Skip to main content
Log in

Bearing the lightning of possible storms: Foucault’s experimental social criticism

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that Michel Foucault explicitly rejected the model of critique by which he is often understood—by both his defenders and detractors. Rather than justifying norms that could be said to represent “the people;” judging institutions, norms, and practices accordingly; and creating programs for others to enact, he theorized and practiced an experimental social criticism in which specific intellectuals help people work through “intolerable” situations by multiplying the ways they can think about and act upon them. As Foucault’s work with the prisons in France shows, one way intellectuals can be part of the experimental transformations social bodies carry out upon themselves is through genealogical work describing the ways problems have come to be identified—and can thus be transformed. This account of criticism undercuts the problem of justifying a standpoint of critique that has plagued philosophers and suggests a few concrete means of better aligning theory and practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Nancy Fraser (1985), Michael Walzer (1988), Gayatri Spivak (1988), and Jürgen Habermas (1990) argue that Foucault is uncritical because he forwards no universal norms. Walzer claims, for instance, “Foucault believes that discipline is a literal necessity; he abhors all its forms, every sort of confinement and control; liberalism for him is nothing more than discipline concealed. Since he cannot point to an alternative and better discipline, social criticism must always be a futile enterprise” (p. 204).

  2. Amy Allen (2003), Johanna Oksala (2005), and Eric Paras (2006) claim that Foucault embraced Enlightenment values in some form, if with some revision. Oksala writes, "By rooting his thought in the inheritance of the Enlightenment, he implicitly professed his faith in its values: the increase to autonomy among individuals and the importance of philosophy, that is, philosophy understood as critical thought. His writings on the Enlightenment can be read as a clear gesture of distancing himself from the utlra-relativist, neoconservative, and postmodern labels that had been stuck on him" (p. 183).

  3. I make use of Mitchell Dean's (1994, p. 119) distinction between “criticism” and “critique,” using the former to characterize Foucault's views and the latter for contrast, though this may seem arbitrary given Foucault's own use of the word in “What is Critique?” (2002; see also Butler 2002). I believe that the term “criticism” should help distinguish what Foucault is doing from Kantian Kritik, which is an intellectual or reflective and not experimental act. Foucault himself was not consistent on this question of terminology, though I do take it to be significant that the mature version of the essay, “What is Enlightenment?” (1997, pp. 303–319), uses “critique” to characterize Kant's work and ethos—an attitude, habit, or way of life—to describe his own.

  4. Besides Foucault, John Dewey articulated a theory and practice of criticism similar to the one I will describe through his term “reconstruction.” For instance, in a passage echoing Foucault's account of the specific intellectual, Dewey writes that the expert is not defined by her knowledge but is “one who has skill in making experiments to introduce an old meaning into different situations and who has a sensitive ear for detecting resultant harmonies and discords” (1988 [1925], p. 152). This kind of reconstruction is very similar to genealogical problematization, and, though he was not quite as comfortable in the archives as Foucault, Dewey did attempt some genealogical work, such as Liberalism and Social Action (1991 [1936]). See John Stuhr (1997) and VanderVeen (2010a) for more on the resonances between Dewey and Foucault.

  5. Foucault (2000, p. 288).

  6. Though it may seem that the language of “experimentation” entails a kind of scientism or objectivism of the kind Foucault would be wary, he says, “I am an experimenter and not a theorist” (2000, p. 240). He calls his texts “an ensemble of descriptive experiments still in basic outline” (1998, p. 310). And he asserts that the “historico-critical attitude must also be an experimental one” (1997, p. 316).

  7. Foucault (1977b, p. 206).

  8. Though Foucault does not use this term, I hope to show that it is a not implausible way of understanding Foucault’s work. In the preface to The Use of Pleasure, he explains that the book required an analysis not of “behaviors or ideas, nor societies and their ‘ideologies,' but the problematizations through which being offers itself to be, necessarily, thought—and the practices on the basis of which these problematizations are formed” (1990, p. 11). Since we are already operating on the basis of certain problematizations and practices, I will call the work of transforming conceptual frameworks “re-problematization” to be most clear.

  9. I am not at all arguing that critique should not have a standpoint, i.e., that it should be disinterested or universal. On the contrary, the purposes for doing intellectual work should be affirmed (see, e.g., Collins 2000). I am simply suggesting that the value of such work or the norms it expresses cannot be determined in theory. That is, whether or not a “critique” is critical is a function of its conditions and effects for certain purposes, such as helping certain people deal with an intolerable situation.

  10. Foucault (1997, p. 323).

  11. I take this term from Gayatri Spivak (1988). She argues that Foucault and Deleuze cannot conceptualize the economic interests that are truly representative of the people of developing countries. The term echoes the epistemological problem of developing criteria that distinguish between appearances that are representative of reality from those that are not, because both uses depend upon a dichotomy between reality and appearance. The experimental account that I will use Foucault to develop is an attempt to move past such a dichotomy and its consequent problems.

  12. Locke (1988 [1690]).

  13. Rawls (1999 [1971], p. 10).

  14. Habermas (1996a, b, p. 103).

  15. Rorty (1996, p. 334).

  16. Rorty (1989, p. 197).

  17. Walzer (1987, p. 32).

  18. Walzer (1988, p. 202).

  19. Rorty (1989, 1991, pp. 63–65).

  20. Habermas (1994, p. 154).

  21. Allen (2003, p. 191).

  22. Foucault (2000, p. 288).

  23. Foucault (2000, p. 127).

  24. Foucault (2000, p. 126).

  25. See Glucksmann (1992, pp. 336–339) and Thompson (2009). Though it may be an overstatement to say that a situation must be “intolerable” in order to evoke a response, the point is that there must be a stimulus to inquiry.

  26. Foucault (1997, p. 117).

  27. Foucault (2000, pp. 236, 288). I believe it is for this reason that Foucault connected problematization with askeseis for developing new ethe. Some commentators who have connected Foucault’s aesthetics, ethics, and criticism are Ladelle McWhorter (1999), Judith Butler (2002), Timothy O’Brien (2002), and Dianna Taylor (2003). See also Jane Addams’ Democracy and Social Ethics (2002 [1902]), which suggests that more democratic ways of life (ethe) can only occur through new experiments in living—not via governmental reform alone.

  28. Foucault (2000, p. 370).

  29. I will provide a more positive account of looking to effects in my discussion of Discipline and Punish. There I suggest that genealogy may turn purely theoretical debates over the purposes of penality towards an analysis of the norms and practices problematizations make possible.

  30. Foucault (1998, p. 441).

  31. Foucault (1997, pp. 114–115).

  32. Some of Foucault’s readers who prioritize his work on problematization include John Rajchman (1985), Paul Rabinow (2003), and Colin Koopman (2010).

  33. Foucault (1997, p. 118).

  34. Foucault (1990, p. 11).

  35. Foucault (2000, p. 288).

  36. Foucault (1977a, p. 31). Foucault's concept of genealogy borrows heavily from Nietzsche's work. See Nietzsche (1989, 1997) and Foucault (1998, pp. 369–392).

  37. Foucault (2000, pp. 215–220).

  38. Foucault (2000, p. 370).

  39. Foucault (1984, p. 88).

  40. Foucault (1997, p. 323).

  41. Foucault (1997, p. 325).

  42. The experimental question about, for example, John Rawls's work (1993, 1999), would not be whether or not he gives coherent or intuitive arguments—though this may be important—but when and how the concepts he invents are useful. We could then compare “the original position,” “reflective equilibrium,” or “the fact of reasonable pluralism” with, say, Deleuze and Guattari's “micropolitics,” “nomadology,” or “schizoanalysis” (1987) in ameliorating certain value conflicts. Despite—or perhaps because of—the tremendous differences between these philosophers, they have all contributed to the conceptual frameworks of many different fields of inquiry.

  43. Foucault (2000, p. 284).

  44. Foucault (1980, p. 396).

  45. I will not explore le Group d’information sur les prisons (GIP) or any of Foucault’s “activist” interventions, which seem to exemplify the specific intellectual. These well-known stories show one way of problematizing or re-problematizing the problems people face, and they notably involve the participation of non-philosophers, as in the GIP’s collection and dissemination of testimonials from prisoners. However, they are not useful for showing how intellectual work may itself problematize and thus potentially be part of a social body’s critical work upon itself. For more on the GIP, see Eribon (1991) and Foucault (1980, 2001).

  46. Foucault (1977a, pp. 272–278).

  47. Foucault (1977a, pp. 85–87, 278–280).

  48. Foucault (2000, p. 236).

  49. See, e.g., Walzer (1988), Habermas (1990), and Rorty (1991).

  50. In later interviews, Foucault often remarked that discipline, for example, is only one aspect of assujettissment and that Discipline and Punish may have been too one-sided on this issue. In describing the four technologies of subjectivization/objectivization—those of objects, sign systems, domination, and selves—he remarks, “Perhaps I've insisted too much on the technology of domination and power” (1997, p. 225; see also 1997, p. 177).

  51. Many of Foucault’s interpreters split his work into a number of parts—usually three—and then try to understand how these stages show a development in his thought. See Dreyfus and Rabinow (1983), Han (2002), and Paras (2006). If, on the contrary, we see his different methods as ways of taking part in experimental social criticism upon different problems, we need not figure out how to put the pieces back together again.

  52. Foucault (1977b, p. 208).

  53. Foucault (2000, pp. 242–243).

  54. Foucault (1977b, 206). To anticipate Spivak's objection (1988), Foucault and Deleuze do not deny that economic interests are often important. Foucault's account of the development of discipline, outlined above, is strongly tied to class issues. Foucault and Deleuzue simply become worried when all other interests are trumped by a single set of interests—whether they be economic or something else—and those who do not agree with the “experts” are said to be suffering from “ideology.” Instead, the two suggest that the differential effects of an economic problematization for those working to address a problem show its value, not the arguments of philosophers.

  55. Foucault (1997, p. 316).

  56. Dzur (2008). See also Frank Fischer (2000), who brings Foucault explicitly to the issue of expertise.

  57. VanderVeen (2010b).

  58. For a sampling of engagement literature, see Boyer (1990) and the 1999 report from the Kellogg Commission on the Future of State and Land-Grant Institutions.

References

  • Addams, Jane. 2002 [1902]. Democracy and social ethics. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

  • Allen, Amy. 2003. Foucault and the enlightenment: A critical reappraisal. Constellations 10 (2): 180–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, ErnestL. 1990. Scholarship reconsidered: Priorities of the professoriate. Princeton, NJ: The Carnegie Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2002. What is critique? An essay on Foucault’s virtue. In The political: Readings in continental philosophy, ed. David Ingram. London: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, PatriciaHill. 2000. Black feminist thought, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dean, Mitchell. 1994. Critical and effective histories: Foucault’s methods and historical sociology. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. 1987. A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia (trans: Brian Massumi). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Dewey, John. 1988 [1925]. Experience and nature: Later works, vol. 1, 1925. Carbondale: Southern Illinois Press.

  • Dewey, John. 1991 [1935]. Liberalism and social action. In Later works, vol. 11, 1935–1937. Carbondale: Southern Illinois Press.

  • Dreyfus, Hubert, and Paul Rabinow. 1983. Michel Foucault: Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dzur, Albert. 2008. Democratic professionalism: Citizen participation and the reconstruction of professional ethics, identity, and practice. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eribon, Didier. 1991. Michel Foucault (trans: Betsy Wing). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Fischer, Frank. 2000. Citizens, experts, and the environment: The politics of local knowledge. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1977a. Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison (trans: Alan Sheridan). New York: Vintage Books.

  • Foucault, Michel. 1977b. In Language, counter-memory, practice ed. Donald F. Bouchard. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Foucault, Michel. 1980. In Power/knowledge ed. Colin Gordon. New York: Pantheon.

  • Foucault, Michel. 1990. The use of pleasure: The history of sexuality, vol. 2. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1997. In Ethics: Subjectivity and truth ed. Paul Rabinow. New York: New Press.

  • Foucault, Michel. 1998. In Aesthetics, method, and epistemology ed. James D. Faubion. New York: New Press.

  • Foucault, Michel. 2000. In Power ed. James D. Faubion. New York: New Press.

  • Foucault, Michel. 2001. Manifest du GIP. In Dits et Écrits. 19541988, vol. I, 1954–1975 ed. Daniel Defert and François Ewald, 1042–1043. Paris: Gallimard.

  • Foucault, Michel. 2002. What is critique? In The political: Readings in continental philosophy, ed. David Ingram. London: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy. 1985. Michel Foucault: A young conservative? Ethics 96 (1): 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glucksmann, André. 1992. “Michel Foucault’s Nihilism.” Michel Foucault: Philosopher (trans: Timothy Armstrong). London: Routledge.

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy (trans: William Rehg). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1990. The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. “Taking aim at the heart of the present: On Foucault’s lecture on Kant’s What is enlightenment?” In Critique and power: Recasting the Foucault/Habermas Debate ed. Michael Kelly. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Han, Béatrice. 2002. Foucault’s critical project: Between the transcendental and the historical (trans: Edward Pile). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Kellogg Commission on the Future of State and Land-Grant Institutions. 1999. Returning to our roots: The engaged institution. Washington, DC: National Association of State Universities and Land-Grant Colleges.

  • Koopman, Colin. 2010. Historical critique or transcendental critique in Foucault: Two Kantian Lineages. Foucault Studies 8 February.

  • Locke, John. 1988 [1690]. Two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • McWhorter, Ladelle. 1999. Bodies and pleasures. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1989. On the genealogy of morals (trans: Walter Kaufmann). New York: Vintage.

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1997. In Untimely meditations ed. Danial Breazeale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • O’Brien, Timothy. 2002. Foucault and the art of ethics. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oksala, Johanna. 2005. Foucault on freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paras, Eric. 2006. Foucault 2.0. New York: Other Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabinow, Paul. 2003. Anthropos today: Reflections on modern equipment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rajchman, John. 1985. The freedom of Foucault. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999 [1971]. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, irony, solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1996. Does democracy need foundations? In Democracy and difference: Contesting the boundaries of the political ed. Seyla Benhabib. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Rorty, Richard. 1991. “Moral identity and private autonomy: The case of Foucault.” Essays on Heidegger and others. Philosophical papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. 1988. Can the Subaltern speak? In Marxism and the interpretation of culture ed. Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg, 271–313. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

  • Stuhr, John. 1997. Idols of the twilight: Pragmatism and postmodernism. Genealogical pragmatism. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Dianna. 2003. Practicing politics with Foucault and Kant: Towards a critical life. Philosophy and Social Criticism 29(3): 259–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Kevin. 2009. Intolerable: Foucault & the problem of political judgment. Society for phenomenology and existential philosophy annual conference, Arlington, VA.

  • VanderVeen, Zach. 2010a. John Dewey’s experimental politics: Inquiry and legitimacy. Peirce Society: Transactions of the Charles S.

    Google Scholar 

  • VanderVeen, Zach. 2010b. What makes media public? Dealing with ‘The current economic crisis.’ The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 24(2).

  • Walzer, Michael. 1988. The company of critics: Social criticism and political commitment in the twentieth century. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1987. Interpretation and social criticism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank John Stuhr, Charles Scott, José Medina, Noellë McAfee, Brooke Ackerly, Matt Whitt, Erin C. Tarver, Colin Koopman, and two anonymous reviewers for providing comments on previous versions of this paper. I have also benefited from the support of the Kettering Foundation and my colleagues there, especially Randy Nielsen, Derek Barker, Dana Walker, and David Matthews. Finally, I am grateful to Jeff Edmonds for our ongoing conversations and his generosity in reviewing my work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zach VanderVeen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

VanderVeen, Z. Bearing the lightning of possible storms: Foucault’s experimental social criticism. Cont Philos Rev 43, 467–484 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-010-9160-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-010-9160-7

Keywords

Navigation