Skip to main content

Models as Make-Believe

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Beyond Mimesis and Convention

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 262))

Abstract

In this paper I propose an account of representation for scientific models based on Kendall Walton’s “make-believe” theory of representation in art. I first set out the problem of scientific representation and respond to a recent argument due to Craig Callender and Jonathan Cohen, which aims to show that the problem may be easily dismissed. I then introduce my account of models as props in games of make-believe and show how it offers a solution to the problem. Finally, I demonstrate an important advantage my account has over other theories of scientific representation. All existing theories analyze scientific representation in terms of relations, such as similarity or denotation. By contrast, my account does not take representation in modeling to be essentially relational. For this reason, it can accommodate a group of models often ignored in discussions of scientific representation, namely models which are representational but which represent no actual object.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that I use the term “theoretical” only to indicate that scientists do not construct a physical model of the system modeled, and not to imply that the model is derived from some existing theory, like Newtonian mechanics. Recent case studies suggest scientists must often go beyond existing theory to model a system; for example, see Morgan and Morrison (1999).

  2. 2.

    For my own view of the ontology of theoretical modeling, see Toon (2010).

  3. 3.

    Salisbury Cathedral from the Meadows on http://www.nationalgallery.org.uk

  4. 4.

    Versions of this point may be found in Frigg (2006), Hughes (1997) and Suárez (2003), although each draw rather different lessons from it.

  5. 5.

    Callender and Cohen (2006, 68). See also Frigg (2006a) and Hughes (1997).

  6. 6.

    This problem is also raised by Suárez (2003) and Callender and Cohen (2006). As we shall see in section “Models Without Actual Objects”, however, neither provide a solution.

  7. 7.

    See also Callender and Cohen (2006) and Frigg (2006a).

  8. 8.

    Of course, this is not to claim that realism in modeling is the same as realism in painting.

  9. 9.

    Of course, in certain cases such objects may be representational. A chair might be used in a work of abstract art, for example, or a table used to represent a shelter in a play.

  10. 10.

    These central features of the account are introduced in Section 1.5 of Walton (1990).

  11. 11.

    The suggestion that Walton’s theory may be applied in the context of scientific modeling is also found in Barberousse (2006), Barberousse and Ludwig (2000) and Frigg (2010). See below for a discussion of Frigg’s views.

  12. 12.

    For more on the ontology of theoretical modeling, see Toon (2010).

  13. 13.

    The suggestion that models might be understood as fictional entities is found in Godfrey-Smith (2006) and Frigg (2006b). Contessa (2010) follows this approach by developing his own “dualist” account of fictional entities, while Thomson-Jones (2007) also explores versions of this view.

  14. 14.

    Note also that the position I advocate is distinct from what Arthur Fine (1998) calls fictionalism. As Fine characterizes it, fictionalism is an anti-realist position which argues that a scientific theory may be reliable without being true and without the entities it invokes existing. To classify a model as a representation in Walton’s sense is to say nothing about the truth of the propositions the model prescribes or about the existence of the entities it invokes.

  15. 15.

    The terms “accommodationist” and “eliminativist” are taken from Lamarque (2003).

  16. 16.

    This example reminds us that the same prepared description and equation of motion may serve very different representational functions.

  17. 17.

    Similarly, Frigg (2010) suggests that the problem of models without actual objects can be avoided simply by adopting his distinction between p-representation and t-representation. This alone does not seem sufficient to solve the problem, however: we still require an account of t-representation that can explain how some model systems (like the simplified ether model system) can be representational, without representing any actual object.

  18. 18.

    Giere allows there may be other ways in which models are used to represent, although does not specify any; see also Giere (1988, 1999).

  19. 19.

    “D.D.I.” stands for “denotation, demonstration, and interpretation”. According to Hughes, these combine in the following way: elements of the physical world are denoted by elements of the model; the model possesses an internal dynamic that allows us to demonstrate theoretical conclusions; these in turn need to be interpreted if we are to make predictions (Hughes 1997, S325).

  20. 20.

