directions, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brannigan, A. (1981). The Social Basis of Scientific Discovery. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1974a). Evolutionary epistemology. In Schilpp, 1980, pages 413–463. Reprinted (along with other relevant papers) in Campbell's Methodology and Epistemology for Social Science: Selected Papers. Edited by E. S. Overman. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pages 393–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1974b). Unjustified variation and selective retention in scientific discovery. In Ayala, F. and Dobzhansky, T., editors, Studies in the Philosophy of Biology, pages 139–161. Macmillan, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1997). From evolutionary epistemology via selection theory to a sociology of scientific validity. Evolution and Cognition, 3:5–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chamberlain, T. C. (1897). Studies for students. Journal of Geology, 5:837–848. Reprinted under the title, “The Method of Multiple Working Hypotheses”, in Philosophy of Geohistory, 1785–1970. Edited by C. Albritton. Dowden, Hutchinson and Ross, Stroudsburg, PA, 1975, pages 125–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crevier, D. (1993). AI: The Tumultuous History of the Search for Artificial Intelligence. Basic Books, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cziko, G. (1995). Without Miracles: Universal Selection Theory and the Second Darwinian Revolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cziko, G. (2000). The Things We Do: Using the Lessons of Bernard and Darwin to Understand the What, How, and Why of Our Behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1986). The Blind Watchmaker. W. W. Norton, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1995). Darwin's Dangerous Idea. Simon and Schuster, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1987). Neural Darwinism: The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection. Basic Books, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1969). The Triumph of the Darwinian Method. University of California Press, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, D. (1989). Genetic Algorithms in Search, Optimization, and Machine Learning. Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. and Lewontin, R. (1979). The spandrels of san marco and the panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society, B205:581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J. (1975). Adaptation in Natural and Artificial Systems. University of Michigan, Ann Arbor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J. (1992). Genetic algorithms. Scientific American, pages 66–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J. (1995). Hidden Order: How Adaptation Builds Complexity. Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1988). Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird, P. and Byrne, R. (1991). Deduction. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, N.J.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich, A. (1993). Scientific Discovery: Logic and Tinkering. SUNY Press, Buffalo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, K. (1994). Out of Control: The New Biology of Machines, Social Systems, and the Economic World. Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimura, M. (1983). The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koza, J. (1992). Genetic Programming: On the Programming of Computers by Means of Natural Selection, vol. I. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza, J. (1994). Genetic Programming II: Automatic Discovery of Reusable Programs. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza, J., Bennett III, F., Andre, D., and Keane, M. (1999). Genetic Programming III: Darwinian Invention and Problem Solving. Morgan Kaufmann, San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza, J., Keane, M., Streeter, M., Mydlowec, W., Yu, J., and Lanza, G. (2003). Genetic Programming IV: Routine Human-Competitive Machine Intelligence. Kluwer, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza, J. R., Yu, J., Keane, M. A., and Mydlowec, W. (2000). Evolution of a controller with a free variable using genetic programming. Volume 1802 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages 91–105. Springer-Verlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1978). Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langley, P., Simon, H., Bradshaw, G., and Zytkow, J. (1987). Scientific Discovery: Computational Explorations of the Creative Processes. MIT Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1980). Why was the logic of discovery abandoned? In Nickles, T., editor, Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, pages 173–183. Reidel, Dordrecht. Reprinted in Laudan Laudan, 1981, pages 181–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). Science and Hypothesis. Kluwer, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louis, S. Website: http://www.cse.unr.edu/sushil/.

