Skip to main content
Log in

Consequences of reversing preferences

  • Published:
The Mathematical Intelligencer Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Other than standard election disruptions involving shenanigans, strategic voting, and so forth, it is reasonable to expect that elections are free from difficulties. But this is far from being true; even sincere election outcomes admit all sorts of counterintuitive conclusions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Borda, J. C. 1781,Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin, Histoire de l013E;Académie Royale des Sciences, Paris.

  2. Condorcet, M. 1785.Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix, Paris.

  3. Copeland, A. H. 1951, A reasonable social welfare function.Mimeo, University of Michigan.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Gibbard, A., 1973, Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result.Econometrica 41, 587–601.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Kemeny J., 1959, Mathematics without numbers.Daedalus 88, 571–591.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Merlin, V., M. Tataru, and F. Valognes 2000, On the probability that all decision rules select the same winner,Journal of Mathematical Economics 33, 183–208.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Nanson, E. J., 1882, Methods of elections,Trans. Proc. R. Soc. Victoria 18, 197–240.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Nurmi, H., 1999,Voting Paradoxes and How to Deal with Them, Springer-Verlag, NY.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Nurmi, H., 2002,Voting Procedures under Uncertainty Springer Verlag, Heidelberg.

  10. Ratliff, T. 2001, A comparison of Dodgson’s method and Kemeny’s rule,Social Choice & Welfare 18, 79–89.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Ratliff, T. 2002, A comparison of Dodgson’s Method and the Borda Count,Economic Theory 20, 357–372.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Ratliff, T. 2003, Some starting paradoxes when electing committees, to appearSocial Choice & Welfare

  13. Riker, W. H., 1982,Liberalism Against Populism, W. H. Freeman, San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Saari, D. G., 1992, Millions of election rankings from a single profile,Social Choice & Welfare (1992) 9, 277–306.

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Saari, D. G. 1994,Geometry of Voting, Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Saari, D. G. 1995,Basic Geometry of Voting, Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Saari, D. G. 1999, Explaining all three-alternative voting outcomes,Journal of Economic Theory 87, 313–355.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Saari, D. G. 2000a, Mathematical structure of voting paradoxes 1 ; pairwise vote,Economic Theory 15, 1–53.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  19. Saari, D. G. 2000b, Mathematical structure of voting paradoxes 2: positional voting.Economic Theory 15, 55–101.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Saari, D. G. 2001,Chaotic Electionsl A Mathematician Looks at Voting, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Saari, D. G., and V. Merlin 2000, A geometric examination of Kemeny’s rule,Social Choice & Welfare 17, 403–438.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  22. Saari, D. G., and J. Van Newenhizen, 1988, Is Approval Voting an “unmitigated evil?”Public Choice 59, 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Saari, D. G. and M. Tataru 1999, The likelihood of dubious election outcomes,Economic Theory 13, 345–363.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Satterthwaite, M., 1975, Strategyproofness and Arrow’s conditions,Jour. Econ. Theory 10, 187–217.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  25. Tabarrok, A., 2001, Fundamentals of voting theory illustrated with the 1992 election, or could Perot have won in 1992?Public Choice 106, 275–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Tabarrok, A. and L. Spector 1999, Would the Borda Count have avoided the Civil War?Journal of Theoretical Politics 11, 261–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Tataru, M., and V. Merlin 1997, On the relationships of the Condorcet winner and positional voting rules,Mathematical Social Sciences 34, 81–90.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Donald G. Saari.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Saari, D.G., Barney, S. Consequences of reversing preferences. The Mathematical Intelligencer 25, 17–31 (2003). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02984858

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02984858

Keywords

Navigation