Skip to main content
Log in

Ambiguity sensitive preferences in Ellsberg frameworks

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study the market implications of ambiguity sensitive preferences using the \(\alpha \)-maxmin expected utility (\(\alpha \)-MEU) model. In the standard Ellsberg framework, we prove that \(\alpha \)-MEU preferences are equivalent to either maxmin, maxmax or subjective expected utility (SEU). We show how ambiguity aversion impacts equilibrium asset prices, and revisit the laboratory experimental findings in Bossaerts et al. (Rev Financ Stud 23:1325–1359, 2010). Only when there are three or more ambiguous states, \(\alpha \)-MEU, maxmin, maxmax and SEU models induce different portfolio choices. We suggest criteria to discriminate among these models in laboratory experiments and show that ambiguity seeking agents may prevent the existence of market equilibrium. Our results indicate that ambiguity matters for portfolio choice and does not wash out in equilibrium.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Gilboa and Marinacci (2013) and Machina and Siniscalchi (2014) for recent discussions of ambiguity and ambiguity aversion.

  2. Several studies investigate how agents’ non-participation may arise in the presence of ambiguity averse agents; see Dow and Werlang (1992), Epstein and Miao (2003), Cao et al. (2005), Easley and O’Hara (2009), Illeditsch (2011) and Dimmock et al. (2016). Studies relating ambiguity aversion to other market phenomena include Chen and Epstein (2002), Uppal and Wang (2003), Trojani and Vanini (2004), Epstein and Schneider (2008), Cao et al. (2011), and Boyle et al. (2012). For a survey on this topic see Epstein and Schneider (2010). Ambiguity averse preferences have been used to address long-standing puzzles in Economics regarding the conflict between efficiency and incentive compatibility, see for e.g. He and Yannelis (2015) and De Castro and Yannelis (2016), and the existence of Rational Expectations Equilibrium, see for e.g. De Castro et al. (2017).

  3. The \(\alpha \)-maxmin expected utility is a generalization of the Hurwicz’s model introduced by Hurwicz (1951a, b); see also Arrow and Hurwicz (1972) and Jaffray (1988).

  4. Theoretical properties of the \(\alpha \)-MEU model have been studied by Ghirardato et al. (1998) and Marinacci (2002). For characterizations of subclasses of the \(\alpha \)-MEU preferences see Ghirardato et al. (2004), Olszewski (2007), Eichberger et al. (2011), and Klibanoff et al. (2014). Chen et al. (2007) focus on sealed bid auctions and use the \(\alpha \)-MEU to derive the equilibrium bidding strategy for \(\alpha \)-MEU bidders. For recent experimental studies see, Ahn et al. (2014), Cubitt et al. (2014) and reference therein.

  5. Bossaerts et al. (2010), and Ahn et al. (2014) derive the \(\alpha \)-MEU model portfolio choice in the standard Ellsberg framework. However, as we show in Proposition 1, in that framework \(\alpha \)-MEU preferences coincide with either maxmin, maxmax or SEU preferences.

  6. This result holds true for any number of risky states as long as that there are only two ambiguous states.

  7. Bossaerts et al. (2010) and Ahn et al. (2014) run portfolio choice laboratory experiments in the standard Ellsberg framework and provide evidence of considerable heterogeneity in agents’ preferences. They find that one half of the agents are well approximated by SEU preferences, while the remaining half has a significant degree of ambiguity aversion and prefers portfolios with no exposure to ambiguity.

  8. To rationalize their experimental findings Bossaerts et al. (2010) use a theoretical market model populated by \(\alpha \)-MEU agents with \(\alpha >1/2\) and SEU agents. Unaware that in the standard Ellsberg framework \(\alpha \)-MEU utilities with \(\alpha >1/2\) reduce to concave maxmin utilities, Bossaerts et al. (2010) do not derive the equilibrium state prices but make conjectures. Our theoretical findings in Sect. 3.1 complete the Bossaerts et al. (2010) model and show that their experimental findings are much closer to the theory than they could conclude based on their analysis.

  9. To further strengthen this result we remark that while the maxmin portfolio choice explains the fraction of portfolios with no exposure to ambiguity observed in the Bossaerts et al. (2010) experiments, the portfolio choice of a SEU agent cannot, even if the SEU agent is endowed with a non-smooth utility. The intuitive reason is that a kink of a non-smooth SEU utility does not discriminate between risky and ambiguous states, while a kink of the maxmin utility, consequence of the multiple priors evaluation of the maxmin agent, it does.

  10. Studies of agent’s ambiguity aversion based on the \(\alpha \)-MEU model typically assume, as we do here, that the set of priors describing the uncertainty of the setting is known; see, e.g., Chen et al. (2007), and Ahn et al. (2014). This assumption has been debated in the literature, but it appears to be necessary to achieve specific behavioral predictions which are amenable to testing in an experimental setting.

  11. In contrast to the standard Ellsberg framework, in the extended Ellsberg frameworks (i.e., when \(l\ge 3\)) the value of \(\alpha \) that separates ambiguity seeking from ambiguity averse agents is not anymore \(\alpha =1/2\) but \(\alpha =(l-1)/l\): when \(l=3\), \(\alpha =(l-1)/l=2/3\) and increases toward 1 when l increases. Moreover, \((l-1)/l\)-\(\mathcal C_{\max }\)-MEU preferences do not reduce to SEU preferences; see Sect. 4.3.

  12. These properties can be insured, for instance, by requiring that the feasible portfolios are in the interior of the utility domain.

  13. The set of priors \(\mathcal C\) equals \(\mathcal D\) when \(\alpha =1\) (\(\alpha =0\)), and when \(\alpha \) decreases (increases) to 1 / 2 shrinks up to only containing the prior (5).

  14. Section 4 shows that when there are more than two ambiguous states, the equivalence result does not hold anymore: the \(\alpha \)-MEU model induces different portfolio choice and expresses different attitude toward ambiguity than the maxmin, maxmax and SEU models.

  15. Rankings (7) and (10) of the state-price/state-probability ratio of SEU agents in the market are not opposite to the ranking of the corresponding total endowments. By contrast, the state-price/state-probability of the SEU representative agent who rationalizes the market equilibrium is ranked opposite to total endowment: the representative agent has to hold the total endowment of the economy as optimal portfolio, thus (27) has to hold.

  16. This occurs if and only if \(\frac{p_B}{\pi _B}>\frac{p_G}{\pi _G}\) (see (27) in “Appendix A”) and excludes all state-price/state-probability rankings in which \(\frac{p_B}{\pi _B} \le \frac{p_G}{\pi _G}\).

  17. Suppose there exists a maxmin representative agent characterized by the set of priors \(\{(\pi _R,q,1-\pi _R-q)\mid q\in [c_R,d_R])\}\) who rationalizes the market equilibrium. Let \(\{(\pi _R,q,1-\pi _R-q)\mid q\in [c,d])\}\) be the set of priors of the maxmin agents in the market. Since the maxmin agents in the market choose the unambiguous portfolio and the representative agent has to hold the total endowment W of the economy as optimal portfolio, (29) implies that: If \(W_G> W_B\), then

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{c}{1-\pi _R-c}\le \frac{p_G}{p_B}< \frac{c_R}{1-\pi _R-c_R}, \end{aligned}$$

    has to hold true and thus \(c_R>c\). With a similar reasoning, if \(W_G< W_B\), then \(d_R<d\) has to hold true.

  18. From (29) and the results that follow in this section (specifically equalities (13)) one can see that maxmin agents hold an unambiguous portfolio, i.e., \(w_G=w_B\) if and only if q in (12) satisfies \(c\le q<\pi _G< d\).

  19. Depending on the particular rank of the total endowment \(W=(W_R, W_B, W_G)\), the price of the Arrow security that pays in the state R will increase or decrease with \({\frac{\beta }{L} (W_G-W_B)}\).

  20. The fact that q does not depend neither on the number of M of maxmin agents nor on their risk aversion \(\gamma \) is a peculiarity of the exponential utility.

  21. These values of the aggregate endowment W are the same values used by Bossaerts et al. (2010) in one of their experiments that we discuss in Sect. 3.4 and which empirical rankings are summarized in Fig. 2 in our paper.

  22. Note that the market model for which we derive the theoretical rankings is the same theoretical market model proposed by Bossaerts et al. (2010) to explain the experimental market. Relative to Bossaerts et al. (2010), from the equivalence result (Proposition 1) in addition we know that in the standard Ellsberg framework risk averse \(\alpha \)-MEU preferences with \(\alpha >1/2\) are equivalent maxmin preferences with concave utility.

  23. The analysis in the Bossaerts et al. (2010) not always could explain the experimental findings, as discussed by the authors; see the Conclusion in Bossaerts et al. (2010).

  24. Bossaerts et al. (2010, p. 1351) report that “the rankings appear anomalous,” because they only expect to see the second ranking (Bossaerts et al. 2010, p. 1339).

  25. The interpretation of \(\alpha \) as a measure of ambiguity can be lost if the set of priors \(\mathcal C\) is smaller than the set of priors \(\mathcal C_{\max }\) that describes the uncertainty of the setting. A \(\mathcal C\) strictly smaller than \(\mathcal C_{\max }\) can reflect both additional information and less aversion toward ambiguity. However, in general the intuitive interpretation of \(\alpha \) as an ambiguity aversion parameter is not warranted. One of the reasons is the potential multiplicity of representations of preferences as either \(\alpha \)-MEU or maxmin/maxmax; see Sect. 3. The underlying subtle question is linked to the precise notion of the ambiguity in a problem, which has been debated in the decision theory literature; see, e.g., Siniscalchi (2006), Ghirardato et al. (2004) and Machina and Siniscalchi (2014).

  26. It is easy to see that also when the set of priors \(\mathcal C\) is a strict subset of \(\mathcal C_{\max }\), the \(\alpha \)-MEU utility cannot in general be rewritten neither as 1-MEU, 0-MEU nor SEU, and is not concave.

  27. Another way to see this is to observe that the \(\alpha \)-\({\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\)-MEU utility from a portfolio \(w\in \mathbb {R}^{m+l}\) on the ambiguous states only depends on \(w_{\min }^A\) and \(w_{\max }^A\). This is not the case for a maxmin (maxmax) utility model, as long as the state space contains more than two ambiguous states. The utility of the maxmin model from a portfolio \(w\in \mathbb {R}^{m+l}\) will be a function of the portfolio’s smallest wealth \(w_{\min }^A\) (respectively, the portfolio’s largest wealth \(w_{\max }^A\)) and then, depending on the set of priors, of the second smallest wealth (respectively, the second largest wealth) and so on, until the sum of the probabilities of the states in which these wealths are allocated reaches \((1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R )\).

  28. These properties are used in the proofs of Lemmas 26 that in turns prove Proposition 4, and can be ensured for instance by requiring that the feasible portfolios are in the interior of the utility domain.

  29. The non-existence of the optimal portfolio of 0-MEU agent is due to the fact that when the utility is defined on the whole real line, the agent can go arbitrarily long in one of the ambiguous states and still satisfy the budget constraint by going arbitrarily short in another ambiguous state. A utility with bounded domain would imply the existence of an optimal portfolio for the 0-MEU agent as the bounded domain will prevent the agent from going arbitrarily short; see Lemma 6.

  30. The dependence of the portfolio choice on the number of ambiguous states l is discussed in Sect. 4.2.3.

  31. In the limit, when \(\alpha \rightarrow 0\), \( {\overline{w}}- {\underline{w}} \rightarrow \infty \), and thus there is no optimum; see discussion after Proposition 4.

  32. When \(\alpha \uparrow 1-\frac{p_{\min }^A}{\sum _{\nu \in A}p_{\nu }}\), \(1-\alpha \downarrow \frac{p_{\min }^A}{\sum _{\nu \in A}p_{\nu }}\) and thus \(\frac{u'({\underline{w}})}{u'({\overline{w}})}\downarrow 1\).

  33. A comparatively high price in one of the ambiguous state may make the agents believe that this state has a higher probability of occurrence than the other ambiguous states, even though in the Ellsberg framework an exact knowledge of the probabilities is not available and the ambiguous states are “equally ambiguous”.

  34. In Standard Ellsberg framework, when \(l=2\), any \(\alpha \)-MEU utility with \(\alpha =\frac{l-1}{l}=\frac{1}{2}\) reduces to a SEU utility; see Proposition 1.

  35. In fact, when \(1<\mid I\mid <l-1\), the optimal portfolio of any \(\alpha \)-\(\mathcal C_{\max }\)-MEU agent with \(\alpha \in [0,1]\) is different from the SEU optimal portfolio.

  36. In Sect. 4.2 we observe that the equivalence result does not hold when the number of ambiguity states is larger than two. However, the fact that \(\alpha \)-MEU utilities cannot be rewritten as 1-MEU utilities does not imply that their portfolio choice may not be observationally equivalent.

  37. If a set of priors \(\mathcal C\) is symmetric (i.e., permutation invariant) in the ambiguous coordinates then \(\tilde{\pi }\in \mathcal C\). Thus, if \(\tilde{\pi }\notin \mathcal C\) some ambiguous states will be systematically overweighted and other underweighted. Note that \({\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\) includes \(\tilde{\pi }\) and is symmetric in the ambiguous states.

  38. The optimal portfolio of a maxmin agent is typically unique. In particular this is always the case when the maxmin utility is strictly concave.

  39. When \(p_B=p_G\) approach zero the right-hand side of the interval \([\frac{2}{3}, 1- \frac{p_G}{1-p_R} ]\) approaches 1.

  40. A necessary condition for the existence of the equilibrium is that beliefs are consistent across agents in the market. We recall that \(\tilde{\pi }\) is in the set of prior \(\mathcal C_{\max }\) of the \(\alpha \)-\(\mathcal C_{\max }\)-MEU.

  41. When the ambiguous states have equal prices, the unambiguous portfolio is optimal both for the \(\alpha \)-\(\mathcal C_{\max }\)-MEU (see Corollary 3) and the maxmin agent (see Lemma 1).

  42. The \(\alpha \)-\(\mathcal C_{\max }\)-MEU utility assigns probability \((1-\alpha )(1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R)\) to the state \(\sigma \) on which the highest wealth \({\overline{w}}\) is allocated, and probability \(\frac{\alpha (1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R)}{(l-1)}\) to each of the remaining states \(\eta \in A{\setminus } \{\sigma \}\). The SEU-prior \(\tilde{\pi }\) does not appear in the inequalities characterizing the ambiguous state prices because \(\tilde{\pi }\) assigns equal probability \(\tilde{\pi }_a\) to each ambiguous state and thus cancels out. The total endowment W also cancels out because \(W_\eta =W_\nu \), for all \(\eta , \nu \in A\).

  43. This can be shown by observing that \(w_\sigma >w_\eta \), \(\forall \eta \in A{\setminus }\{\sigma \}\) implies \(u(w_\eta )-u(w_\sigma )<0\), \(\forall \eta \in A{\setminus }\{\sigma \}\). Then the optimal prior \(\pi ^*\) has to be a prior which maximizes the sum of the probability of the state \(\eta \in A{\setminus }\{\sigma \}\). Therefore, since \(\tilde{\pi }\in \mathcal C\), then \(\pi ^*\) is such that \(\sum _{\eta \in A{\setminus }\{\sigma \}} \pi _\eta ^*\ge \frac{1-\sum _{S{\setminus } A} \pi _R}{l}(l-1)\) or equivalently \(\pi _\sigma ^*\le \frac{1-\sum _{S{\setminus } A} \pi _R}{l}\).

References

  • Ahn, D., Choi, S., Gale, D., Kariv, S.: Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment. Quant. Econ. 5(2), 195–223 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K., Hurwicz, L.: An optimality criterion for decision making under ignorance. In: Carter, C.F., Ford, J.L. (eds.) Uncertainty and Expectations in Economics. Basil Blackwell, Oxford (1972)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossaerts, P., Ghirardato, P., Guarnaschelli, S., Zame, W.: Ambiguity in asset markets: theory and experiments. Rev. Financ. Stud. 23, 1325–1359 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, P., Garlappi, L., Uppal, R., Wang, T.: Keynes meets Markowitz: the trade-off between familiarity and diversification. Manag. Sci. 58, 253–272 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cao, H.H., Wang, T., Zhang, H.: Model uncertainty, limited market participation, and asset prices. Rev. Financ. Stud. 18, 1219–1251 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cao, H.H., Han, B., Hirshleifer, D., Zhang, H.H.: Fear of the unknown: familiarity and economic decisions. Rev. Finance 15, 173–206 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Y., Katuščák, P., Ozdenoren, E.: Sealed bid auctions with ambiguity: theory and experiments. J. Econ. Theory 136, 513–535 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Z., Epstein, L.: Ambiguity, risk, and asset returns in continuous time. Econometrica 70, 1403–1443 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt, R., van de Kuilen, G., Mukerji, S.: Discriminating Between Models of Ambiguity Attitude: A Qualitative Test. Mimeo, University of Oxford, Oxford (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • De Castro, L., Yannelis, N.C.: Uncertainty, efficiency and incentive compatibility, Working Paper (2016)

  • De Castro, L., Pesce, M., Yannelis, N.C.: Rational expectations equilibrium under ambiguity. Working Paper (2017)

  • Dimmock, S.G., Kouwenberg, R., Wakker, P.P.: Ambiguity attitudes in a large representative sample. Manag. Sci. 62, 1363–1380 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dow, J., Werlang, S.R.D.C.: Uncertainty aversion, risk aversion, and the optimal choice of portfolio. Econometrica 60, 197–204 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easley, D., O’Hara, M.: Ambiguity and nonparticipation: the role of regulation. Rev. Financ. Stud. 22(5), 1817–1843 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., Grant, S., Kelsey, D., Koshevoy, G.A.: The \(\alpha \)-MEU model: a comment. J. Econ. Theory 146, 1684–1698 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D.: Risk, ambiguity, and the savage axioms. Q. J. Econ. 75, 643–669 (1961)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L., Schneider, M.: Ambiguity, information quality, and asset pricing. J. Finance 63, 197–228 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L., Schneider, M.: Ambiguity and asset markets. Annu. Rev. Financ. Econ. 2, 315–346 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L.G., Miao, J.: A two-person dynamic equilibrium under ambiguity. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 27, 1253–1288 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M.: Additivity with multiple priors. J. Math. Econ. 30, 405–420 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M.: Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude. J. Econ. Theory 118, 133–173 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Marinacci, M.: Ambiguity and the Bayesian paradigm. In: Acemoglu, D., Arellano, M., Dekel, E. (eds.) Advances in Economics and Econometrics: Theory and Applications, Tenth World Congress of the Econometric Society. Cambridge University Press, New York (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Schmeidler, D.: Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior. J. Math. Econ. 18, 141–153 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, W., Yannelis, N.C.: Equilibrium theory under ambiguity. J. Math. Econ. 61, 86–95 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz, L.: Optimality criteria for decision making under ignorance. Discussion Paper 370, Cowles Commission (1951a)

  • Hurwicz, L.: Some specification problems and application to econometric models. Econometrica 19, 343–344 (1951b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Illeditsch, P.: Ambiguous information, portfolio inertia, and excess volatility. J. Finance 66, 2213–2247 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaffray, J.Y.: Application of linear utility theory to belief functions. In: Bouchon, B., Saitta, L., Yager, R.R. (eds.) Uncertainty and Intelligent Systems. IPMU 1988. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 313, pp. 1–8. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg (1988)

  • Klibanoff, P., Mukerji, S., Seo, K.: Perceived ambiguity and relevant measures. Econometrica 82, 1945–1978 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.: Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Houghton, Mifflin, Boston (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M.J., Siniscalchi, M.: Ambiguity and ambiguity aversion. In: Machina, M.J., Viscusi, W.K. (eds.) Handbook of the Economics of Uncertainty. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Marinacci, M.: Probabilistic sophistication and multiple priors. Econometrica 70, 755–764 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olszewski, W.: Preferences over sets of lotteries. Rev. Econ. Stud. 74, 567–595 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rockafellar, R.T.: Convex analysis. Princeton mathematical series, Princeton University Press (1970)

  • Siniscalchi, M.: A behavioral characterization of plausible priors. J. Econ. Theory 128, 91–135 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trojani, F., Vanini, P.: Robustness and ambiguity aversion in general equilibrium. Rev. Finance 8, 279–324 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uppal, R., Wang, T.: Model misspecification and underdiversification. J. Finance 58, 2465–2486 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are particularly indebted to Larry Epstein and Bill Zame for insightful discussions. For helpful comments we thank Peter Bossaerts, Pierre Collin-Dufresne, Darrell Duffie, Damir Filipovic, Lorenzo Garlappi, Paolo Ghirardato, Julien Hugonnier, Pablo Koch-Medina, Leonid Kogan, Loriano Mancini and Jean-Charles Rochet, as well as the participants of the 2016 Risk and Stochastics Conference at London School of Economics.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudia Ravanelli.

Appendices

Proof of Proposition 2

In the following, we briefly summarize how the interaction among SEU and maxmin agents impacts the equilibrium asset prices. This will provide us the tools to prove Proposition 2.

Assume that \((p;w^1, \ldots , w^n)\) is an equilibrium with \(p_\sigma >0\) for all \(\sigma \in \{R,G,B\}\). Then, the equilibrium price p satisfies

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda _n p \in \partial U^n(w^n) \end{aligned}$$
(25)

for some \(\lambda _n>0\); see (44). Here \(\partial U^n(w)\) denotes the supergradient of the criterion \(U^n\) of agent n at \(w\in {\mathbb {R}}^3\).

The supergradient of a SEU agent with prior \(\pi =(\pi _R, \pi _G, \pi _B)\) is simply the gradient

$$\begin{aligned} \partial U^n( w)= \left\{ \left( \pi _R u'(w_R),\pi _G u'(w_G) ,\pi _B u'(w_B) \right) \right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(26)

From (26) and the strict concavity of the utility function, it follows the well-known fact that the optimal portfolio \(w=(w_R,w_G,w_B)\) of a SEU agent is always such that the optimal choices of state-dependent wealth are ranked opposite to the state-price/state-probability ratios, i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} w_{\sigma }>w_{\nu } \Leftrightarrow \frac{p_{\sigma }}{\pi _{\sigma }}<\frac{p_{\nu } }{\pi _{\nu }}, \quad \sigma ,\nu \in \{R,B,G\}. \end{aligned}$$
(27)

The supergradient of an agent with maxmin (1-MEU) preferences represented as in (4) is

$$\begin{aligned} \partial U^m(w) = \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \{(\pi _R u'(w_R), c u'(w_G), (1-\pi _R-c )u'(w_B) )\} &{} \text{ if } w_G> w_B \\ \{(\pi _R u'(w_R), d u'(w_G), (1-\pi _R-d )u'(w_B) )\} &{} \text{ if } w_G< w_B\\ \{(\pi _R u'(w_R), (\lambda c + (1-\lambda )d) u'(w_G), &{}\\ (1-\pi _R -(\lambda c + (1-\lambda )d))u'(w_B))\mid \lambda \in [0,1]\} &{} \text{ if } w_G= w_B. \end{array} \right. \nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(28)

Using (25) and the shape of the supergradients we easily obtain the optimal portfolio choices that were already derived in Bossaerts et al. (2010).

In particular, from (28) and the strict concavity of u it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ \begin{array}{lll} w_G>w_B &{} \hbox {if and only if} &{} \frac{p_G}{p_B}<\frac{c}{1-\pi _R-c}\\ w_G<w_B &{} \hbox {if and only if} &{} \frac{p_G}{p_B}>\frac{d}{1-\pi _R-d}\\ w_G=w_B &{} \hbox {if and only if} &{} \frac{p_G}{p_B}\in \left[ \frac{c}{1-\pi _R-c}, \frac{d}{1-\pi _R-d}\right] \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(29)

where \(x/0:=\infty \). The larger the set of priors \(\mathcal C\) in (5), the more likely a maxmin agent will take an unambiguous portfolio (\(w_B=w_G\)). In particular this will be always the case if \({\mathcal {C}}={\mathcal {C}}_{\max }:= \{(\pi _R, q, 1-q-\pi _R): q\in [0,1-\pi _R]\}\), because then the second, respectively, third coordinate of the supergradient in (28) will be 0 if either \(w_G> w_B\) or \(w_G< w_B\). Hence, \(p_\sigma >0\) for all \(\sigma \in \{R,G,B\}\) and (25) imply that in equilibrium this agent will only take an unambiguous portfolios w. If \(c>0\) and/or \(d<1-\pi _R\) in (5), then the multiple prior agent may also take an ambiguous portfolio in equilibrium. We observe that a maxmin agent holding an unambiguous optimal portfolio behaves as a SEU agent who is not differentiating between the ambiguous states G and B, but merges them to an unambiguous state \(\{G,B\}\) with probability \((1-\pi _R)\). Indeed, from (28) and (25) it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_{\{G,B\}}}{p_R}= \frac{(1-\pi _R)u'(w_{\{G,B\}})}{\pi _R u'(w_R)}\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}<\frac{(1-\pi _R)}{\pi _R} &{} \text{ iff } w_{\{G,B\}}>w_R\\ >\frac{(1-\pi _R)}{\pi _R} &{} \text{ iff } w_{\{G,B\}}<w_R \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(30)

and thus

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_{\{G,B\}}}{(1-\pi _R)}< \frac{p_R}{\pi _R}\Leftrightarrow & {} w_{\{G,B\}}>w_R \end{aligned}$$
(31)
$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_{\{G,B\}}}{(1-\pi _R)}> \frac{p_R}{\pi _R}\Leftrightarrow & {} w_{\{G,B\}}<w_R \quad (\hbox {compare this to } (27)), \end{aligned}$$
(32)

where \(p_{\{G,B\}}:= p_G+p_B\) and \(w_{\{G,B\}}:=w_G=w_B\).

Proof of Proposition 2

Case 1 Let \(W_R>W_G>W_B\). Since the 1-MEU agents take an unambiguous portfolio, the optimal portfolio of some SEU agent must satisfy \(y_G>y_B\) which according to (27) is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_B}{\pi _B}>\frac{p_G}{\pi _G}\end{aligned}$$
(33)

which only leaves the ranking of \(p_R/\pi _R\) within (33) an open question. Suppose that the ranking of the ratios state-price/state-probability is as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_R}{\pi _R}\ge \frac{p_B}{\pi _B}>\frac{p_G}{\pi _G}. \end{aligned}$$
(34)

Then (27) implies that \(y_G>y_B\ge y_R\) for any SEU agent, and rearranging (34) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_G+p_B}{1-\pi _R}=\frac{p_G+p_B}{\pi _G+\pi _B} <\frac{p_R}{\pi _R}. \end{aligned}$$

Consequently, according to (30), we must have for each 1-MEU agent that \(w_R<w_G=w_B\). But this contradicts the clearing of the market and \(W_R>W_G>W_B\). If the ranking is (7), then we have \(y_G>y_R>y_B\) for each SEU agent according to (27). Denote by \(y^\Sigma =(y^\Sigma _R,y^\Sigma _G,y^\Sigma _B)\) the sum over all optimal portfolios of the SEU agents and similarly by \(w^\Sigma =(w^\Sigma _R,w^\Sigma _G,w^\Sigma _B)\) the sum over all optimal portfolios of the 1-MEU agents. The market clearing condition says \(W_\sigma = y^\Sigma _\sigma +w^\Sigma _\sigma \) for every \(\sigma \in \{R,G,B\}\). Since \(y^\Sigma _G>y^\Sigma _R\) we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} w^\Sigma _R=W_R-y^\Sigma _R>W_G-y_G^\Sigma =w_G^\Sigma . \end{aligned}$$

Thus there must be at least one 1-MEU agent who’s portfolio \(w=(w_R,w_G,w_B)\) satisfies \(w_R>w_G=w_B\) which implies that \((p_G+p_B)/p_R>(1-\pi _R)/\pi _R\) due to (30). But then, again by (30), we must have \(w_R>w_G=w_B\) for all 1-MEU agents. In case of (8) (27) and (30) imply the claimed ranking of payoffs in the portfolios y and w.

Case 2 Let \(W_G>W_R>W_B\). As in case one we conclude that \(y_G>y_B\). Assume that the ranking of the ratio state-price/state-probability is as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_R}{\pi _R}\ge \frac{p_B}{\pi _B}>\frac{p_G}{\pi _G}. \end{aligned}$$
(35)

Then as in case 1 it follows that \(y_G>y_B\ge y_R\) and \(w_R<w_G=w_B\) which together with the clearing of the market contradicts \(W_R>W_B\). Similarly it follows that the ranking

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_B}{\pi _B}>\frac{p_G}{\pi _G}\ge \frac{p_R}{\pi _R} \end{aligned}$$

is not possible, since it would imply that \( y_R\ge y_G>y_B\) and \(w_R>w_G=w_B\) due to (30), again contradicting the assumed ranking of the aggregate wealth.

Case 3 Let \(W_G> W_B>W_R\): Suppose that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_B}{\pi _B}>\frac{p_G}{\pi _G}\ge \frac{p_R}{\pi _R} \end{aligned}$$

then, \(y_R\ge y_G>y_B\), and in view of (30) we obtain \(w_R>w_G=w_B\) for every 1-MEU agent which again contradicts the market clearing and the assumed ranking \(W_G> W_B>W_R\). Again (27), (30), and the clearing of the market imply the claimed ranking of payoffs in the portfolios y, w for the remaining possible rankings.\(\square \)

Proof of Propositions 1 and 3

Proposition 1 is a special case of Proposition 3 since every set of priors in the standard Ellsberg framework is of the type \({\mathcal {C}}\) in (15), required in Proposition 3.

