Skip to main content
Log in

Violations of dominance in pricing judgments

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The dominance principle states that the judged price of gamble A should be equal to or greater than the judged price of gamble B whenever A's outcomes are equal to or better than the corresponding outcomes of B, holding everything else constant. Subjects often violate the dominance principle by assigning a higher price to a gamble with some probability of winning a positive amount, Y, otherwise zero, than to a superior gamble with the same chances of winning Y, otherwise winning X. Violations also occur with losses. Results are consistent with a configural-weight theory in which the decision weight for each outcome depends on the rank of the outcome with respect to the other outcomes in the lottery and the value of the outcome (zero vs. nonzero).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Arnobius. (1949). The Case Against the Pagans. (H. Bryce and H. Campbell, translators and annotators). Winchester, MD: Newman Press, 116–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • BirnbaumM. H. (1974). “The Nonadditivity of Personality Impressions”, Journal of Experimental Psychology (Monograph) 102, 543–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • BirnbaumM. H. (1976). “Intuitive Numerical Prediction”, American Journal of Psychology 89, 417–429.

    Google Scholar 

  • BirnbaumM. H. and B. A.Mellers. (1983). “Bayesian Inference: Combining Base Rates with Opinions of Sources who Vary in Credibility”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 45, 792–804.

    Google Scholar 

  • BirnbaumM. H. and S. E.Stegner. (1979). “Source Credibility: Bias, Expertise, and the Judge's Point of View”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37, 48–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • BirnbaumM. H. and S. E.Stegner. (1981). “Measuring the Importance of Cues in Judgment for Individuals: Subjective Theories of IQ as a Function of Heredity and Environment”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 17, 159–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. H., G. Coffey, B. A. Mellers and R. S. Weiss. (1992). “Utility Measurement: Configural-Weighting Theory and the Judge's Point of View,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, in press.

  • Birnbaum, M. H. and S. E. Sutton. (1992). “Scale Convergence and Decision Making,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, in press.

  • BirnbaumM. H., R.Wong and L.Wong. (1976). “Combining Information from Sources that Vary in Credibility”, Memory & Cognition. 4, 330–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • CoombsC. H., T. G.Bezembinder and F. M.Goode. (1967). “Testing expectation theories of decision making without measuring utility or subjective probability”, Journal of Mathematical Psychology 4, 72–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grier, B. (1981). The Origin of Risky Choice and the Dominance Principle. Paper presented at the Fourteenth Annual Mathematical Psychology Meetings, Santa Barbara, CA.

  • HammackJ. and G. M.Brown. (1974). Waterfowl and Wetlands: Towards Bioeconomic Analysis. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press for Resources of the Future.

    Google Scholar 

  • HorwichP. (1982). Probability and Evidence. Cambridge University Press. New York: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • KahnemanD. and A.Tversky. (1984). “Choices, Values, and Frames”, American Psychologist 39, 341–350

    Google Scholar 

  • KnetschJ. L. and J. A.Sinden. (1984). “Willingness to Pay and Compensation Demanded: Experimental Evidence of an Unexpected Disparity in Measures of Value”, Quarterly Journal of Economics 99, 507–522.

    Google Scholar 

  • LopesL. (1984). “Risk and Distributional Inequality”, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 10, 465–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. (1986). “Comments on Plott and on Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler”, Journal of Business 59, S337-S343.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. (1988). “Rank-dependent, subjective expected utility representations”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 1, 305–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. (1990). “Rational versus plausible accounting equivalences in preference judgments”, Psychological Science 1, 225–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. (1991). “Rank-and Sign-Dependent Utility Models for Binary Gambles”, Journal of Economic Theory 53, 75–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. (1992). “Where Does Subjective Expected Utility Fail Descriptively?” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5, 5–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. and P. C.Fishburn. (1991). “Rank- and Sign-Dependent Linear Utility Models for Finite First-Order Gambles”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 4, 29–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • LuceR. D. and L.Narens. (1985). “Classification of Concatenation Structures According to Scale Type”, Journal of Mathematical Psychology 29, 1–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • MarshallJ. D., J. L.Knetsch and J. A.Sinden. (1986). “Agent's Evaluations and the Disparity in Measures of Economic Loss”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 7, 115–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellers, B., L. Ordóñez and M. Birnbaum. (1992). “A Change-of-Process Theory for Contextual Effects and Prefer-ence Reversals in Risky Decision Making,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, in press.

  • QuigginJ. (1982). “A Theory of Anticipated Utility”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 3, 324–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • RoweR. D., R. C.d'Arge and D. S.Brookshire. (1980). “An Experiment on the Economic Value of Visibility”, Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 8, 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • TroutmanC. M. and J.Shanteau. (1977). “Inferences Based on Nondiagnostic Information”, Organizational Behavior and Human Perfornance 19, 43–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • TverskyA. and D.Kahneman. (1986). “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions”, Journal of Business 59, S251-S278.

    Google Scholar 

  • TverskyA., Sattah, and P.Slovic. (1988). “Contingent Weighting in Judgment and Choice”, Psychological Review 95, 371–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • ViscusiW. K. (1989). “Prospective Reference Theory: Toward an Explanation of the Paradoxes”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 2, 235–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • YaariM. E. (1987). “The Dual Theory of Choice Under Risk”, Econometrica 55, 95–115.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

The authors thank Shi-jie Chang, Duncan Luce, and Lisa Ordóñez for comments on an earlier draft. This research was supported by a National Science Foundation grant to the first author (BNS-8451368). Requests for reprints should be sent to Barbara Mellers, Dept. of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mellers, B., Weiss, R. & Birnbaum, M. Violations of dominance in pricing judgments. J Risk Uncertainty 5, 73–90 (1992). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00208788

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00208788

Key words

Navigation