  • Margolis, H. (1987). Patterns, Thinking, and Cognition: A Theory of Judgment. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, M. (1996). An Introduction to Genetic Algorithms. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, M. and Forrest, S. (1995). Genetic algorithms and artificial life. In Langton, C., editor, Artificial Life: An Overview. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1976). Moral luck. Reprinted in his Mortal Questions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1979, chap. 3, and in Statman (1993), pages 57–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. and Simon, H. (1972). Human Problem Solving. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1981). What is a problem that we may solve it? Synthese, 47:85–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1984). Positive science and discoverability. PSA 1984, 1. Edited by P. Asquith and P. Kitcher. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association:13–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1985). Beyond divorce: Current status of the discovery debate. Philosophy of Science, 52:177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1987). From natural philosophy to metaphilosophy of science. In Kargon, R. and Achinstein, P., editors, Kelvin's Baltimore Lectures and Modern Theoretical Physics: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives, pages 507–541. MIT Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1992a). Epistemic amplification: Toward a bootstrap methodology of science. In Brzezinski, J., Coniglione, F., and Marek, T., editors, Science: Between Algorithm and Creativity, pages 29–52. Eburon, Delft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1992b). Good science as bad history: From order of knowing to order of being. In McMullin, E., editor, The Social Dimensions of Science, pages 85–129. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1995). History of science and philosophy of science. Osiris, 10:139–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (2003a). Evolutionary models of innovation and the Meno problem. In Shavinina, L., editor,International Handbook of Creativity, vol. 1, pages 54–78. Elsevier Scientific Publications, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (2003b). Normal science: From logic of science to case-based and model-based reasoning. In Nickles, T., editor, Thomas Kuhn, pages 142–77. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olby, R. (1979). Mendel no mendelian? History of Science, 17:53–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1877). The fixation of belief. Reprinted with changes in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. 5. Edited by C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1934, pages 358–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1984a). Against putting the phenomena first: The discovery of the weak neutral current. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 15:85–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1984b). Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plotkin, H. (1993). Darwin Machines and the Nature of Knowledge. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1934). Logik der Forschung. Hutchinson, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and Refutations. Routledge and Kegan, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1972). Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1974). Response to Campbell. In Schilpp, 1980, pages 1059–1065.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reitman, W. (1964). Heuristics, decision procedures, open constraints, and the structure of ill-defined problems. In Shelly, M. W. and Bryan, G. L., editors, Human Judgments and Optimality, pages 282–315. John Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1990). Luck. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 64:5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a History of Epistemic Things: Synthesizing Proteins in the Test Tube. Stanford University Press, Stanford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, S. (1986). Scientific discoveries and the end of natural philosophy. Social Studies of Science, 16:387–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, S. (1994). Making up discovery. In Boden, M., editor, Dimensions of Creativity, pages 13–51. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (1980). Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schilpp, P. A., editor (1980). The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court, LaSalle, Ill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, J. (1977). Descartes and the Scientific Revolution: 1618–1634. UMI Dissertation Services, Ann Arbor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, J. and Yeo, R., editors (1986). The Politics and Rhetoric of Scientific Method. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In Feigl, H. and Scriven, M., editors, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, pages 253–329. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1973). The structure of ill structured problems. Artificial Intelligence, 4:181–201. Reprinted in Models of Discovery, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1977, pages 304–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. and Lea, G. (1990). Problem solving and rule induction: A unified view. In Shavlik, J. and Dietterich, T., editors, Readings in Machine Learning, pages 26–43. Morgan Kaufmann, San Mateo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simonton, D. (1988). Scientific Genius: A Psychology of Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1981). Introducing the German Idealists. Hackett, Indianapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Souriau, P. (1881). Theorie de l'Invention. Hatchette, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Statman, D., editor (1993). Moral Luck. SUNY Press, Albany.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1972). Human Understanding. Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics: Or, Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine. Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1976). Moral luck. Reprinted in his Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, chap. 2, and in Statman (1993), pages 35–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winston, P. H. (1992). Artificial Intelligence. Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass. Third edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. (1996). The lack of a priori distinctions between learning algorithms. Neural Computation, 8:1341–1390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. and Macready, W. (1997). No free lunch theorems for optimization. IEEE Transactions on Evolutionary Computation, vol. 1, pages 67–82. Condensed version of 1995 Santa Fe Institute Technical Report, SFITR 95-02-010, “No Free Lunch Theorems for Search”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. Philosophical Review, 82:139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Nickles .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nickles, T. (2009). The Strange Story of Scientific Method. In: Meheus, J., Nickles, T. (eds) Models of Discovery and Creativity. Origins: Studies in the Sources of Scientific Creativity, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3421-2_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics