Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Argumentation 2/2008

01.05.2008

Rationality, Reasonableness, and Critical Rationalism: Problems with the Pragma-dialectical View

verfasst von: Harvey Siegel, John Biro

Erschienen in: Argumentation | Ausgabe 2/2008

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

A major virtue of the Pragma-Dialectical theory of argumentation is its commitment to reasonableness and rationality as central criteria of argumentative quality. However, the account of these key notions offered by the originators of this theory, Frans van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst, seems to us problematic in several respects. In what follows we criticize that account and suggest an alternative, offered elsewhere, that seems to us to be both independently preferable and more in keeping with the epistemic approach to arguments and argumentation we favor.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
The most recent systematic statement of the view is van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004), on which this discussion is based. All references in the text to these authors are to that book.
 
2
We articulate and defend the epistemic view in Biro and Siegel (1992), (2006) and (2006a), and Siegel and Biro (1997).
 
3
Argumentation is, on this view, “instrumental,” aimed at “achieving a certain goal”, namely, that of “justify[ing] or refut[ing] a proposition...defend[ing] a standpoint in such a way that the other party is convinced of its acceptability.” (2004, p. 3; cf. p. 12: argumentation “aims to convince a reasonable critic of a certain standpoint.”) Since this is the goal of the activity, argumentative quality on the pragma-dialectical view is a matter of a given bit of argumentation’s achieving this goal. This seems to us a mistaken way of conceiving of argumentative quality. First, a party, even a reasonable one, can be erroneously convinced of the acceptability or otherwise of a standpoint. Second, and more importantly, an argument’s quality, i.e., its ability to ‘justify or refute a proposition,’ is independent of the reaction (becoming convinced or otherwise) of those who hear or read it. Having argued for these points in the papers cited in the previous footnote, we will not pursue the matter here.
 
4
Further examples which demonstrate how the relevant sort of normativity, i.e., epistemic normativity, fails to track the pragma-dialectical rules and ‘dialectical reasonableness’ are given in Biro and Siegel (1992), pp. 89–91.
 
5
The previous two paragraphs are taken, with changes, from Biro and Siegel (2006), pp. 6–7.
 
6
By ‘adequate’ we mean sufficient to yield knowledge or justified belief, where what is sufficient depends, of course, on subject matter, purpose, and circumstance. For reasons of both space and expertise, we limit our discussion to the Popperian version of critical rationalism.
 
7
It is perhaps worth pointing out that this understanding of ‘justificationism’ as rejecting positive support altogether is not only endorsed by Popper consistently throughout his many writings, it grows increasingly radical as time goes on, as the final citation makes clear.
 
8
The charge that Popper’s position has a ‘whiff of inductivism’ about it was made by Lakatos (1974, pp. 256–263). Popper grudgingly acknowledges the point in his reply to Ayer: “In spite of this, there may be a ‘whiff’ of inductivism here. It enters with the vague realist assumption that reality, though unknown, is in some respects similar to what science tells us or, in other words, with the assumption that science can progress towards greater verisimilitude.” (Popper 1974, p. 1193, note 165b) Newton-Smith remarks of this passage that “it is just false to say that there is a whiff of inductivism here—there is a full-blown storm.” (Newton-Smith 1981, p. 68; cf. pp. 66–70) O’Hear says of it that “It is not surprising that some commentators have seen this passage as an enormous concession by Popper to his critics.” (O’Hear 1980, p. 67) Putnam also “detect[s] an inductivist quaver” in Popper’s writings (Putnam 1974, p. 224).
 
9
We strongly endorse Oddie’s (1996) positive case for the existence and epistemic significance of objectively good reasons, and his devastating critique of (Miller’s version of) critical rationalism.
 
10
There are actually three trilemmas in play here that should be distinguished. In his classic The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959), Popper discusses ‘Freis’ Trilemma’ (FT), according to which the requirement of positive justification ends in dogmatism, infinite regress, or psychologism, by which Popper means justification by immediate sense experience (1959, pp. 93–105). Popper rejects the latter as being of a piece with induction, which, of course, he also rejects; he ‘resolves’ FT by rejecting the possibility of positive justification and urging that our preference for corroborated theories be seen in terms of decision rather than justification (1959, pp. 106–111). But this resolution fails for the reasons given above. Another Trilemma is that of Agrippa. Agrippa’s Trilemma (AT) has it that justification ends in infinite regress, circularity, or dogmatic assumption (Williams 1999, pp. 38–41). AT is very nearly equivalent to MT: the former’s third possibility is dogmatism; the latter’s is arbitrariness. (They are equivalent if a dogmatic assumption is always an arbitrary stopping point. Williams articulates AT in both ways: in terms of dogmatic assumption in Williams (1999), p. 39; and in terms of arbitrariness in Williams (2005), pp. 205.) Our example in the text below (Cheney’s news conference) is meant to avoid both arbitrariness and dogmatic assumption. But as we try to make clear in the text, we do not offer it as a resolution of the ancient problem of the structure (or regress) of justification. Addressing that problem is beyond the scope of this paper. (See Siegel 1997, ch. 5, for a resolution that rests on ‘self-reflexive’ justification or ‘self-justification.’ Thanks to Liz Giles for helpful discussion of AT.)
 
11
For further discussion of this resolution see Siegel (1997), ch. 8.
 
12
It is worth noting that our proposed resolution bears a striking resemblance to Popper’s own solution to ‘Freis’s Trilemma’ concerning the status of ‘basic statements.’ Cf. Popper (1959), p. 105.
 
13
It may be thought that our argument commits us to just such a premise: namely, that reasons can afford justification and that we therefore ought to reason in accordance with them. A justification of this premise, in the form of an answer to the question ‘Why be rational?,’ is offered in Siegel (1997), ch. 5.
 
14
See references in note 2 above.
 
15
As suggested by one of the reviewers. We wish to thank the reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Biro, J., and H. Siegel. 1992. Normativity, argumentation and an epistemic theory of fallacies. In Argumentation illuminated Ch. 7, eds. F.H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair, and C.A. Willard, 85–103. Amsterdam: SICSAT. Biro, J., and H. Siegel. 1992. Normativity, argumentation and an epistemic theory of fallacies. In Argumentation illuminated Ch. 7, eds. F.H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair, and C.A. Willard, 85–103. Amsterdam: SICSAT.
Zurück zum Zitat Biro, J., and H. Siegel. 2006. Pragma-dialectic versus epistemic theories of arguing and arguments: Rivals or partners? In Considering pragma-dialectics, eds. P. Houtlosser, and A. van Rees, 1–10. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Biro, J., and H. Siegel. 2006. Pragma-dialectic versus epistemic theories of arguing and arguments: Rivals or partners? In Considering pragma-dialectics, eds. P. Houtlosser, and A. van Rees, 1–10. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Zurück zum Zitat Biro, J., and H. Siegel. 2006a. In defense of the objective epistemic approach to argumentation. Informal Logic, 26:91–101. Biro, J., and H. Siegel. 2006a. In defense of the objective epistemic approach to argumentation. Informal Logic, 26:91–101.
Zurück zum Zitat van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Lakatos, I. 1974. Popper on demarcation and induction. In Schilpp (1974), 241–273. Lakatos, I. 1974. Popper on demarcation and induction. In Schilpp (1974), 241–273.
Zurück zum Zitat Levison, A. 1974. Popper, hume, and the traditional problem of induction. In Schilpp (1974), 322–331. Levison, A. 1974. Popper, hume, and the traditional problem of induction. In Schilpp (1974), 322–331.
Zurück zum Zitat Miller, D. 1985. Editor’s introduction. In Popper selections. ed. D. Miller, 9–22. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Miller, D. 1985. Editor’s introduction. In Popper selections. ed. D. Miller, 9–22. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Miller, D. 1994. Critical rationalism: A restatement and defense. Chicago: Open Court. Miller, D. 1994. Critical rationalism: A restatement and defense. Chicago: Open Court.
Zurück zum Zitat Newton-Smith, W.H. 1981. The rationality of science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Newton-Smith, W.H. 1981. The rationality of science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Zurück zum Zitat O’Hear, A. 1980. Karl Popper. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. O’Hear, A. 1980. Karl Popper. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K.R. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Harper & Row. Popper, K.R. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Harper & Row.
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K.R. 1963. Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. New York: Harper & Row. Popper, K.R. 1963. Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. New York: Harper & Row.
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K.R. 1972. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Popper, K.R. 1972. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K.R. 1974. Replies to my critics. In Schilpp (1974), 961–1197. Popper, K.R. 1974. Replies to my critics. In Schilpp (1974), 961–1197.
Zurück zum Zitat Putnam, H. 1974. The “Corroboration” of theories. In Schilpp (1974), 221–240. Putnam, H. 1974. The “Corroboration” of theories. In Schilpp (1974), 221–240.
Zurück zum Zitat Salmon, W.C. 1966. The foundations of scientific inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Salmon, W.C. 1966. The foundations of scientific inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Schilpp, P.A. ed. 1974. The philosophy of Karl Popper. (The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XIV.) La Salle: Open Court. Schilpp, P.A. ed. 1974. The philosophy of Karl Popper. (The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XIV.) La Salle: Open Court.
Zurück zum Zitat Siegel, H. 1997. Rationality redeemed?: Further dialogues on an educational ideal. New York: Routledge. Siegel, H. 1997. Rationality redeemed?: Further dialogues on an educational ideal. New York: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Siegel, H., and J. Biro 1997. Epistemic normativity, argumentation, and fallacies. Argumentation 11:277–292.CrossRef Siegel, H., and J. Biro 1997. Epistemic normativity, argumentation, and fallacies. Argumentation 11:277–292.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Williams, M. 1999. Skepticism. In The Blackwell guide to epistemology. eds. J. Greco, and E. Sosa, 35–69. Oxford: Blackwell. Williams, M. 1999. Skepticism. In The Blackwell guide to epistemology. eds. J. Greco, and E. Sosa, 35–69. Oxford: Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Williams, M. 2005. Doing without immediate justification. In Contemporary debates in epistemology. eds. M. Steup, and E. Sosa, 202–216. Oxford: Blackwell. Williams, M. 2005. Doing without immediate justification. In Contemporary debates in epistemology. eds. M. Steup, and E. Sosa, 202–216. Oxford: Blackwell.
Metadaten
Titel
Rationality, Reasonableness, and Critical Rationalism: Problems with the Pragma-dialectical View
verfasst von
Harvey Siegel
John Biro
Publikationsdatum
01.05.2008
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Argumentation / Ausgabe 2/2008
Print ISSN: 0920-427X
Elektronische ISSN: 1572-8374
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-007-9063-x

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2008

Argumentation 2/2008 Zur Ausgabe