Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Public Choice 1-2/2016

04.07.2016

Two types of participation failure under nine voting methods in variable electorates

verfasst von: Dan S. Felsenthal, Hannu Nurmi

Erschienen in: Public Choice | Ausgabe 1-2/2016

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper expands the illustration and analysis regarding the susceptibility of nine voting procedures to two types of what are generally known as No-Show paradoxes. Following the article by Felsenthal and Tideman (Theory and Decision 75:59–77, 2013), the two paradoxes are denoted as P-TOP and P-BOT paradoxes. According to the P-TOP paradox it is possible that if candidate x has been elected by a given electorate then, ceteris paribus, another candidate, y, may be elected if additional voters join the electorate who rank x at the top of their preference ordering. Similarly, according to the P-BOT paradox it is possible that if candidate y has not been elected by a given electorate then, ceteris paribus, y may be elected if additional voters join the electorate who rank y at the bottom of their preference ordering. Voting procedures that are susceptible to these paradoxes are considered to be afflicted with a particularly serious defect because instead of encouraging voters to participate in an election and vote according to their true preference orderings, they may inhibit voters from participating in an election and thereby undermine the rationale for conducting elections.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
Following Moulin (1988, p. 56) we define a voting procedure to be Condorcet-consistent if it elects the Condorcet winner when one exists. This definition differs from Fishburn’s (1977, p. 482) definitions of moderate and weak Condorcet-consistency. A Condorcet winner—named after the Frenchman Marquis de Condorcet, who called this candidate ‘the majority candidate’ —is the candidate whom the majority of the voters prefer over each of the other alternatives in pairwise comparisons. Condorcet thought that if such a candidate exists s/he ought to be elected.
 
2
The Twin paradox (Moulin 1988, p. 59) is a special version of the No-Show paradox. Two voters having the same preference ordering may obtain a preferable outcome if, ceteris paribus, one of them decides not to participate in the election while the other votes sincerely according to his preference ordering. The Twin paradox implies the No-Show paradox.
 
3
The five voting methods investigated by Felsenthal and Tideman (2013) were the Plurality with Runoff, Alternative Vote, Coombs, Nanson, and Dodgson methods. The first three methods are non-Condorcet-consistent and the last two are Condorcet-consistent. “Moving x up” means that all candidates other than x are in the same order after the change as before: all candidates initially below x remain below x after the change, and one or more candidates that were initially above x are below x after the change.
 
4
In the sequel we use a slightly revised definition for illustrating the P-TOP and P-BOT paradoxes under Schwartz’s procedure where multiple winners exist either in the original electorate or in the enlarged electorate.
 
5
However, it is unclear how a tie between two candidates, say a and b, ought to be broken under Bucklin’s procedure when both a and b are supported in the same counting round by the same number of voters and this number constitutes a majority of the voters. If one tries to break the tie between a and b in such an eventuality by performing the next counting round in which all other candidates are also allowed to participate, then it is possible that the number of (cumulated) votes of another candidate, c, will exceed that of a and b.
To see this, consider the following simple example. Suppose there are 18 voters who must elect one candidate under Bucklin’s procedure and whose preference orderings among four candidates, a, b, c, d, are as follows: seven voters with preference ordering a > b > c > d, eight voters with preference ordering b > a > c > d, one voter with preference ordering d > c > a > b, and two voters with preference ordering d > c > b > a. None of the candidates constitutes the top preference of a majority of the voters. However, both a and b constitute the top or second preference of a majority of voters (15). If one tries to break the tie between a and b by performing the next (third) counting round in which c and d also are allowed to participate, then c will be elected (with 18 votes), but if only a and b are allowed to participate in this counting round then b will be elected (with 17 votes).
So which candidate ought to be elected in this example under Bucklin’s procedure? As far as we know, Bucklin did not supply an answer to this question.
 
6
Young (1977, p. 349) prefers to call this procedure ‘The Minimax function’. It is also sometimes called in the literature ‘the max–min method’.
 
7
Borda’s Count (Borda 1784; Black 1958) is a voting procedure that was proposed by Jean Charles de Borda in a paper he delivered in 1770 before the French Royal Academy of Sciences entitled ‘Memorandum on election by ballot’ (‘Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin’). According to Borda’s procedure, each candidate x gets no points for each voter who ranks x last in his preference ordering, 1 point for each voter who ranks x second-to-last in his preference order, and so on, and m-1 points for each voter who ranks x first in his preference order (where m is the number of candidates). Thus, if all n voters have linear preference orderings among the m candidates then the total number of points obtained by all candidates is equal to the number of voters multiplied by the number of paired comparisons, i.e., nm(m-1)/2.
 
8
Tideman (2006, pp. 187–189) proposes two heuristic procedures that simplify the need to examine all m! preference orderings.
 
9
According to Kemeny (1959), the distance between two (individual) preference orderings, R and R′, is the number of pairs of candidates (alternatives) on which they differ. For example, if R = a > b > c > d and R′ = d > a > b > c, then the distance between R and R’ is 3, because they agree on three pairs [(a > b), (a > c), (b > c)], but differ on the remaining three pairs, i.e., on the preference ordering between a and d, b and d, and between c and d. Similarly, if R′′ is c > d > a > b, then the distance between R and R′′ is 4 and the distance between R’ and R′′ is 3. According to Kemeny’s procedure, the most likely social preference ordering is that R such that the sum of distances of the voters’ preference orderings from R is minimized. Because this R has the properties of the median central tendency in statistics it is called the median preference ordering. The median preference ordering (but not the mean preference ordering, which is that R which minimizes the sum of the squared differences between R and the voters’ preference orderings) will be identical to the possible (transitive) social preference ordering W which maximizes the sum of voters that agree with all paired comparisons implied by W.
 
10
When the notation a > b is used in the following examples with respect to a voter it means that the voter ranks candidate a ahead of candidate b. When it is used with respect to a set of voters, it means that the majority of the voters rank a ahead of b. Similarly, when the notation a ~ b is used with respect to a set of voters, it means that half the voters prefer a to b and half the voters prefer b to a.
 
11
This statement is inaccurate. Felsenthal and Tideman (2013) have demonstrated that two of the well-known Condorcet-consistent procedures that they studied (Dodgson’s and Nanson’s), are vulnerable to the P-TOP paradox but not also to the P-BOT paradox.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2007a). A theory of measuring, electing and ranking. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America (PNAS), 104, 8720–8725.CrossRef Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2007a). A theory of measuring, electing and ranking. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America (PNAS), 104, 8720–8725.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2007b). Election by majority judgement: Experimental evidence, (mimeograph). Paris: Ecole Polytechnique, Centre National De La Recherche Scientifique, Laboratoire D’Econommetrie, Cahier No. 2007–28. http://tinyurl.com/65q6cg. Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2007b). Election by majority judgement: Experimental evidence, (mimeograph). Paris: Ecole Polytechnique, Centre National De La Recherche Scientifique, Laboratoire D’Econommetrie, Cahier No. 2007–28. http://​tinyurl.​com/​65q6cg.
Zurück zum Zitat Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2011). Majority judgment: Measuring, ranking, and electing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRef Balinski, M., & Laraki, R. (2011). Majority judgment: Measuring, ranking, and electing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Borda, J. C. de (1784 [1995]). Mémoires sur les élections au scrutin. In Histoire de l'academie royale des sciences année (pp. 651–665). (Reprinted from Classics of social choice, pp. 83–89, by I. McLean & A. B. Urken, Eds., 1995, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press). Borda, J. C. de (1784 [1995]). Mémoires sur les élections au scrutin. In Histoire de l'academie royale des sciences année (pp. 651–665). (Reprinted from Classics of social choice, pp. 83–89, by I. McLean & A. B. Urken, Eds., 1995, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press).
Zurück zum Zitat Copeland, A. H. (1951). A ‘reasonable’ social welfare function, mimeographed. University of Michigan, Department of Mathematics, Seminar on Applications of Mathematics to the Social Sciences. Copeland, A. H. (1951). A ‘reasonable’ social welfare function, mimeographed. University of Michigan, Department of Mathematics, Seminar on Applications of Mathematics to the Social Sciences.
Zurück zum Zitat Farquharson, R. (1969). Theory of voting. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Farquharson, R. (1969). Theory of voting. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Felsenthal, D. S. (2012). Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: Paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures (pp. 19–91). Berlin: Springer.CrossRef Felsenthal, D. S. (2012). Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: Paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures (pp. 19–91). Berlin: Springer.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (2008). The majority judgement voting procedure: A critical evaluation. Homo Oeconomicus, 25, 319–333. Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (2008). The majority judgement voting procedure: A critical evaluation. Homo Oeconomicus, 25, 319–333.
Zurück zum Zitat Felsenthal, D. S., & Tideman, N. (2013). Varieties of failure of monotonicity and participation under five voting methods. Theory and Decision, 75, 59–77.CrossRef Felsenthal, D. S., & Tideman, N. (2013). Varieties of failure of monotonicity and participation under five voting methods. Theory and Decision, 75, 59–77.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn, P. C. (1977). Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, 33, 469–489.CrossRef Fishburn, P. C. (1977). Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, 33, 469–489.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn, P. C. (1982). Monotonicity paradoxes in the theory of elections. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 4, 119–134.CrossRef Fishburn, P. C. (1982). Monotonicity paradoxes in the theory of elections. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 4, 119–134.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn, P. C., & Brams, S. J. (1983). Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56, 207–214.CrossRef Fishburn, P. C., & Brams, S. J. (1983). Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56, 207–214.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hoag, C. G., & Hallett, G. H. (1926). Proportional representation. New York: The Macmillan Co. Hoag, C. G., & Hallett, G. H. (1926). Proportional representation. New York: The Macmillan Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Kemeny, J. G. (1959). Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus, 88, 577–591. Kemeny, J. G. (1959). Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus, 88, 577–591.
Zurück zum Zitat Kemeny, J., & Snell, I. (1960). Mathematical models in the social sciences. Boston: Ginn. Kemeny, J., & Snell, I. (1960). Mathematical models in the social sciences. Boston: Ginn.
Zurück zum Zitat Kramer, G. H. (1977). A dynamical model of political equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 310–333.CrossRef Kramer, G. H. (1977). A dynamical model of political equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 310–333.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Meredith, J. C. (1913). Proportional representation in Ireland. Dublin: E. Ponsonby Ltd. Meredith, J. C. (1913). Proportional representation in Ireland. Dublin: E. Ponsonby Ltd.
Zurück zum Zitat Moulin, H. (1988). Condorcet’s principle implies the No-Show paradox. Journal of Economic Theory, 45, 53–64.CrossRef Moulin, H. (1988). Condorcet’s principle implies the No-Show paradox. Journal of Economic Theory, 45, 53–64.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pérez, J. (2001). The strong no-show paradoxes are a common flaw in Condorcet voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 18, 601–616.CrossRef Pérez, J. (2001). The strong no-show paradoxes are a common flaw in Condorcet voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 18, 601–616.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Richelson, J. T. (1978). A comparative analysis of social choice functions, III. Behavioral Science, 23, 169–176.CrossRef Richelson, J. T. (1978). A comparative analysis of social choice functions, III. Behavioral Science, 23, 169–176.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schwartz, T. (1972). Rationality and the myth of the maximum. Noûs, 6, 97–117.CrossRef Schwartz, T. (1972). Rationality and the myth of the maximum. Noûs, 6, 97–117.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schwartz, T. (1986). The logic of collective choice. New York: Columbia University Press. Schwartz, T. (1986). The logic of collective choice. New York: Columbia University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Simpson, P. B. (1969). On defining areas of voter choice: Professor Tullock on stable voting. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 83, 478–490.CrossRef Simpson, P. B. (1969). On defining areas of voter choice: Professor Tullock on stable voting. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 83, 478–490.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Tideman, N. (2006). Collective decisions and voting: The potential for public choice. Aldershot, Hampshire, England: Ashgate Publishing Ltd. Tideman, N. (2006). Collective decisions and voting: The potential for public choice. Aldershot, Hampshire, England: Ashgate Publishing Ltd.
Zurück zum Zitat Young, H. P. (1977). Extending Condorcet’s rule. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 335–353.CrossRef Young, H. P. (1977). Extending Condorcet’s rule. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 335–353.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Young, H. P. (1988). Condorcet’s theory of voting. American Political Science Review, 82, 1231–1244.CrossRef Young, H. P. (1988). Condorcet’s theory of voting. American Political Science Review, 82, 1231–1244.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Young, P. (1995). Optimal voting rules. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9, 51–63.CrossRef Young, P. (1995). Optimal voting rules. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9, 51–63.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Young, H. P., & Levenglick, A. (1978). A consistent extension of Condorcet’s principle. SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, 35, 283–300.CrossRef Young, H. P., & Levenglick, A. (1978). A consistent extension of Condorcet’s principle. SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, 35, 283–300.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Two types of participation failure under nine voting methods in variable electorates
verfasst von
Dan S. Felsenthal
Hannu Nurmi
Publikationsdatum
04.07.2016
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Choice / Ausgabe 1-2/2016
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-016-0352-5

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1-2/2016

Public Choice 1-2/2016 Zur Ausgabe