Skip to main content
Log in

Credible Worlds, Capacities and Mechanisms

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper asks how, in science in general and in economics in particular, theoretical models aid the understanding of real-world phenomena. Using specific models in economics and biology as test cases, it considers three alternative answers: that models are tools for isolating the ‘capacities’ of causal factors in the real world; that modelling is ‘conceptual exploration’ which ultimately contributes to the development of genuinely explanatory theories; and that models are credible counterfactual worlds from which inductive inferences can be made. The paper argues that the ‘credible worlds’ account captures significant aspects of scientific practice, even if many modellers see their work as conceptual exploration.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I now regret the passages in Sugden (2000, p. 12) in which I claim that the modelling strategies of Akerlof and Schelling are clearly realist.

  2. I say more about abduction in Sugden (2000, pp. 19–20). Following Mill (1843/1967, p. 186), I interpret ‘induction’ to include any mode of reasoning which takes us from specific propositions to more general ones. This makes abduction a sub-category of induction.

  3. As an economist, I have a natural interest in this particular branch of theoretical biology. However, it would be a mistake to think of this literature as importing into biology a modelling strategy from economics. Initially, game-theoretic modelling in biology and in economics developed independently of one another (see Maynard Smith 1982, p. 10). In the 1970s, most economists interpreted game theory as the analysis of strategic interaction between perfectly rational players. The evolutionary interpretation of game theory, now fashionable in economics, began as an import from biology, drawing heavily on the work of Maynard Smith and his collaborators (e.g. Sugden 1986).

  4. This issue is discussed by Maynard Smith (1982, pp. 4, 20–22).

  5. In MSP’s paper, this analysis is framed in terms of a different model of conflict, the “War of Attrition”; but the arguments apply with equal force to the Hawk–Dove game.

  6. Later, Maynard Smith (1982, pp. 85, 96) became aware of a few cases of what appear to be paradoxical ESSs in nature. He interprets the rarity of these cases as supporting the hypothesis that paradoxical ESSs are possible but unlikely.

  7. Cartwright (2009) is particularly uncompromising in her rejection of what she sees as ungrounded inductive arguments. Most commentators on Schelling’s model accept that the mechanism it exhibits is highly robust in the domain of models (see, for example, the literature survey in Aydinonat 2007). Cartwright disagrees, on the following grounds. Given Schelling’s basic assumption that individuals prefer not to live in neighbourhoods in which their own colour is significantly outnumbered, segregated neighbourhoods evolve; this result is robust to different specifications of the space in which they interact. But if instead we assume that individuals always prefer more integration to less and are indifferent between being in the majority and being in the minority, the resulting patterns of segregation or integration are different for different specifications of the space (Pancs and Vriend 2007). Since this latter assumption is wholly different from Schelling’s, and leads to a very different system of dynamics, I cannot see how Schelling’s conjectures are called into question.

  8. In this respect too, my approach is similar to Giere’s: see, e.g., Giere (1988, pp. 1–12, 22–28).

  9. I take Mäki (2009) to be using the concept of ‘isolation’ in this weaker sense when he says that, in his “MISS” account, models are depicted “in terms of isolations and idealisations”.

References

  • Akerlof, G. (1970). The market for ‘lemons’: Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, 488–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aydinonat, N. E. (2007). Models, conjectures and exploration: An analysis of Schelling’s checkerboard model of residential segregation. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14, 429–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, A. (1992). A simple model of herd behavior. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 797–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1998). Capacities. In J. Davis, W. Hands, & U. Mäki (Eds.), The handbook of economic methodology (pp. 45–48). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2002). The limits of causal order, from economics to physics. In U. Mäki (Ed.), Fact and fiction in economics (pp. 137–151). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2009). If no capacities then no credible worlds. But can models reveal capacities? Erkenntnis, this issue. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9136-8.

  • de Donato Rodríguez, X., & Zamora Bonilla, J. (2009). Credibility, idealisation, and model building: An inferential approach. Erkenntnis, this issue. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9139-5.

  • Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009). Learning from minimal economic models. Erkenntnis, this issue. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9138-6.

  • Hausman, D. (1992). The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (1992). On the method of isolation in economics. Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities, 26, 316–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (1994). Isolation, idealization and truth in economics. Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities, 38, 147–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2009). MISSing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, this issue. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9135-9.

  • Maynard Smith, J. (1974). The theory of games and the evolution of animal conflicts. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 47, 209–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J. (1982). Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Parker, G. (1976). The logic of asymmetric contests. Animal Behaviour, 24, 159–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Price, G. (1973). The logic of animal conflicts. Nature, London, 246, 15–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843/1967). A system of logic. London: Longman.

  • Morrison, M., & Morgan, M. (1999). Models as mediating instruments. In M. Morgan & M. Morrison (Eds.), Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science (pp. 10–37). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pancs, R., & Vriend, N. (2007). Schelling’s spatial proximity model of segregation revisited. Journal of Public Economics, 91, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pissarides, C. (1992). Loss of skill during unemployment and the persistence of employment shocks. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 1371–1391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (2006). Strategies of commitment and other essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1986). The economics of rights, co-operation and welfare. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Previous versions of this paper were presented at a symposium on economic models at the 2006 Philosophy of Science Association conference in Vancouver and at a workshop on “Models as Isolating Tools or as Credible Worlds?” at the University of Helsinki in 2008. I thank participants in those meetings, and Emrah Aydinonat and an anonymous referee, for comments. The idea of using Banerjee’s model as an illustration was suggested by Maya Elliott. My work was supported by the Economic and Social Research Council of the UK (award no. RES 051 27 0146).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Sugden.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sugden, R. Credible Worlds, Capacities and Mechanisms. Erkenn 70, 3–27 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-008-9134-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-008-9134-x

Keywords

Navigation