Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Some remarks on the concept of proportionality

  • Published:
Annals of Operations Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Proportionality plays a role in many principles of fairness or justice. In particular, it is often invoked in electoral systems aiming at a similarity of opinion distributions in the parliament and in the electorate at large. The proportional systems of representation (PR systems, for short) strive for maximal similarity between these two distributions. Unfortunately, the concept of proportionality is imprecise in two senses: it is vague and ambiguous. In other words, once a clear criterion of what we mean by proportionality is given, different PR systems may differ in the degree of proportionality achieved in any given election. This is what will be referred to as the vagueness of proportionality (of election outcomes). Proportionality is, however, also ambiguous in that it refers to different things depending on how the voters are expected to signal their opinions and on what is it that one wishes to distribute proportionally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A PR system based on approval balloting is introduced and analyzed by Brams and Kilgour (2011). See also Kilgour and Marshall (2012). Of course, this balloting type stems from the approval voting method introduced by Brams and Fishburn (1983).

  2. Candidate C receives x Borda points from a voter if this voter ranks x candidates lower than C. Summing the Borda points given to C by all voters, we get C’s Borda score. The Borda Count is a system that ranks candidates in the order of their Borda scores.

  3. A reviewer accurately points out that the concept of proportionality per se is neither vague nor ambiguous in the purely technical sense. Proportionality refers to a relation between two distributions, e.g. of votes and seats. The smaller the difference—measured with some agreed-upon metric—the more proportional is the system. However, and this where ambiguity enters the picture, votes or ballots can be of different kinds. Hence, a seat distribution that is reasonably proportional in the sense of plurality ballots, may be rather disproportional when approval or STV ballots are used. Vagueness, in turn, is a result of using different PR formulae, like in the example at the beginning of this section.

  4. A brief analysis of results and campaign is given by Nurmi and Nurmi (2012).

  5. The island province of Åland is a single-member constituency. Its party system also differs from the mainland. Hence it is excluded from the present discussion.

  6. The new system—supported by a majority in the 2007–2011 parliament—is unlikely to be adopted anytime soon, since it was not accepted by the majority government following the 2011 election. So it remains a theoretical benchmark for comparing election results.

  7. In the table the strict preference orders are written from the most preferred (top-most) to the last preferred one. We shall also use ≻ to express strict preference so that AB denotes a strict preference of A over B.

  8. A reviewer points out that the Martin index discussed by Riker (1986) is a precursor of the Penrose one. Overall, the literature on power indices in vast. For a thorough historical and theoretical account, see Felsenthal and Machover (1998). A more recent treatment is Laruelle and Valenciano (2008). For applications to the European Union, see Cichocki and Zyczkowski (2010).

  9. For a recent and relatively extensive discussion on fair distribution of voting power among representatives, the reader is referred to Cichocki and Zyczkowski (2010).

  10. The theoretical possibilities of agenda manipulation are literally endless in the spatial voting models studied by McKelvey (1979). For a brief discussion on the importance of agenda in parliamentary voting, see Nurmi (2010).

  11. The argument is a slight modification of Baigent’s (1987, 163) illustration.

References

  • Baigent, N. (1987). Preference proximity and anonymous social choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 102, 161–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baigent, N., & Klamler, C. (2004). Transitive closure, proximity and intransitivities. Economic Theory, 23, 175–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balinski, M., & Young, H. P., (1982). Fair representation: meeting the ideal of one man, one vote. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2010). Majority judgment: measuring, ranking and electing. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banzhaf, J. F. (1965). Weighted voting doesn’t work: a mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Review, 19, 317–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, S., & Holler, M. J. (1986). Randomized decision rules in voting games: a model for strict proportional power. Quality and Quantity, 20, 419–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, S., & Nurmi, H. (1988). Making choices in the old-fashioned way. Economia Delle Scelte Pubbliche, 2, 95–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Fishburn, P. C. (1983). Approval voting. Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Kilgour, D. M. (July 2011). Satisfaction approval voting. Manuscript.

  • Cichocki, M. & Zyczkowski, K. (Eds.) (2010). Institutional design and voting power in the European Union. Farnham, Surrey: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Brams, S. J. (1983). Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56, 201–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, G., & Tsebelis, G. (1996). An institutional critique of inter-governmentalism. International Organization, 50, 269–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grilli di Cortona, P., Manzi, C., Pennisi, A., Ricca, F., & Simeone, B. (1999). Evaluation and optimization of electoral systems. SIAM monographs on discrete mathematics and applications. Philadelphia: SIAM.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kilgour, D. M., & Marshall, E. (2012). Approval balloting for fixed-size committees. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Studies in choice and welfare, Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laruelle, A., & Valenciano, F. (2008). Voting and collective decision-making. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D. (1979). General conditions for global intransitivities in formal voting models. Econometrica, 47, 1085–1112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merrill, S. III, & Nagel, J. (1987). The effect of approval balloting on strategic voting under alternative decision rules. American Political Science Review, 81, 509–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanson, E. J. (1883). Methods of election. Transactions and Proceedings of the Royal Society of Victoria, XIX, 197–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. & Urken, A. B. (Eds.) (1995). Classics of social choice. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (2010). Voting weights or agenda control: which one really matters?. AUCO Czech Economic Review, 4(1), 5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H., & Nurmi, L. (2012). The parliamentary election in Finland, April 2011. Electoral Studies, 31, 234–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, L. S. (1946). The elementary statistics of majority voting. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 109, 53–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricca, F., & Simeone, B. (2008). Local search algorithms for political districting. European Journal of Operational Research, 189, 1409–1426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1986). The first power index. Social Choice and Welfare, 3, 293–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, T. (1995). The paradox of representation. The Journal of Politics, 57, 309–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L. S. (1962). Values of games with infinitely many players. In M. Maschler (Ed.), Recent advances in game theory (pp. 113–118). Philadelphia: Ivy Curtis Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L. S., & Shubik, M. (1954). A method for evaluating the distribution of power in a committee system. American Political Science Review, 48, 41–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simeone, B. & Pukelsheim, F. (Eds.) (2006). Mathematics and democracy. Studies in choice and welfare. Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank two anonymous reviewers for constructive criticism and suggestions. The support of Academy of Finland and University of Turku through their funding of the Public Choice Research Centre of University of Turku is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hannu Nurmi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nurmi, H. Some remarks on the concept of proportionality. Ann Oper Res 215, 231–244 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-012-1252-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-012-1252-9

Keywords

Navigation