Skip to main content
Log in

Understanding Epistemic Relevance

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Agents require a constant flow, and a high level of processing, of relevant semantic information, in order to interact successfully among themselves and with the environment in which they are embedded. Standard theories of information, however, are silent on the nature of epistemic relevance. In this paper, a subjectivist interpretation of epistemic relevance is developed and defended. It is based on a counterfactual and metatheoretical analysis of the degree of relevance of some semantic information i to an informee/agent a, as a function of the accuracy of i understood as an answer to a query q, given the probability that q might be asked by a. This interpretation of epistemic relevance vindicates a strongly semantic theory of information, according to which semantic information encapsulates truth. It accounts satisfactorily for several important applications and interpretations of the concept of relevant information in a variety of philosophical areas. And it interfaces successfully with current philosophical interpretations of causal and logical relevance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an overview see Bremer and Cohnitz (2004) and Floridi (2004a).

  2. The classic reference is Shannon and Weaver (1949, rep. 1998), see Jones (1979) for an introduction.

  3. The list includes: Bar-Hillel and Carnap (1953), Bar-Hillel (1964), Hintikka and Suppes (1970), Israel and Perry (1990), and Floridi (2004b).

  4. In this sense, theoretical information theory is a branch of probability theory, and applied information theory a branch of engineering, see Cover and Thomas (1991).

  5. For an overview see Floridi (2004a).

  6. This is argued in Floridi (2005b), see Sequoiah-Grayson [forthcoming] for a recent defence.

  7. Defenders of the alethically neutral nature of information include Devlin (1991); Colburn (2000); Fetzer (2004); Dodig-Crnkovic (2005); the latter two criticise Floridi (2004b).

  8. See for example Yus (2006), a bibliography online on relevance theory in pragmatics and related disciplines. For recent review articles on relevance in information science see Greisdorf (2000) and the very useful Borlund (2003). Philosophical accounts of relevance include Gärdenfors (1978); Cohen (1994); Lakemeyer (1997); and Delgrande and Pelletier (1998), all works that have influenced the research for this paper.

  9. “A specific ‘entity’ (such as an action, training sample, attribute, background proposition, or inference step) is irrelevant to a task in some context if the appropriate response to the task does not change by an unacceptable [sic] amount if we change the entity in that context, Otherwise, we view that entity as (somewhat) relevant to the task. This view is explicitly stated in the paper by Galles and Pearl, which deals with causality and where a perturbation corresponds to a material change in the physical world.” Subramanian et al. (1997), p. 2.

  10. The adequacy of Körner criterion of relevance for propositional logic has been proved by Schroder (1992).

  11. The analysis of relevance also depends on the level of abstraction (Floridi and Sanders 2004) at which the process of assessment is conducted. A level of abstraction may be seen as the precise specification of the way in which some information is being accessed and processed, cf. the analysis of “the point of view” according to which something is relevant in Cohen (1994).

  12. Many thanks to Jürg Kohlas for having called my attention to this equivalence.

  13. A question Q is loaded if the respondent is committed to (some part of) the presupposition of Q (Walton 1991, 340) e.g. “how many times did you kiss Mary?” which presupposes that you did kiss Mary at least once.

  14. Two further consequences are that (i) rational agents cannot possess exactly the same information and agree to disagree about the probability of some past or future events. In fact, they must independently come to the same conclusion, and (ii) they cannot surprise each other informationally.

  15. Bowles (1990) follows a similar strategy to explain probabilistically the relation of relevance in propositional inferences.

  16. Accuracy is the degree of conformity of a measure or calculated parameter to its actual (true) value. Precision (also called reproducibility or repeatability) is the degree to which further measurements or calculations show the same or similar results.

  17. Plato, Meno 80d–81a:

    “Meno: And how will you investigate, Socrates, that of which you know nothing at all? Where can you find a starting-point in the region of the unknown? Moreover, even if you happen to come full upon what you want, how will you ever know that this is the thing that you did not know?

    Socrates: I know, Meno, what you mean; but just see what a tiresome dispute you are introducing. You argue that man cannot enquire either about that which he knows, or about that which he does not know; for if he knows, he has no need to enquire; and if not, he cannot; for he does not know the very subject about which he is to enquire.”

  18. This solution is partly adopted in information theory by Tishby et al. (1999), who “define the relevant information in a signal x ∈ X as being the information that this signal provides about another signal y ∈ Y. Examples include the information that face images provide about the names of the people portrayed, or the information that speech sounds provide about the words spoken.” Note that what they treat as “relevance” is really a quantitative relation of structural conjunction, which can be considered a necessary condition for semantic relevance, but should not be confused with it.

  19. The mere assumption of these values is justified here because this is only an illustrative example. The identification of the right set of Bayesian priors is a hard problem faced by any analysis of real-life phenomena. Of course, the formulation of a prior distribution over the unknown parameters of the model should be based on the available data (including subjective beliefs) about the modelled phenomena, yet this is easier said than done, see for example Dongen (2006).

