Skip to main content
Log in

The extended mind: born to be wild? A lesson from action-understanding

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The extended mind hypothesis (Clark and Chalmers in Analysis 58(1):7–19, 1998; Clark 2008) is an influential hypothesis in philosophy of mind and cognitive science. I argue that the extended mind hypothesis is born to be wild. It has undeniable and irrepressible tendencies of flouting grounding assumptions of the traditional information-processing paradigm. I present case-studies from social cognition which not only support the extended mind proposal but also bring out its inherent wildness. In particular, I focus on cases of action-understanding and discuss the role of embodied intentionality in the extended mind project. I discuss two theories of action-understanding for exploring the support for the extended mind hypothesis in embodied intersubjective interaction, namely, simulation theory and a non-simulationist perceptual account. I argue that, if the extended mind adopts a simulation theory of action-understanding, it rejects representationalism. If it adopts a non-simulationist perceptual account of action-understanding, it rejects the classical sandwich view of the mind.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The extended mind hypothesis I shall consider in this paper is not concerned with providing a definition of the mind or a mark of the mental. I shall follow Clark’s (2008) and Chalmers’ (2008) pragmatic insight that where one sets the boundaries of the mind is largely a matter of what one wants to explain. This paper is also not concerned with metaphysical views which challenge the division between the mind and the world and stress their co-emergence (Thompson 2007; Zahavi 2008). I shall follow the original hypothesis of the extended mind theorists (Clark and Chalmers 1998) that some cases of ongoing agent–environment interaction qualify as cognitive processes in their own right even if they are not conducted entirely “in the head” and thus an account of mental states need not be radically neurocentric.

  2. “Embodied intentionality” refers to the kind of intentionality that characterises our skilful bodily coping with the world. Much contemporary discussion of embodied intentionality is inspired by Merleau-Ponty’s (2002) idea of “motor intentionality”. He writes, “...my body appears to me as an attitude directed towards a certain existing or possible task.” (p.114). Again, “…the recognition of something between movement as a third person process and thought as a representation of movement- something which is an anticipation of, or arrival at, the objective and is ensured by the body itself as a motor power, a “motor project”…a “motor intentionality”….”(pp.126-127).

  3. Theory–theory approaches to mind-reading (Gopnik and Wellman 1994; Baron-Cohen 1995) fall outside the scope of the present paper because they primarily focus on how we attribute propositional attitudes to others rather than how we understand the other’s embodied intentionality.

  4. The purpose of the present discussion is not to evaluate the respective explanatory advantages of the simulationist and the non-simulationist perceptual accounts of action-understanding. The goal is to explore whether either account of action-understanding fares any better than the other in keeping the extended mind hypothesis in line with the assumptions of the traditional information-processing paradigm.

  5. Some authors argue that understanding embodied engagement is ontogenetically the most primitive form of social cognition (Trevarthen 1998; Meltzoff and Moore 1998; Reddy and Morris 2004). It is an open empirical question whether or not our most primitive understanding of others is in terms of their embodied intentionality. However, embodied engagement, like gesturing and facial expressions, continues to play a vital role in adult intersubjective interactions.

  6. The parity principle states “If, as we confront some task, a part of the world functions as a process which, were it done in the head, we would have no hesitation in recognizing as part of the cognitive process, then that part of the world is . . . part of the cognitive process.” (Clark and Chalmers 1998, 29)

  7. This paper is neutral with regard to the question whether or not some mental states are such that they cannot, in principle, be enabled in the absence of coupling with the extra-cranial world. It follows Clark and Chalmer’s (1998) moderate principle of extending the mind into the extra-cranial world, namely, the parity principle as stated in footnote 6. The present paper claims that certain embodied intersubjective interactions satisfy the requirements of an extended cognitive system based on the parity principle. To this end, the removal of the “external components” like gestures and facial expressions is viewed as leading to a drop in the behavioural competence of the agent whose mental state is enabled rather than as a statement about the inadequacy of purely neural processes to generate the mental states in question.

  8. Hurley (2010) maintains that the causal-constitutive debate is a non-starter and dubs the debate “the causal-constitutive error”. The dynamical systems influence on the shared circuits model seems to motivate Hurley’s rejection of the debate.

  9. The best way to ensure that dynamical systems explanations do not creep into a simulationist interpretation of action-understanding is by describing the functioning of the simulationist mechanisms as not grounded in ongoing sensorimotor feedback. In other words, the simulationist system is to be taken “offline” for inputs. Instead of grounding the function of the system on actual ongoing sensorimotor input from the world it is grounded in counterfactual inputs internally generated by the system. When such an offline system is coupled with appropriate “controls”, which enable the brain to distinguish between actions of self and others, it results in a simulation theory of action-understanding that does not necessarily refer to ongoing sensorimotor feedback. However, combining offline simulation with internal controls as the building blocks of action-understanding encourages a significantly internalist picture of the mind. The process of action-understanding can be run entirely on internal models and corresponds to the emulation theory described by Grush (2003, 2004). Grush (2003) describes the internal offline process in detail in an article appropriately titled “In Defense of Some ‘Cartesian’ Assumptions Concerning the Brain and Its Operation.”

  10. In the context of action-understanding as simulation, whether an adequate functioning of mirroring mechanisms of the brain can be achieved by a wholly neural route is an open empirical question. However, this does not prevent an account from construing the mechanism of simulation, in principle, as offline processing enabled by a fully internal route, as for example, in Grush’s account. On such a reading of simulationist mechanisms of action-understanding, vehicle externalism is unable to make use of the instances of embodied intersubjectivity which would otherwise support it. In a purely “offline” description of action-understanding as simulation the mechanism that drives one’s mental state of grasping the other’s embodied intentionality is purely neural.

  11. Gallagher and colleagues (De Jaegher et al. 2010) have recently proposed an “Interaction theory” of social cognition. The present paper is, however, concerned with the particular theory of perceptual understanding of the other’s embodied intentionality as elaborated by Gallagher (2008) and Gallagher and Zahavi (2008) and the implications of a perceptual non-simulationist account of action-understanding for the extended mind hypothesis.

  12. It is to be noted that action-oriented theories differ among themselves on many important details, for example, on the notion of “action” (Noë 2010; Gangopadhyay & Kiverstein 2009).

  13. Peripersonal space is the space surrounding the body of the agent where the agent can interact with objects (including other bodies) at the present moment without bodily displacement. Extrapersonal space is the space lying outside the zone of the embodied agent’s immediate interaction and requiring bodily displacement for future interactions.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The Bounds of Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. (2007). Understanding the embodiment of perception. Journal of Philosophy. CIV(1): 5–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alač, M., & Hutchins, E. (2004). I see what you are saying: Action as cognition in fMRI Brain Mapping Practice. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 4(3), 629–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beers, R. D. (2000). Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends Cog Sci, 4(3), 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2005). Review of Alva Noë, Action in Perception. J Philosophy, 102, 259–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calder, A. J., Keane, J., Manes, F., Antoun, N., & Young, A. W. (2000). Impaired recognition and experience of disgust following brain injury. Nat Neurosci, 3(11), 1077–1078.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2008). Preface. In A. Clark, Supersizing the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philos Sci, 75(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2004). Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Vision as Dance? Three Challenges for Sensorimotor Contingency Theory. Psyche. 12 (1)

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2009). Perception, action and experience: Unraveling the golden braid. Neuropsychologia, 47, 1460–1468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Grush, R. (1999). Towards a cognitive robotics. Adaptive Behavior., 7(1), 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing Without Representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (2001). Sensorimotor chauvinism. Behav Brain Sci, 24(5), 979–980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J. (1998). About Face. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J. (2001). Empathy needs a face. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 51–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J. (2009). Impaired embodiment and intersubjectivity. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, http://www.springerlink.com/content/q078452405721853

  • De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends Cog Sci, 14(10), 441–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delevoye-Turrell, Y., Bartolo, A., & Coello, Y. (2010). Motor representations and the perception of space: perceptual judgments of the boundary of action space. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness (pp. 217–242). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, E., & Markman, A. (2003). Discrete thoughts: Why cognition must use discrete representations. Mind Lang., 18, 95–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Findlay, J. M., & Gilchrist, I. D. (2003). Active vision: The psychology of looking and seeing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Inference or interaction: Social cognition without precursors. Philo Explor, 11(3), 163–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2005). Embodied simulation: From neurons to phenomenal experience. Phenom Cogn Sci, 4, 23–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2004). Intentional Attunement. The Mirror Neuron system and its role in interpersonal relations.http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/1/15#_15

  • Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Keysers, C., & Rizzolatti, G. (2004). A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends Cogn Sci, 8, 396–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangopadhyay, N. (2010). Experiential blindness revisited: In defence of a case of embodied cognition. Cog Sys Res, 11, 396–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangopadhyay, N., & Kiverstein, J. (2009). Enactivism and the unity of perception and action. Topoi, 28(1), 63–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garzón, F. C. (2008). Towards a general theory of antirepresentationalism. BJ Philo Sci., 59, 259–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1977). The Theory of Affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, Acting, and Knowing: Toward an Ecological Psychology (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. (1994). The Theory-Theory. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture (pp. 257–293). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biol Philos, 18, 53–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: motor control, imagery, and perception. Behav Brain Sci, 27, 377–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in Action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2001). Perception and Action: Alternative views. Synthese, 129, 3–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2008). The shared circuits model: How control, mirroring and simulation can enable imitation and mindreading. Behav Brain Sci, 31, 1–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2010). The Varieties of Externalism. In R. Menary (Ed.), The Extended Mind (pp. 101–154). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P., & de Vignemont, F. (2010). Spatial coordinates and phenomenology in the two-visual systems model. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness (pp. 125–144). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic Patterns. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J. (2010). Sensorimotor knowledge and the contents of experience. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness (pp. 257–274). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1986). Visualization and cognition: Thinking with eyes and hands. Know Soc, 6, 1–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. New York: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, D. (1995). Hand and Mind: What Gestures reveal about Thought. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, D. (2005). Gesture and Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of Perception (Routledge Classics). Translated by C.Smith. New York: Routledge

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates. Science, 198, 74–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1998). Infant intersubjectivity: broadening the dialogue to include imitation, identity and intention. In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 47–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1995). Infants’ understanding of people and things: from body imitation to folk psychology. In J. L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel, & N. Eilan (Eds.), The Body and the Self (pp. 43–69). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2010). Cortical visual systems for perception and action. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness (pp. 71–94). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mojzisch, A., Schilbach, L., Pannasch, S., Helmert, J. R., Velichkovsky, B. M., & Vogeley, K. (2006). The effects of self-involvement on attention, arousal, and facial expression during social interaction with virtual others: a psychophysiological study. Soc Neurosci, 1, 184–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2010). Vision without representation. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness (pp. 245–256). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav Brain Sci, 24(5), 883–917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (1999). Pre-linguistic communication. In M. Barrett (Ed.), The Development of Language (pp. 25–50). London: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V., & Morris, P. (2004). Participants don’t need theories: Knowing minds in engagement. Theory and Psychology, 14(5), 647–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossi, M. (2004). Internalist and externalist interpretations of the mirror systems: How to avoid foundational inconsistency in the Theory of Embodied Simulation? http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/1/15#_15

  • Rowlands, M. (2006). Sensorimotor Activity. Psyche 12 (1)

  • Schilbach, L., Eickhoff, S. B., Mojzisch, A., & Vogeley, K. (2008). What’s in a smile? Neural correlates of facial embodiment during social interaction. Soc Neurosci, 3(1), 37–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Enactive understanding and motor intentionality. In F. Morganti, A. Carassa, & G. Riva (Eds.), Enacting Intersubjectivity: A Cognitive and Social Perspective on the Study of Interactions (pp. 17–32). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spivey, M. J. (2007). The Continuity of Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Belknap-Harvard University Press.

  • Trevarthen, C. (1985). Facial expressions of emotion in mother-infant interaction. Hum Neurobiol, 4, 21–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1998). The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity. In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 15–46). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., & Reddy, V. (2007). Consciousness in infants. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), A Companion to Consciousness (pp. 41–57). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? J. Philos. XCI, 345–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1998). The Dynamical Hypothesis in Cognitive Science. Behav Brain Sci, 21, 615–665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M., & Clark, A. (1999). Genic representation: reconciling content andcausal complexity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(1), 103–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2010). Extended Vision. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness (pp. 277–289). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2008). Internalism, Externalism, and Transcendental Idealism. Synthese, 160(3), 355–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nivedita Gangopadhyay.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gangopadhyay, N. The extended mind: born to be wild? A lesson from action-understanding. Phenom Cogn Sci 10, 377–397 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9198-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9198-y

Keywords

Navigation