    Callender and Cohen also attempt to defer the problem posed by models without actual objects, observing that “the worry arises for all species of representation—not just scientific representation—and there is no reason to suspect that whatever ultimately explains representations of unicorns and golden mountains won’t work for representation of phlogiston and the ether” (2006, 81). There is an important difference between Callender and Cohen’s deferral strategy and my own, however. Callender and Cohen simply express a hope that a solution to the problem for other forms of representation may be applied to scientific models. They tentatively suggest a “Humean strategy”, which provides a relational theory for “atomic” representations and explains representations without actual objects as constructed as “compounds” of other representations. But they do not show whether this can be applied to scientific models, nor whether their account would remain intact if it were. This amounts simply to deferring the problem for scientific representation itself. By contrast, my own account reduces the problem of understanding models without actual objects to the more general problem of understanding imaginings about fictional entities.

References

  • Barberousse, A. (2006), “Images of Theoretical Models”, unpublished paper delivered at A.P.A. Pacific Division Mini-Conference on Scientific Images, March 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberousse, A. and Ludwig, P. (2000), “Les modèles comme fictions”, Philosophie 68: 16–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. and Cohen, J. (2006), “There Is No Special Problem About Scientific Representation”, Theoria 55: 7–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2010), “Scientific Models as Fictional Objects”, Synthese 172: 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1998), “Fictionalism”, in E. Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, URL = <http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/Q035>. Retrieved December 05, 2007.

  • Frigg, R. (2006a), “Scientific Representation and the Semantic View of Theories”, Theoria 55: 49–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2006b), “Scientific Models”, with Stephan Hartmann, in S. Sarkar and J. Pfeifer (eds.), The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. New York: Routledge, 740–749.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010) “Models and Fiction”, Synthese 172: 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1999), Science Without Laws. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2004), “How Models are Used to Represent Reality”, Philosophy of Science 71: S742–S752.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006), “The Strategy of Model-Based Science”, Biology and Philosophy 21: 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2003), “Representation in Art”, in J. Levinson (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 192–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1976), Languages of Art. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. I. G. (1997), “Models and Representation”, in PSA 1996, vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, S325–S336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarque, P. (2003), “Fiction”, in J. Levinson (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 377–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. and Morrison, M. (eds.) (1999), Models as Mediators. Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (1999), “Theories, Models, and Representations”, in L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessiand and P. Thagard (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning and Scientific Discovery. New York: Kluwer/Plenum, 75–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2003), “Scientific representation: against similarity and isomorphism”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17: 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004), “An Inferential Conception of Scientific Representation”, Philosophy of Science 71: S767–S779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2007), “Missing Systems and the Face Value Practice”, URL = < http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00003519 >.

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2010), “Missing Systems and the Face Value Practice”, Synthese 172: 283–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2010), “The Ontology of Theoretical Modelling: Models as Make-Believe”, Synthese 172: 301–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1990), Mimesis as Make-Believe: on the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells, H. G. (2005), The War of the Worlds. London: Penguin (1st ed., 1898).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper is based on a talk delivered at the “Beyond Mimesis and Nominalism: Representation in Art and Science” conference held at London School of Economics and the Courtauld Institute of Art in June 2006. Parts of the paper were also presented at the Philosophy Workshop in Cambridge in June 2006, the CMM Graduate Conference held in Leeds in June 2007, and the “Scientific Models: Semantics and Ontology” workshop, held in Barcelona in July 2007. I would like to thank participants at all of these events. Thanks also to Nancy Cartwright, Stacie Friend, Manuel Garcia-Carpintero, Ronald Giere, Mary Leng, Mauricio Suárez, Paul Teller, Martin Thomson-Jones and Kendall Walton for helpful discussion and correspondence, and to Roman Frigg and two anonymous referees for comments on drafts of this paper. Finally, I would like to thank my PhD supervisor Martin Kusch, and my advisor, the late Peter Lipton. Research for this paper was supported by The Arts and Humanties Research Council, The Darwin Trust of Edinburgh and The Rausing Fund for History and Philosophy of Science. I am very grateful to all of these institutions for their support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam Toon .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Toon, A. (2010). Models as Make-Believe. In: Frigg, R., Hunter, M. (eds) Beyond Mimesis and Convention. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 262. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3851-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics