Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare 1/2014

01.01.2014 | Original Paper

Strategic voting and nomination

verfasst von: James Green-Armytage

Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare | Ausgabe 1/2014

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Using computer simulations based on three separate data generating processes, I estimate the fraction of elections in which sincere voting is a core equilibrium given each of eight single-winner voting rules. Additionally, I determine how often each rule is vulnerable to simple voting strategies such as ‘burying’ and ‘compromising’, and how often each rule gives an incentive for non-winning candidates to enter or leave races. I find that Hare is least vulnerable to strategic voting in general, whereas Borda, Coombs, approval, and range are most vulnerable. I find that plurality is most vulnerable to compromising and strategic exit (causing an unusually strong tendency toward two-party systems), and that Borda is most vulnerable to strategic entry. I use analytical proofs to provide further intuition for some of my key results.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
Specifically, if there are more than two candidates for a single office, and a non-dictatorial election method allows voters to rank the candidates in any order, then there must be some profile of voter preferences under which at least one voter can get a preferred result by voting insincerely. This well-known ‘Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem’ relies in turn on the even more well-known ‘Arrow theorem’; for this, see Arrow (1951, rev. ed. 1963).
 
2
For example, Nitzan (1985), Kelly (1993), Smith (1999), and Aleskerov and Kurbanov (1999). Saari (1990) focuses on ‘micro manipulations’, i.e. strategic incursions by groups of arbitrarily small size.
 
3
For example, Chamberlin (1985), Lepelley and Mbih (1994), Kim and Roush (1996), Lepelley and Valognes (2003), and Tideman (2006).
 
4
For example, Favardin et al. (2002), and Favardin and Lepelley (2006). Pritchard and Wilson (2007) determine whether manipulation is possible, and what the minimum coalition size is for strategic incursion in each case.
 
5
Chamberlin (1985) considers only the four candidate case, while Lepelley and Mbih (1994), Favardin et al. (2002), Favardin and Lepelley (2006), Lepelley and Valognes (2003) and Pritchard and Wilson (2007) consider only the three candidate case.
 
6
Nitzan (1985), Kim and Roush (1996), Smith (1999), Saari (1990) and Kelly (1993) all use an ‘impartial culture’ (IC) model, while Lepelley and Mbih (1994), Favardin et al. (2002), and Favardin and Lepelley (2006) use an ‘impartial anonymous culture’ (IAC) model. Tideman (2006) uses a data set consisting of 87 elections. On the other hand, Chamberlin (1985) uses both spatial model and an impartial culture model, Pritchard and Wilson use both IC and IAC, and Lepelley and Valognes (2003) use a somewhat more general model that has IC and IAC as two of its special cases.
 
7
Osborne and Slivinski (1996) focus on nomination equilibria given the plurality and runoff systems, with costs of entry and benefits of winning. Besley and Coate (1997) focus on nomination and voting equilibria given the plurality system. Moreno and Puy (2005, 2009) focus on positional voting rules, and show that plurality is unique among them in that it will elect the Condorcet winner among declared candidates when there are three or fewer potential candidates, although it will not necessarily do so when there are four or more. Another approach to strategic nomination is given by Tideman (1987), who shows that the addition or removal of ‘clone’ candidates may change the result given some voting rules, but not others.
 
8
In a result that is somewhat analogous to the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem, Dutta et al. (2001) show that there will in some cases be downward pressure on the number of candidates (in the present paper, I will call this an incentive for ‘strategic exit’), given any ‘unanimous’ and non-dictatorial ranked ballot voting rule. (Note that this doesn’t apply to non-ranked systems like approval or range voting.)
 
9
For example, these may be assigned randomly, according to lexicographic or anti-lexicographic order, etc., but in any case they are exogenous, and known by the voters and candidates before the election.
 
10
This system is the application to the single-winner case of proportional representation by the single transferable vote, which is often named for Thomas Hare, who introduced the idea of successively eliminating the candidate with the fewest first choice votes. See ((Hoag and Hallett 1926, pp. 162–195))
 
11
See Coombs (1964). I note that some versions of Coombs include a provision to automatically elect a candidate who holds a majority of first choice votes, but I don’t use this provision here.
 
12
Condorcet (1785) describes the pairwise comparison method and the Condorcet winner. He also observes the possibility of a majority rule cycle emerging despite transitive voter preferences—this is known as the Condorcet paradox.
 
13
Black (1958, p. 175), develops the minimax method as a possible interpretation of Condorcet’s intended proposal. Levin and Nalebuff (1995) label this method as the “Simpson-Kramer min-max rule”; presumably this is due to Simpson (1969) and Kramer (1977). (Nurmi (1999), p. 18) refers to it as “Condorcet’s successive reversal procedure”. (Tideman (2006), p. 212) refers to it as “maximin”.
 
14
This method was proposed by Jean-Charles de Borda in 1770; see (McLean and Urken (1995), p. 81), Saari (2001) gives a contemporary argument in favor of it.
 
15
See Brams and Fishburn (1978, 1983).
 
16
This terminology was used by Blake Cretney, on his currently-defunct web site Condorcet.org.
 
17
See Duverger (1964).
 
18
To be precise, the strong incentives for compromising and strategic exit make it highly likely that there will only be two ‘viable’ candidates in any particular plurality election. The two parties that these candidates belong to may vary from jurisdiction to jurisdiction, but once two parties have been established as dominant in any given jurisdiction, it is difficult for a third party to mount an effective challenge there. Cox (1997) refers to this as ‘local bipartism’.
 
19
I discuss these immunities in Sect. 8 below. Woodall (1997) demonstrates that Condorcet-efficient methods can’t satisfy his ‘later-no-help’ and ‘later-no-harm’ criteria; a similar proof can be used to show that they must be vulnerable to the burying strategy in some situations.
 
20
This is similar to the model described in Chamberlin and Cohen (1978), but without inter-dimensional covariance.
 
21
The impartial culture model is defined, for example, in Nitzan (1985).
 
22
Here, I follow Tideman and Plassmann (2011).
 
23
This process creates 931 elections with three candidates, 1553 with four candidates, 1898 with five candidates, and 1764 with six candidates.
 
24
More detailed descriptions, along with the codes themselves, are available from the author on request.
 
25
It is also possible to ask how often groups of candidates may change the result in a way that they all prefer by either simultaneously entering or simultaneously exiting (thus, looking for core equilibria instead of Nash equilibria), but I omit this additional analysis in the interest of brevity, because its results don’t differ in any particularly interesting way from the results of the analysis already described.
 
26
A margin of error of \(\pm \).0098 is the upper bound, which applies when the true probability is exactly one half. I further reduce the random error in the difference between the scores that the various voting methods receive by using the same set of randomly generated elections for each method.
 
27
Despite the similar name, this is not equivalent to the impartial culture model. Rather, the IAC model supposes that every possible division of the voters among the \(C!\) possible preference orderings is equally likely.
 
28
This was also defined by Blake Cretney on Condorcet.org. Note that it is not the same as burying, compromising, or a combination of these, as it involves shifting votes from candidate q to candidate x in order to help candidate q.
 
29
See for example Beck (1975), who shows that ties are unlikely in large two-candidate elections; it is not hard to extend this intuition to the case of a pairwise tie within a multi-candidate election.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Aleskerov F, Kurbanov E (1999) Degree of manipulability of social choice procedures. In: Alkan et al. (eds) Current Trends in Economics. Springer, Berlin Aleskerov F, Kurbanov E (1999) Degree of manipulability of social choice procedures. In: Alkan et al. (eds) Current Trends in Economics. Springer, Berlin
Zurück zum Zitat Arrow K (1951, rev. ed. 1963) Social Choice and Individual Values Arrow K (1951, rev. ed. 1963) Social Choice and Individual Values
Zurück zum Zitat Beck N (1975) A note on the probability of a tied election. Public Choice 23(1):75–79CrossRef Beck N (1975) A note on the probability of a tied election. Public Choice 23(1):75–79CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Besley T, Coate S (1997) An economic model of representative democracy. Q J Econ 112(1):84–114CrossRef Besley T, Coate S (1997) An economic model of representative democracy. Q J Econ 112(1):84–114CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Black D (1958) The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Black D (1958) The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Brams S, Fishburn P (1978) Approval voting. Am Political Sci Rev 72(3):831–847CrossRef Brams S, Fishburn P (1978) Approval voting. Am Political Sci Rev 72(3):831–847CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brams S, Fishburn P (1983) Approval voting. Birkhäuser Brams S, Fishburn P (1983) Approval voting. Birkhäuser
Zurück zum Zitat Condorcet M de (1785) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix Condorcet M de (1785) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix
Zurück zum Zitat Coombs C (1964) A Theory of Data. Wiley, New York Coombs C (1964) A Theory of Data. Wiley, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Chamberlin J, Cohen M (1978) Toward applicable social choice theory: a comparison of social choice functions under spatial model assumptions. Am Political Sci Rev 72(4):1341–1356CrossRef Chamberlin J, Cohen M (1978) Toward applicable social choice theory: a comparison of social choice functions under spatial model assumptions. Am Political Sci Rev 72(4):1341–1356CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chamberlin J (1985) An investigation into the relative manipulability of four voting systems. Behav Sci 30(4):195–203CrossRef Chamberlin J (1985) An investigation into the relative manipulability of four voting systems. Behav Sci 30(4):195–203CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cox G (1997) Making votes count: strategic coordination in the world’s electoral systems. Cambridge university press, Cambridge Cox G (1997) Making votes count: strategic coordination in the world’s electoral systems. Cambridge university press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Dutta B, Jackson M, Le Breton M (2001) Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica 69(4):1013–1037CrossRef Dutta B, Jackson M, Le Breton M (2001) Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica 69(4):1013–1037CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Duverger M (1964) Political Parties: Their Organization and Activity in the Modern State. Methuen, London Duverger M (1964) Political Parties: Their Organization and Activity in the Modern State. Methuen, London
Zurück zum Zitat Favardin P, Lepelley D, Serais J (2002) Borda rule, Copeland method and strategic manipulation. Rev Econ Des 7:213–228 Favardin P, Lepelley D, Serais J (2002) Borda rule, Copeland method and strategic manipulation. Rev Econ Des 7:213–228
Zurück zum Zitat Favardin P, Lepelley D (2006) Some further results on the manipulability of social choice rules. Soc Choice Welf 26:485–509CrossRef Favardin P, Lepelley D (2006) Some further results on the manipulability of social choice rules. Soc Choice Welf 26:485–509CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41:587–601CrossRef Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41:587–601CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Green-Armytage J (2011) Four Condorcet-Hare hybrid methods for single-winner elections. Voting Matters 29:1–14 Green-Armytage J (2011) Four Condorcet-Hare hybrid methods for single-winner elections. Voting Matters 29:1–14
Zurück zum Zitat Hoag C, Hallett G (1926) Proportional Representation. MacMillan, New York Hoag C, Hallett G (1926) Proportional Representation. MacMillan, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Kelly J (1993) Almost all social choice rules are highly manipulable, but a few aren’t. Soc Choice Welf 10(2):161–175CrossRef Kelly J (1993) Almost all social choice rules are highly manipulable, but a few aren’t. Soc Choice Welf 10(2):161–175CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kim KH, Roush FW (1996) Statistical manipulability of social choice functions. Group Decis Negot 5: 263–282 Kim KH, Roush FW (1996) Statistical manipulability of social choice functions. Group Decis Negot 5: 263–282
Zurück zum Zitat Kramer G (1977) A dynamical model of political equilibrium. J Econo Theory 16(2):310–334CrossRef Kramer G (1977) A dynamical model of political equilibrium. J Econo Theory 16(2):310–334CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lepelley D, Mbih B (1994) The vulnerability of four social choice functions to coalitional manipulation of preferences. Soc Choice Welf 11(3):253–265CrossRef Lepelley D, Mbih B (1994) The vulnerability of four social choice functions to coalitional manipulation of preferences. Soc Choice Welf 11(3):253–265CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lepelley D, Valognes F (2003) Voting rules, manipulability and social homogeneity. Public Choice 116: 165–184 Lepelley D, Valognes F (2003) Voting rules, manipulability and social homogeneity. Public Choice 116: 165–184
Zurück zum Zitat Levin J, Nalebuff B (1995) An introduction to vote-counting schemes. J Econ Perspectives 9(1):3–26 Levin J, Nalebuff B (1995) An introduction to vote-counting schemes. J Econ Perspectives 9(1):3–26
Zurück zum Zitat McLean I, Urken A (1995) Class Soc Choice. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor McLean I, Urken A (1995) Class Soc Choice. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor
Zurück zum Zitat Moreno B, Puy S (2005) The scoring rules in an endogenous election. Soc Choice Welf 25:115–125CrossRef Moreno B, Puy S (2005) The scoring rules in an endogenous election. Soc Choice Welf 25:115–125CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Moreno B, Puy S (2009) Plurality rule works in three-candidate elections. Theory Decis 67:145–162 Moreno B, Puy S (2009) Plurality rule works in three-candidate elections. Theory Decis 67:145–162
Zurück zum Zitat Nitzan S (1985) The vulnerability of point-voting schemes to preference variation and strategic manipulation. Public Choice 47:349–370CrossRef Nitzan S (1985) The vulnerability of point-voting schemes to preference variation and strategic manipulation. Public Choice 47:349–370CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nurmi H (1999) Voting Paradoxes and How to Deal with Them. Springer, BerlinCrossRef Nurmi H (1999) Voting Paradoxes and How to Deal with Them. Springer, BerlinCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Osborne M, Slivinski A (1996) A model of political competition with citizen-candidates. Q J Econ 111(1):65–96CrossRef Osborne M, Slivinski A (1996) A model of political competition with citizen-candidates. Q J Econ 111(1):65–96CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pritchard G, Wilson M (2007) Exact results on manipulability of positional voting rules. Soc Choice Welf 29:487–513CrossRef Pritchard G, Wilson M (2007) Exact results on manipulability of positional voting rules. Soc Choice Welf 29:487–513CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Saari D (1990) Susceptibility to manipulation. Public Choice 64:21–41CrossRef Saari D (1990) Susceptibility to manipulation. Public Choice 64:21–41CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Saari D (2001) Chaotic Elections!. American Mathematical Society, Providence Saari D (2001) Chaotic Elections!. American Mathematical Society, Providence
Zurück zum Zitat Satterthwaite M (1975) Strategy-proofness and arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. J Econ Theory 10:187–217CrossRef Satterthwaite M (1975) Strategy-proofness and arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. J Econ Theory 10:187–217CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Smith D (1999) Manipulability measures of common social choice functions. Soc Choice Welf 16:639–661CrossRef Smith D (1999) Manipulability measures of common social choice functions. Soc Choice Welf 16:639–661CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Simpson P (1969) On defining areas of voter choice: Professor Tullock on stable voting. Q J Econ 83(3): 478–490 Simpson P (1969) On defining areas of voter choice: Professor Tullock on stable voting. Q J Econ 83(3): 478–490
Zurück zum Zitat Tideman TN (1987) Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Soc Choice Welf 4(3):185–206CrossRef Tideman TN (1987) Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Soc Choice Welf 4(3):185–206CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Tideman TN (2006) Collective Decisions and Voting: the Potential for Public Choice. Ashgate, Aldershot Tideman TN (2006) Collective Decisions and Voting: the Potential for Public Choice. Ashgate, Aldershot
Zurück zum Zitat Tullock G (1967) Proportional representation. In Toward a Mathematics of Politics. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, pp 144–157 Tullock G (1967) Proportional representation. In Toward a Mathematics of Politics. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, pp 144–157
Zurück zum Zitat Woodall D (1997) Monotonicity of single-seat preferential election rules. Discret Appl Math 77:81–98CrossRef Woodall D (1997) Monotonicity of single-seat preferential election rules. Discret Appl Math 77:81–98CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Strategic voting and nomination
verfasst von
James Green-Armytage
Publikationsdatum
01.01.2014
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Erschienen in
Social Choice and Welfare / Ausgabe 1/2014
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Elektronische ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-013-0725-3

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2014

Social Choice and Welfare 1/2014 Zur Ausgabe