  20. “Relevance here is a technical term (though clearly related to the natural language homonym), whereby an interpretation is relevant only in cases where the cognitive cost of processing the event which demands the attention of the agent is outweighed by the cognitive benefits of that processing (where benefits include deriving or strengthening new assumptions, and confirming or rejecting previous assumptions). ‘Optimal relevance’ states that the first interpretation which crosses the relevance threshold is the right one; that is, that the first relevant interpretation the addressee arrives at is the one the speaker intended to communicate.” (Emma Borg, Intention-Based Semantics, in Lepore and Smith (2006, p. 255).

  21. Ziv (1988) has argued that relevance theory needs to be supplemented by a theory of rationality of causal relations, in other words, what in this paper has been called causal relevance (following Hitchcock 1992) and the assumption of a rational agent.

  22. “Disinformation” is misinformation purposefully conveyed to mislead the receiver into believing that it is information.

  23. This is consistent with the truth requirement established in Cohen (1994).

  24. I am summarising here a variety of questions and objections raised, with some consistency, at several meetings where I presented the ideas laid out in this article (for a complete list see the acknowledgments). I discussed with Fred Dretske the first objection during the 30th Wittgenstein Symposium. I am very grateful to Jeremy Seligman for having suggested the second objection and for our conversations about it, which greatly helped me to clarify the issue.

References

  • Aumann, R. J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. Annals of Statistics, 4(6), 1236–1239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1964). Language and information: Selected essays on their theory and application. Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y., & Carnap, R. (1953). An outline of a theory of semantic information. rep. in Bar-Hillel (1964).

  • Borlund, P. (2003). The concept of relevance in Ir. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 54(10), 913–925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, G. (1990). Propositional relevance. Informal Logic, 90, 65–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bremer, M., & Cohnitz, D. (2004). Information and information flow – An introduction. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choo, C. W., Detlor, B., & Turnbull, D. (2000). Web work: Information seeking and knowledge work on the world wide web. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1994). Some steps towards a general theory of relevance. Synthese, 101, 171–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colburn, T. R. (2000). Philosophy and computer science. Armonk: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, W. S. (1971). A definition of relevance for information retrieval. Information Storage and Retrieval, 7, 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cover, T. M., & Thomas, J. A. (1991). Elements of information theory. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crestani, F., Lalmas, M., Van Rijsbergen, C. J., & Campbell, I. (1998). Is this document relevant?… Probably: A survey of probabilistic models in information retrieval. ACM Computing Surveys, 30(4), 528–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delgrande, J. P., & Pelletier, J. (1998). A formal analysis of relevance. Erkenntnis, 49(2), 137–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, K. J. (1991). Logic and information. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodig-Crnkovic, G. (2005). System modeling and information semantics. In J. Bubenko, O. Eriksson, H. Fernlund, & M. Lind (Eds.), Proceedings of the Fifth Promote IT Conference, Borlänge, Sweden. Studentlitteratur: Lund.

  • Dodig-Crnkovic, G. (2006). Model validity and semantics of information. In L. Magnani (Ed.), Model-based reasoning. Science and engineering abduction, visualization, and simulation. London: King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dongen, S. V. (2006). Prior specification in Bayesian statistics: Three cautionary tales. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 242(1), 90–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. H. (2004). Information, misinformation, and disinformation. Minds and Machines, 14(2), 223–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2004a). Information. In L. Floridi (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information (pp. 40–61). Oxford, New York: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2004b). Outline of a theory of strongly semantic information. Minds and Machines, 14(2), 197–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2005a). Semantic conceptions of information. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/information-semantic/.

  • Floridi, L. (2005b). Is information meaningful data? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2006). The logic of being informed. Logique et Analyse, 49(196), 433–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L., & Sanders, J. W. (2004). The method of abstraction. In M. Negrotti (Ed.), Yearbook of the artificial-nature, culture and technology, models in contemporary sciences (pp. 177–220). Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaifman, H. (1988). A theory of higher-order probabilities. In B. Skyrms & W. Harper (Eds.), Causation, chance and credence. London, Ontario: University of Western Ontario Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1978). On the logic of relevance. Synthese, 37, 351–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greisdorf, H. (2000). “Relevance: An interdisciplinary and information science perspective. Informing Science, 3(2), 67–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J. (2003). Questions and answers: Semantics and logic. In R. Bernardi & M. Moortgat (Eds.), 2nd Colognet-Elsnet Symposium – Questions and answers: Theoretical and applied perspectives. Amsterdam: OTS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. (1968). Games with incomplete information played by “Bayesian” Players – Parts 1, 2, 3. Management Science, 14, 159–182, 320–134, 486–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Suppes, P. (Eds.) (1970). Information and inference. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. (1992). Relevance. Argumentation, 6(2), 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Israel, D., & Perry, J. (1990). What is information? In P. Hanson (Ed.), Information, language, and cognition. Vancouver: British Columbia Press.

  • Jones, D. S. (1979). Elementary information theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlas, J. (2003), Information algebras: Generic structures for inference. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakemeyer, G. (1997). Relevance from an epistemic perspective. Artificial Intelligence, 97(1–2), 137–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LePore, E., & Smith, B. C. (Eds.) (2006). The Oxford handbook of philosophy of language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J., & Hayes, P. J. (1969). Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence. In D. Michie & B. Meltzer (Eds.), Machine intelligence (pp. 463–502). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizzaro, S. (1996). Relevance: The whole (Hi)story. Technical Report UDMI/12/96/RR (Dec.) Dipartimento di Matematica e Informatica, Universita’ di Udine, Italy.

  • Moser, P. K. (2002). The Oxford handbook of epistemology. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polani, D., Martinetz, T., & Kim, J. T. (2001). An information-theoretic approach for the quantification of relevance. In J. Kelemen & P. Sosík (Eds.), Proceedings of the 6th European Conference on Advances in Artificial Life (pp. 704–713). Springer.

  • Polani, D., Nehaniv, C., Martinetz, T., & Kim, J. (2006). Relevant information in optimized persistence vs. progeny strategies. In L. Rocha, L. Yaeger, M. Bedau, D. Floreano, R. Goldstone, & A. Vespignani (Eds.), Artificial Life X: Proceedings of the Tenth International Conference on the Simulation and Synthesis of Living Systems (pp. 337–343). MIT.

  • Saracevic, T. (1970). The concept of “relevance” in information science: A historical review. In T. Saracevic (Ed.), Introduction to information science. New York: Bower Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroder, J. (1992). Korner’s criterion of relevance and analytic tableaux. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21(2), 183–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, A. (1970). Reflections on the problem of relevance. In R. M. Zaner (Ed.), Annotated, and with an introduction. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sequoiah-Grayson, S. forthcoming. The Metaphilosophy of Information. Minds and Machines.

  • Shannon, C. E., & Weaver, W. (1949, rep. 1998). The mathematical theory of communication. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1995), Relevance: Communication and cognition (2nd ed.). Malden: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1964). Identifying reference and truth-value.Theoria, 30, 96–118. Reprinted in P. Strawson, (1971). Logicolinguistic papers (pp. 75-95). London: Methuen.

  • Subramanian, D., Greiner, R., & Pearl, J. (1997). The relevance of relevance. Artificial Intelligence, 97(1–2), 1–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tishby, N., Pereira, F., & Bialek, W. (1999). The information bottleneck method. In B. Hajek & R. S. Sreenivas (Eds.), Proceedings of the 37th Annual Allerton Conference on Communication, Control and Computing (pp. 368–377). The University of Illinois.

  • Walton, D. N. (1991). Critical faults and fallacies of questioning. Journal of Pragmatics, 15, 337–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weingartner, P., & Schurz, G. (1986). Paradoxes solved by simple relevance criteria. Logique et Analyse, 29, 3–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D., & Sperber, D. (2004). Relevance theory. In L. R. Horn, & G. L. Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics (pp. 607–632). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yus, F. (2006). Relevance theory online bibliographic service. http://www.ua.es/personal/francisco.yus/rt.html.

  • Ziv, Y. (1988). On the rationality of “relevance” and the relevance of “rationality”. Journal of Pragmatics, 12, 535–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The first time I discussed the topic of a theory of epistemic relevance was during a talk I gave at the University of Regensburg (Regensburg, Germany 9 November 2005). I owe to Rainer Hammwoehner and Hans Rott not only the kind invitation but also the conceptual pressure that made me start working on this paper. A first version of the paper was then presented at the Department of Communication Science of the University of Salerno (Fisciano, Italy, 10 May 2006), and I wish to thank Roberto Cordeschi for that opportunity and the feedback I received in that occasion. The paper was further improved and discussed at the “Workshop on Information Theories”, organized by Juerg Kohlas and Giovanni Sommaruga at Fribourg University (Münchenwiler, Switzerland, 17–18 May 2006). They, the attendees, and especially Rolf Haenni and Jeremy Seligman provided some very helpful comments. A new version was the subject of an invited talk at the Department of Philosophy of the University of Siena (Siena, 14 June 2006), where I took advantage of a long discussion with Claudio Pizzi on secondorder probabilities. This led to a paper presented at a seminar organised by the Computer Science Department of Mälardalen University (Västerås, Sweden, September 2006), where I was kindly invited by Gordana Dodig Crnkovic. The discussion with the participants and especially with Gordana, Susan Stuart and Lars-Göran Johansson generated several improvements. The issue of hardwired questions was discussed there. The final version of the article then became the ISI Samuel Lazerow Memorial Lecture I delivered at the University of Arizona (Tucson, 8 February 2007). I am grateful to Don Fallis for the invitation and to the Research Group on the History and Philosophy of Information Access, the School of Information Resources and Library Science and The International Visitors Fund for the kind support. The last opportunity I had to discuss this paper was as an invited lecture at the 30th Wittgenstein Symposium and at the 48th Boston Colloquium for Philosophy of Science. Finally, I would like to acknowledge the help, useful comments and criticisms by Pia Borlund, Ken Herold, Karen Mather, Paul Oldfield and Federica Russo and the journal’s anonymous referees. As usual, all the aforementioned people are responsible only for the improvements and not for any remaining mistakes.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luciano Floridi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Floridi, L. Understanding Epistemic Relevance. Erkenn 69, 69–92 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9087-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9087-5

Keywords

Navigation