To prove Proposition 3 we observe that the maxmin utility with set of priors \({\mathcal {C}}\) can be written as

$$\begin{aligned}&u(w_\eta )+\sum _{\sigma \in S{\setminus } A}(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))\pi _\sigma \nonumber \\&\quad +\sum _{\sigma \in A{\setminus }\{\eta \}}(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))^+a_\sigma -(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))^-b_\sigma , \end{aligned}$$
(36)

and the maxmax utility as

$$\begin{aligned} u(w_\eta )+\sum _{\sigma \in S{\setminus } A}(u(w_\sigma )-u(\eta ))\pi _\sigma +\sum _{\sigma \in A{\setminus }\{\eta \}}(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))^+b_\sigma -(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))^-a_\sigma . \end{aligned}$$
(37)

Consequently, the \(\alpha \)-MEU utility is

$$\begin{aligned} U(w)= & {} u(w_\eta )+ \sum _{\sigma \in S{\setminus } A}(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))\pi _\sigma + \sum _{\sigma \in A{\setminus }\{\eta \}}(u(w_\sigma )\\&-\,u(w_\eta ))^+c_\sigma -(u(w_\sigma )-u(w_\eta ))^-d_\sigma . \end{aligned}$$

where \(c_\sigma :=\alpha a_\sigma + (1-\alpha )b_\sigma \), and \(d_\sigma :=\alpha b_\sigma + (1-\alpha )a_\sigma \), \(\sigma \in A{\setminus }\{\eta \}\). If \(\alpha >1/2\), then \(c_\sigma <d_\sigma \); if \(\alpha <1/2\), then \(d_\sigma <c_\sigma \); and finally \(c_\sigma =d_\sigma \) for \(\alpha =1/2\). These facts, and comparing U for the different cases (i), (ii) and (iii) with (36) and (37) prove Proposition 3.

Lack of concavity of the \(\alpha \)-MEU utility

To see the lack of concavity of the \(\alpha \)-\({\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\)-MEU utility when \(\alpha \ne 1\), consider portfolio \(w^1\) such that \(w^1_1=1, w^1_2=4 \hbox { and } w^1_j=2, \forall j= 2, \ldots , l\), and portfolio \(w^2\) such that \(w^2_1=1, w^2_2=2, w^2_3=6 \hbox { and } w^2_j=2, \forall j=4, \ldots , l\). Let \(w^{\lambda }=(w^{\lambda }_1, \ldots , w^{\lambda }_l)\) be their convex combination, i.e., \(w^{\lambda }_j=\lambda w^1_j +(1-\lambda ) w^2_j\), \(j=1, \ldots , l\), \(\lambda \in [0,1]\). Take for instance \(\lambda ={1/2}\). Then \(w^{\lambda }_1=1, w^{\lambda }_2=3, w^{\lambda }_3=4 \hbox { and } w^{\lambda }_j= 2, \forall j=4, \ldots , l\), and using (16)

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda U(w^1)+(1-\lambda )U(w^2)= & {} \alpha u(1) +(1-\alpha )\frac{1}{2} (u(4)+u(6))\\> & {} \alpha u(1)+(1-\alpha )u(4) =\alpha u(w^{\lambda \, A}_{\min })+(1-\alpha )u\left( w_{\max }^{\lambda \, A}\right) \\= & {} U(w^{\lambda })=U((\lambda w^1+ (1- \lambda )w^2)). \end{aligned}$$

Proof of Proposition 4

Proposition 4 follows from Lemmas 26 in the following.

Lemma 2

Suppose that the state-price vector \(p=(p_\sigma )_{\sigma \in S}\) satisfies \(p_\sigma >0\) for all \(\sigma \in S\). Consider an \(\alpha \)-\({\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\)-MEU agent with \(\alpha \in (0,1)\). Let \(w=(w_\sigma )_{\sigma \in S}\in {\mathbb {R}}^n\) be an optimal portfolio for the \(\alpha \)-\({\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\)-MEU agent. Then, either w takes the same value on all ambiguous states, or there exist two disjoint subsets \({\overline{A}}\) and \({\underline{A}}\) of the set of ambiguous states A such that \({\overline{A}} \cup {\underline{A}} = A\) and two values \(\overline{w},\underline{w}\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(w_\sigma = \overline{w}> \underline{w}=w_\eta \) for all \(\sigma \in {\overline{A}}\) and all \(\eta \in {\underline{A}}\).

Proof

Note that the only portfolio values on the ambiguous states on which the utility U in (16) depends are \(w^A_{\max }\) and \(w^A_{\min }\). We order the set of ambiguous states \(A=\{\sigma _1,\ldots ,\sigma _l\}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} w_{\sigma _1}\le w_{\sigma _2}\le \cdots \le w_{\sigma _l}. \end{aligned}$$
(38)

Let s be the number of strict inequalities in (38). Consider states \(\nu _1,\ldots \nu _{s+1}\in A\) such that \(w_{\nu _1}<w_{\nu _2}<\ldots <w_{\nu _{s+1}}\). Suppose there is a state \(\eta \in A\) such that \(w_\eta \ne w^A_{\max }\) and \(w_\eta \ne w^A_{\min }\), namely suppose that \(s\ge 2\). We now consider the function U in (16) as defined on \({\mathbb {R}}^{m+s+1}\), where we merge those ambiguous states in which w takes the same value. Let \(\tilde{w}\in {\mathbb {R}}^{m+s+1}\) such that \(\tilde{w}_R=w_R\) for all risky states \(R\in S{\setminus } A\) and otherwise \(\tilde{w}_{\sigma _i}=w_{\sigma _i}\) for \(i=1,\ldots ,s+1\). Then, \(\tilde{w}\) is a maximizer for the function U restricted to the open set \(C:=\{x\in {\mathbb {R}}^{ m+s+1}\mid x_{\sigma _1}<x_{\sigma _2}<\ldots <x_{\sigma _{s+1}}\}\), which we call \(U_C\), given the budget constraint \(\tilde{p} \cdot \tilde{w}\le p\cdot e\). Here e is the initial portfolio and \(\tilde{p}\in {\mathbb {R}}^{m+s+1}\) is obtained from p by summing up the prices of those states which are merged when forming \(\tilde{w}\). As \(U_C\) is concave, according to (44), a multiple of \(\tilde{p}\) is in the supergradient of \(U_C\) at \(\tilde{w}\). However, this supergradient is equal to zero in any \(x_{\sigma _i}\)-direction, \(i\in \{2,\ldots , s\}\), because only the largest value and the smallest value on the ambiguous states matter for U. This contradicts the assumption \(p_{\sigma _i}>0\) for \(i\in \{2,\ldots , s\}\). \(\square \)

Lemma 3

Assume Lemma 2. If \(p_\sigma <p_\eta \) for \(\sigma ,\eta \in A\), then the optimal portfolio w satisfies \(w_\eta \le w_\sigma \).

Proof

Suppose that the optimal portfolio w is such that \(w_\eta > w_\sigma \). Let \(\tilde{w}\) given by \(\tilde{w}_\nu =w_\nu \) for all \(\nu \in S{\setminus } \{\sigma ,\eta \}\) and \(\tilde{w}_{\sigma }=w_\eta \) and \(\tilde{w}_{\eta }=w_{\sigma }\). Then \(U(\tilde{w})=U(w)\), but \(p\cdot \tilde{w} < p \cdot w\) because \(p\cdot (w-\tilde{w})= (p_\eta -p_\sigma ) (w_\eta -w_\sigma )>0\). This contradicts the optimality of w, because increasing the wealth \(\tilde{w}_{\sigma }\) one could achieve a strictly higher utility while still respecting the budget constraint. \(\square \)

Lemma 4

Assume Lemma 2. If the sets \({\overline{A}}\) and \({\underline{A}}\) associated to the optimal portfolio w are not empty, then \({\overline{A}}=\{{\overline{\sigma }}\}\) for a state \({\overline{\sigma }}\in I:=\{\sigma \in A\mid p_\sigma =\min _{\eta \in A} p_\eta \}\). Moreover, any portfolio which equals w on the risky states and assigns the weight \(w^A_{\max }\) to a single state in I and \(w^A_{\min }\) to all the other ambiguous states is optimal. Hence, there are |I| optimal portfolios.

Proof

By contradiction suppose that there are two different states \(\sigma _1\) and \(\sigma _2\) in \({\overline{A}}\), i.e., that the optimal portfolio w is such that \(w_{\sigma _1}=w_{\sigma _2}=w^A_{\max }\), and without loss of generality we assume that \(p_{\sigma _1}\le p_{\sigma _2}\). Consider \(\tilde{w}\) given by \(\tilde{w}_\eta =w_\eta \) for all \(\eta \in S{\setminus } \{\sigma _1,\sigma _2\}\) and \(\tilde{w}_{\sigma _1}=2w^A_{\max } -w^A_{\min }\) and \(\tilde{w}_{\sigma _2}=w^A_{\min }\). Then \(p\cdot \tilde{w} \le p\cdot w\), so \(\tilde{w}\) satisfies the budget constraint, and \(U(\tilde{w})>U(w)\) since \(\tilde{w}^A_{\max }= \tilde{w}_{\sigma _1}>w^A_{\max }\) and \(\tilde{w}^A_{\min }=w^A_{\min }\). This is a contradiction to optimality of w. Lemma 3 implies that \({\overline{\sigma }}\in I\).

The last statement of the lemma follows by observing that all these portfolios share the same price and utility. \(\square \)

Lemma 5

Assume Lemma 2 and let \(\alpha <1\). Then w is unambiguous, i.e., \(w_\sigma =w_\nu \) for all \(\sigma ,\nu \in A\), if and only if (20) holds. In this case w is the only optimal portfolio. Condition (20) can only be satisfied if \(\alpha \ge \frac{l-1}{l}\).

Proof

Suppose \({\overline{A}}=\{\sigma \}\) and thus \({\underline{A}}=A{\setminus }\{\sigma \}\). Then, the first-order conditions imply

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_R}{ \pi _R u'(w_R)}= \frac{p_\sigma }{(1-\alpha )(1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R)u'(w^A_{\max })}= \frac{\sum _{\nu \in A{\setminus } \{\sigma \}}p_{\nu }}{\alpha (1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R )u'(w^A_{\min })}\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(39)

where R denotes any risky state among the m ones. Thus,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p_\sigma }{\sum _{\nu \in A{\setminus } \{\sigma \}}p_{\nu }} =\frac{(1-\alpha ) u'(w^A_{\max })}{\alpha u'(w^A_{\min })} < \frac{1-\alpha }{\alpha } \end{aligned}$$
(40)

as \(w^A_{\max }>w^A_{\min }\). Consequently, if there are no \(\sigma \in A\) for which (40) is satisfied, i.e., if the condition (20) holds true, then w must be unambiguous. In order to prove necessity of (20), assume that (40) holds for some \(\sigma \in A\). In the following we show that in this case the unambiguous portfolio cannot be optimal. To this end, suppose by contradiction that the unambiguous portfolio w is optimal and let \(z:=w^A_{\max }=w^A_{\min }\). Then \(\epsilon =0\) needs to maximize the function

$$\begin{aligned} F:{\mathbb {R}}\ni \epsilon \mapsto \alpha u(z-\epsilon ) + (1-\alpha )u\left( z +\delta (\epsilon )\right) \end{aligned}$$

over all \(\epsilon \ge 0\), where \(\delta (\epsilon ):=\epsilon \frac{\sum _{\sigma \in A{\setminus } \{\sigma \}}p_\nu }{p_\sigma }\) is chosen such that the portfolio which invests \(z-\epsilon \) in the states \(\nu \in {\underline{A}}\), and \(z+\delta (\epsilon )\) in the state \(\sigma \) satisfies the budget constraint (while the investment in the risky states is unaltered). F is a concave function and the first-order condition reads

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{u'(z+\delta (\epsilon ))}{u'(z-\epsilon )}= \frac{\alpha }{(1-\alpha )} \frac{p_\sigma }{\sum _{\sigma \in A{\setminus } \{\sigma \}}p_\nu }. \end{aligned}$$

By assumption, the right-hand side of the above equation is strictly smaller than 1. Hence, F attains its optimum for \(\epsilon >0\), which contradicts the optimality at 0 over all \(\epsilon \ge 0\). Finally, note that summing up (20) over all \(\sigma \in A\) yields:

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha \sum _{\sigma \in A} p_\sigma \ge (1-\alpha )(l-1)\sum _{\nu \in A} p_\nu \quad \Leftrightarrow \quad \alpha \ge \frac{l-1}{l}. \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Lemma 6

Assume Lemma 2. If \(\alpha =1\), then w is unambiguous. If \(\alpha =0\), then there is no optimal portfolio.

Proof

If \(\alpha =1\), then (16) is a maxmin agent and also \(\tilde{\pi }\in {\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\). Hence, Lemma 1 proves the claim. The optimization problem of a 0-MEU agent with the maximal set of priors \({\mathcal {C}}_{\max }\) is

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R u(w_R) + (1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R ) u(w^A_{\max }) \rightarrow \max \nonumber \\ \hbox { subject to }&p\cdot w \le p\cdot e \end{aligned}$$
(41)

where e denotes her initial endowment. Since the agent may go arbitrarily long in the ambiguous state \(\sigma \) with \(w_\sigma =w^A_{\max }\) and satisfy the budget constraint by going arbitrarily short in an other ambiguous state, the optimal value in (41) cannot be attained. \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 1

Let w be an optimal portfolio of the maxmin agent and assume that \(w_\sigma \ne w_\eta \) for \(\sigma ,\eta \in A\). Consider the portfolio \({\hat{w}}\) given by \({\hat{w}}_R=w_R\) for any risky state \(R\in S{\setminus } A\) and \({\hat{w}}_\sigma =z\) for any ambiguous state \(\sigma \in A\) where

$$\begin{aligned} z:= \frac{\sum _{\sigma \in A}p_\sigma \, w_\sigma }{\sum _{\sigma \in A}p_\sigma }=\frac{1}{l}\sum _{\sigma \in A} w_\sigma . \end{aligned}$$

The portfolio \({\hat{w}}\) satisfies the budget constraint and

$$\begin{aligned} U({\hat{w}})= & {} \sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R \, u(w_R) + \left( 1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R\right) \, u(z) \\> & {} \sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R \, u(w_R) + \frac{1}{l} \left( 1-\sum _{R\in S{\setminus } A}\pi _R\right) \, \sum _{\sigma \in A} u(w_\sigma )\ge U(w) \end{aligned}$$

where the strict inequality follows from the strict concavity of u and the last inequality is due to \(\tilde{\pi }\in {\mathcal {C}}\). This contradicts the optimality of w.

Optimization in the partially concave case

Consider the optimization problem

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{x\in C} U(x) \quad \hbox {subject to}\quad px\le pe \end{aligned}$$
(42)

where \(C\ne \emptyset \) is a convex subset of \({\mathbb {R}}^n\), \(p,e\in {\mathbb {R}}^n\), and \(U:{\mathbb {R}}^n\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\cup \{-\infty \}\) is a concave function with \({\text {dom}}\,U=C\).

Lemma 7

If the optimal value in (42) is not \(+\infty \) and if there exists at least one \(\bar{x}\in {\text {ri}} C\) with \(p\bar{x}\le pe\), then there is a multiplier \(\lambda \ge 0\) such that the supremum of \(h_\lambda (x)=U(x)-\lambda p(x-e)\), \(x\in {\mathbb {R}}^n\), is finite and equal to the optimal value in (42). Moreover, suppose that \(\lambda >0\) and that D is the set of points \(x\in {\mathbb {R}}^n\) where h attains its maximum intersected with the set of points satisfying \(px=pe\), then D is the set of all optimal solutions to (42).

Proof

see Theorem 28.1 and Corollary 28.2.2 in Rockafellar (1997). \(\square \)

Now suppose that agent n with choice criterium \(U^n:{\mathbb {R}}^{|S|}\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) maximizes her utility over all portfolios \(w\in {\mathbb {R}}^{|S|}\) satisfying the budget constraint \(pw\le pe^n\) for some \(p\in {\mathbb {R}}^{|S|}\) with \(p_i>0\) for all \(i=1,\ldots ,|S|\). Furthermore, assume that an optimal portfolio \({\hat{w}}\) exists and that \({\hat{w}}\in C\) for a convex set \(C\subset {\mathbb {R}}^{|S|}\) such that the restriction \(U^n_C\) of \(U^n\) to C is concave. Then, we may view \(U^n_C\) as defined on all \({\mathbb {R}}^{|S|}\) by defining \(U^n_C(x):=-\infty \) for \(x\not \in C\), and we are thus in the setting of Lemma 7 where \({\hat{w}}\) is a solution to problem (42) with \(U=U^n_C\). Hence, if there exists \(x\in {\text {ri}} C\) with \(px\le pe^n\), which is satisfied if for instance \({\hat{w}}\in {\text {ri}} C\), then there exists a multiplier \(\lambda \ge 0\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} U_C^n({\hat{w}})=\sup _{x\in {\mathbb {R}}^n} h_\lambda (x) \end{aligned}$$
(43)

with \(h_\lambda \) as in Lemma 7. If \(C=C+{\mathbb {R}}_+\cdot (1,0,\ldots ,0)\) and given that the utility function u is strictly increasing we deduce that \(\lambda >0\), since otherwise

$$\begin{aligned} h_\lambda ({\hat{w}}+ (1,0,\ldots ,0))=U^n_C({\hat{w}}+(1,0,\ldots ,0))>U^n_C({\hat{w}}). \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, any solution \({\hat{x}}\) to the right-hand side of (43) with \(p{\hat{x}}=pe^n\) is a solution to the portfolio optimization problem, and in particular \({\hat{w}}\) is such a solution. Additionally, for any solution \({\hat{x}}\) to the right-hand side of (43) we have for all \(y\in {\mathbb {R}}^{|S|}\) that

$$\begin{aligned} U_C^n(y)-\lambda p(y-e^n)\le U_C^n(\hat{x})-\lambda p({\hat{x}}-e^n) \end{aligned}$$

which shows that

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda p\in \partial U_C^n({\hat{x}})\end{aligned}$$
(44)

where \(\partial U_C^n(w)\) denotes the supergradient of \(U_C^n\) at w, i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} \partial U_C^n(w):=\left\{ \nu \in \mathbb {R}^{|S|} \mid \forall y\in \mathbb {R}^{|S|}, \ U_C^n(y)\le U_C^n(w)+ \nu \cdot (y-w) \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ravanelli, C., Svindland, G. Ambiguity sensitive preferences in Ellsberg frameworks. Econ Theory 67, 53–89 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1095-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1095-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation