Skip to main content
Log in

Structure-induced equilibrium and legislative choice

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusion

Professor Tullock has raised a central question in the confrontation between abstract models of PMR and majority rule as practiced in real institutions. We believe the decision making stability of real-world legislatures lies in the way these legislatures institutionalize majority rule. Logrolling, vote trading, coalition formation, and bargaining are red herrings in this argument. Rather, it is the restrictions on such legislative exchange that promote structure-induced equilibrium. Put differently, institutional arrangements place constraints on the completeness of the majority rule relation by restricting social comparisons.

The framework developed here shows that an assumption implicit in the discussions of many majority rule theorists fails to hold. In part, the implicit rationale for focusing upon PMR was that results proved for this rule were presumed to hold forany institution based on PMR. In one sense this remains true, namely, that the majority rule win sets,W(x), are everywhere non-empty. In another sense, however, it is not true that all properties of institutions based upon majority rule are inherited from PMR. The theory outlined above shows that stability may not be as elusive as theorists of PMR have concluded.

The concept of equilibrium developed in the last section incorporates the major features of prominent choice institutions as well as capturing the special cases in the literature cited in Section II. We now turn to a brief discussion of future work. We address the question that remains, in our opinion, the salient one in the study of institutions and their effect on policy choice, namely, understanding the factors governing the choice of one institutional arrangement over another.

Throughout this paper, we have distinguished agreements that transform the rules from agreements (or vote-trades) that take place within a given set of rules. In principle, anything attainable under the former could also be attained under the latter if there were some form of mechanism to enforce vote-trades as contracts. Under such a rubric, complex legislative agreements in the form of contingent contracts achieve the desired result without resorting to the institutionalization of a rule. In practice, however, there are several problems with vote-trading agreements as contracts. First, the cost of writing these contracts is often quite high due to the number of potential contingencies for which provision must be made. Second, and more important, PMR lacks an enforcement mechanism. Individual parties to contracts in market settings have recourse to the courts. This provides protection beyond the assurance of good faith and brand names. No comparable institution exists within the legislature to supplement the natural though imperfect brand name phenomenon (i.e., that of ‘keeping one's word’ to preserve and enhance credibility for future trades).

While the legislature could create a court or committee to monitor contracts and enforce agreements, alternatively, it could simply impose a rule binding upon everyone which insured the outcome sought. Of the two alternative institutions, the latter probably economizes on transaction costs, particularly for those situations that recur with some frequency. With a rule, a new contract need not be negotiated each time between new sets of players. Moreover, a contingency clause might easily be appended to a rule to cover cases where there is widespread agreement that it is inappropriate. For example, in the Congress a special majority may vote to suspend the rules (note that if only a simple majority were required, then this would be no different from PMR).Footnote 1 In sum, logrolling solutions to the problem of forging agreements are unworkable because they lack enforcement mechanisms. Logrolling, then, cannot constitute an answer to the question, ‘Why so much stability?’Footnote 2

If institutional rules are to constitute an answer to Tullock's stability question, then we must confront the manner in which those rules are chosen. There are very few theories about the choice of rules — exceptions include Buchanan and Tullock (1962), Buchanan (1975, 1979), and contributions in the property rights literature. Even in the absence of a theory, we may still worry that constitutional choice processes (the choice of rules) are vulnerable to the same instabilities found in PMR. We term this the ‘Riker Objection’ since this issue was recently posed by Riker (1980). If institutional constraints create equilibrium — that is, if transformations of a PMR institution into a non-PMR institution create a situation of equilibrium from one without an equilibrium — then preferences over outcomes lead naturally to aninduced set of preferences over institutional arrangements. In this sense, an individual prefers one institution over another if he prefers the equilibrium policy state of one over the equilibrium (or unpredictability) of the other. In the case of multiple equilibria, an individual prefers the institution that yields the highest expected utility given a probability distribution over equilibrium states (Plott, 1972).

As long as preferences for policy states differ, then preferences over institutions with differing equilibrium states (distribution of equilibria) should also differ. The Riker Objection suggests that a simple extension of McKelvey's Chaos Theorem predicts endless cycles here so long as PMR governs the choice over institutions. In this sense, the existence of institutions and their stability must remain, like policy choices under PMR, tenuous — what Riker calls ‘unstable constants.’ Nevertheless, empirically we observe institutions persisting for long periods; in light of the Riker Objection, Tullock's question applies at this level as well.

We may make several observations that imply an attenuation of endless cycling at the institutional-choice level. First, typically, non-PMR rules govern the choice of new rules. Second, it is risky to attempt to change the status quo contrary to the interests of those currently in control. Since failure may lead to the imposition of sanctions, expected gains must be weighed against the certainty of these sanctions. While this does not rule out changes, it will reduce the number of attempts. This is surely the conclusion to be drawn from a reading of the history of the U.S. Congress. The comparison between choice in this setting and the McKelvey world, then, is not parallel since proposals are costless to make in the latter but not in the former. Finally, there often exists a well-defined status quo alternative. In the case of the social contract, the status quo is the Hobbesian state of nature. For the case of the U.S. Constitutional Convention, it was the Articles of Confederation (Riker, 1979). In these and similar settings, even though there may be no formal rule that the status quo must literally be voted last; this restriction nevertheless may hold de facto. Consequently, the constitutional outcome is either the status quo ante or an alteration that cannot be vetoed, i.e., an element in the ‘win set’ of the status quo. With these qualifications in mind, the effect of the Riker Objection is mitigated. Even at the constitutional level, then, restrictions on the ability of individuals to make proposals may induce equilibrium.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is the same rationale that underpins the Uniform Commercial Code and other areas of the law of contracts. To cover situations that occur quite regularly, certain standard procedures are written into the law and are automatically a part of any agreement or exchange. This significantly lowers transaction costs (contracts need not be negotiatedsui generis), and in those circumstances where the standard is inappropriate, the parties may simply contract around it. Similar results occur in most areas of the common law. For further discussion, see Posner (1976).

  2. This reasoning justifies our separation throughout the text of choices within a given institution and choices among institutions. This distinction is a natural one, dating back to Buchanan and Tullock'sThe Calculus of Consent. There they analyze separately the constitutional calculus of choice over voting rules and the behavior under a specific voting rule.

References

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1975).The limits of liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1979).What should economists do? Indianapolis: Liberty Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., and Tullock, G. (1962).The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. (1979). Cyclic sets in multidimensional voting models.Journal of Economic Theory 20: 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L., and Matthews, S. (1980). Constrained Plott equilibria, directional equilibria, and global cycling sets.Review of Economic Studies 47: 975–986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiorina, M. P. (1980). Legislative facilitation of government growth: Universalism and reciprocity practices in majority rule institutions.Research in Public Policy Analysis and Management 1: forthcoming.

  • Isaac, R. M., and Plott, C. R. (1978). Cooperative game models of the influence of the closed rule in three person majority rule committees: Theory and experiments. In P. C. Ordeshook (Ed.),Game theory and political science. New York: New York University Press. 283–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J. B. (1972). On division of the question.Public Choice 13: 47–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, G. H. (1973). On a class of equilibrium conditions for majority rule.Econometrica 41: 285–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D. (1976). Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for agenda control.Journal of Economic Theory 12: 472–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D. (1977). Constructing majority paths between arbitrary points. Paper delivered at American Economic Association Meetings. New York.

  • McKelvey, R. D. (1979). General conditions for global intransitivities in formal voting models.Econometrica 47: 1085–1111.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D., and Wendell, R. E. (1976). Voting equilibria in multidimensional choice spaces.Mathematics of Operations Research 1: 144–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. J. (1979). Experimental results in two-party agenda setting: What's it worth to be a party? Working paper. Michigan State University.

  • Plott, C. R. (1967). A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under majority rule.American Economic Review 57: 787–806.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R. (1972). Individual choice of a political-economic process. In R. G. Niemi and H. F. Weisberg (Eds.),Probability models of collective decision making. Columbus: Charles E. Merrill Publishing Co. 83–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R., and Levine, M. E. (1978). A model of agenda influence on committee decisions.American Economic Review 68: 146–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (1977).Economic analysis of law. 2nd Edition. Boston: Little-Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1979). The verification of scientific generalizations by historical case studies: The genesis of the American Constitution. Presented at Meeting of Social Science History Association. Cambridge, Mass.

  • Riker, W. H. (1980). Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions.American Political Science Review 74: 432–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romer, T., and Rosenthal, H. (1978). Political resource allocation, controlled agendas, and the status quo.Public Choice 33: 27–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. (1978). Instability of simple dynamic games.Review of Economic Studies 45: 575–594.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. (1980). Formal political theory.Quality and Quantity 14: 249–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A. (1979a). Institutional arrangements and equilibrium in multidimensional voting models.American Journal of Political Science 23: 27–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A. (1979b). The role of institutional structure in the creation of policy equilibrium. In D. W. Rae and T. J. Eismeier (Eds.),Public choice and public policy. Beverly Hills: Sage. 249–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A., and Weingast, B. R. (1980). Political solutions to market problems: The political incidence of economic benefits and costs. Delivered at Meetings of Public Choice Society. San Francisco.

  • Shepsle, K. A., and Weingast, B. R. (1981). Political preferences for the pork barrel: A generalization.American Journal of Political Science 25: 96–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloss, J. (1973). Stable outcomes in majority rule voting games.Public Choice 15: 19–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slutsky, S. M. (1977). A voting model for the allocation of public goods: Existence of an equilibrium.Journal of Economic Theory 14: 299–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1967). The general irrelevance of the general impossibility theorem.Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 1967, p. 256. Reprinted inTowards a mathematics of politics, 1967, University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, Michigan, p. 37.

  • Tullock, G. (1981). Why so much stability?Public Choice 37: 189–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weingast, B. R. (1979). A rational choice perspective on Congressional norms.American Journal of Political Science 24: 245–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weingast, B. R. (1981). Regulation, reregulation, and deregulation: The political foundations of agency-clientele relationships.Law and Contemporary Problems 44: 147–177.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

Mr. Shepsle is Professor of Political Science and Research Associate at the Center for the Study of American Business, Washington University. Mr. Weingast is Assistant Professor of Economics and Research Associate at the Center for the Study of American Business, Washington University. This paper was stimulated by Tullock's paper, ‘Why so much stability?’ We would like to thank author Tullock for sending us the early versions of this paper, and editor Tullock for encouraging us to write up our own comments and thoughts. An earlier version was presented at the Annual Meeting of the Public Choice Society, New Orleans, 1981, where it benefitted from wide-ranging discussion. We also greatly benefitted from several conversations with John Ferejohn.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Shepsle, K.A., Weingast, B.R. Structure-induced equilibrium and legislative choice. Public Choice 37, 503–519 (1981). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00133748

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00133748

Keywords

Navigation