Skip to main content
Log in

Darwinism in economics: from analogy to continuity

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Journal of Evolutionary Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Currently there is an ongoing discussion about how Darwinian concepts should be harnessed to further develop economic theory. Two approaches to this question, Universal Darwinism and the continuity hypothesis, are presented in this paper. It is shown whether abstract principles can be derived from Darwin’s explanatory model of biological evolution that can be applied to cultural evolution. Furthermore, the relation of the ontological basis of biological and cultural evolution is clarified. Some examples illustrate the respective potential of the two approaches to serve as a starting-point for theory development.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term “Universal Darwinism” was coined by Dawkins (1983).

  2. Hodgson and Knudsen (personal communication) argue that abstraction removes the particular content from the specific domain in which a principle applies. Hence, they maintain, the abstract principle may be applied in different domains. On the other hand, Knudsen argues “… that an appreciation of the causal structure of neo-Darwinism may help develop a general selection theory which can be used as a basis for a development of evolutionary economics” (Knudsen 2002, p. 446). Obviously, some domain-specific content in the form of a ‘causal structure’ is reentering the argument here. Hodgson (2002, 2003) introduces socio-economic replicators such as habits, routines, and institutions, which are compared to DNA, and that are subsequently subject to selection processes. Again, some domain-specific contents from biology seem to inspire the development of the argument.

  3. Most biologists, anthropologists, and geneticists today assume that natural selection is no longer a source of systematic change of the genetic endowment of man (see, e.g., Mayr 2001, p. 261f; Tomasello 1999a). Hence, the basic genetic endowment of man is very similar to the one that has been in place by the time natural selection stopped exerting a systematic influence on the human genome.

  4. Modifications of the basic principles of Darwinism in the course of time, for example, Weismann’s neo-Darwinism or the evolutionary synthesis, did not call into question these foundations.

  5. Hodgson and Knudsen (personal communication) claim that only these three principles are necessary and apply to both biological and socio-economic evolution.

  6. While formal institutions—where institutions are defined as the recurrent coordination of individual interactions—are deliberately conceived and implemented, informal institutions can emerge as a consequence of repeated human action, not involving conscious human design (see, e.g., Smith 1993; Hayek 1967, p. 66ff). These institutions may subsequently be subject to deliberate considerations.

  7. Knudsen claims that there are analogues of genotypes and phenotypes in the economic realm. He says that a “… replicator/interactor distinction is possibly such a general feature common to both social and biological systems” (Knudsen 2004, p. 157; see also Hodgson and Knudsen 2004). However, a clear-cut distinction between replicators and interactors in the cultural sphere is hardly possible. Knudsen concedes that it “… is further possible that a replicator in one hierarchy can function as an interactor in another” (Knudsen 2004, p. 157).

  8. There are two kinds of selection: first, there is natural selection for general viability that improves adaptedness and, second, there is sexual selection, both leading to greater reproductive success (Mayr 1991, p. 164). As will be shown in this section, it is problematic to talk about ‘natural selection’ in the cultural sphere, as it is done by, for example, Knudsen (2002), who uses the term “economic natural selection”. The second kind of selection is definitely hard to identify in cultural evolution.

  9. Knudsen states that in “… order to protect the replicator (routines or teams), the possibility of reverse influence from interactors to replicators must be restricted at a fundamental level in the nested hierarchy of replicators and interactors … If this were not the case, the stability needed to produce reliable feedback in a selection process might be lost“ (Knudsen 2004, p. 158).

  10. Artifacts with similar purposes, for instance, can be designed to very different specifications and chosen for very different reasons (Ziman 2000, p. 7).

  11. Although the existence of a common ontological basis with evolutionary biology is denied by some approaches to economics and Darwinian concepts are often applied in a more heuristic fashion, serious problems remain: true analogies do not hold and the metaphorical use of Darwinian principles risks concealing the real mechanisms underlying economic and cultural evolution.

  12. Neoclassical economics has constructed a misleading analogy between Newtonian classical mechanics and the economic sphere.

References

  • Alexander RD (1981) Evolution, culture, and human behavior: some general considerations. In: Alexander RD, Tinkle DW (eds) Natural selection and social behavior. Chiron, New York pp 509–520

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1980) Sociobiology, culture and economic theory. J Econ Behav Organ 1:97–121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordes C (2004) The human adaptation for culture and its behavioral implications. J Bioecon 6(2):143–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordes C (2005a) Long-term tendencies in technological creativity: a preference-based approach. J Evol Econ 15(2):149–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordes C (2005b) Veblen’s “instinct of workmanship”, its cognitive foundations, and some implications for economic theory. J Econ Issues 39(1):1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of the species by means of natural selection. Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1983) Universal Darwinism. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to men. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, pp 403–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Durham WH (1976) The adaptive significance of cultural behavior. Hum Ecol 4(2):89–121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1967) Studies in philosophy, politics and economics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Illinois

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2002) Darwinism in economics: from analogy to ontology. J Evol Econ 12:259–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2003) The mystery of the routine: the Darwinian destiny of an evolutionary theory of economic change. Rev Econ 54(2):355–384

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2004) The firm as an interactor: firms as vehicles for habits and routines. J Evol Econ 14(3):281–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006) Why we need a generalized Darwinism: and why generalized Darwinism is not enough. J Econ Behav Organ (forthcoming)

  • Khalil EL (1995) Neo-classical economics and neo-Darwinism: clearing the way for historical thinking. In: Hodgson GM (ed) Economics and biology. Edward Elgar, Aldershot pp 548–598

    Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen T (2002) Economic selection theory. J Evol Econ 12:443–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen T (2004) General selection theory and economic evolution: the price equation and the replicator/interactor distinction. J Econ Methodol 11(2):147–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruger AC, Ratner HH, Tomasello M (1993) Cultural learning. Behav Brain Sci 16:495–552

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R (1970) The units of selection. Ann Rev Ecolog Syst 1:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1991) One long argument: Charles Darwin and the Genesis of modern evolutionary theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (2001) What evolution is. Basic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of economic change. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1995) The nature of selection. J Theor Biol 175:389–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer W (2000) Response synchronization: a universal coding strategy for the definition of relations. In: Gazzaniga MS (ed) The new cognitive neurosciences. MIT, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp 325–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1993) An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (1999a) The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (1999b) The human adaptation for culture. Annu Rev Anthropol 28:509–529

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg VJ (2004) Human intentionality and design in cultural evolution. Papers on Economics and Evolution #0402:1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Vromen J (2004) Conjectural revisionary economic ontology: outline of an ambitious research agenda for evolutionary economics. J Econ Methodol 11(2):213–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (1999) Bioeconomics as economics from a Darwinian perspective. J Bioecon 1:19–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2000) Changing cognitive frames—changing organizational forms: an entrepreneurial theory of organizational development. Industrial and Corporate Change 9(4):733–755

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2003) The evolving economy—essays on the evolutionary approach to economics. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2004) On the proper interpretation of ‘evolution’ in economics and its implications for production theory. J Econ Methodol 11(2):125–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2005) On novelty and heterogeneity. In: Lux T, Reitz S, Samanidou E (eds) Nonlinear dynamics and heterogeneous interacting agents. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York pp 123–138

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ziman J (2000) Evolutionary models for technological change. In: Ziman J (ed) Technological innovation as an evolutionary process. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, pp 3–12

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is very grateful to Geoffrey Hodgson and Thorbjørn Knudsen for critical comments on an earlier version of this paper. The ideas presented here have developed in discussions with colleagues at the Centre for Research on Innovation and Competition in Manchester and the Max Planck Institute of Economics in Jena.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Cordes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cordes, C. Darwinism in economics: from analogy to continuity. J Evol Econ 16, 529–541 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-006-0027-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-006-0027-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation