Skip to main content
Log in

A tractable method to measure utility and loss aversion under prospect theory

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper provides an efficient method to measure utility under prospect theory. Our method minimizes both the number of elicitations required to measure utility and the cognitive burden for subjects, being based on the elicitation of certainty equivalents for two-outcome prospects. We applied our method in an experiment and were able to replicate the main findings on prospect theory, suggesting that our method measures what it is intended to. Our data confirmed empirically that risk seeking and concave utility can coincide under prospect theory. Utility did not depend on the probability used in the elicitation, which offers support for the validity of prospect theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The idea of simultaneously estimating decision weights and utility was also recently used by Viscusi and Evans (2006).

References

  • Abdellaoui, Mohammed. (2000). “Parameter-Free Elicitation of Utility and Probability Weighting Functions,” Management Science 46, 1497–1512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, Mohammed, Aurélien Baillon, and Peter P. Wakker. (2007). “Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes towards Uncertainty,” Working Paper, Erasmus University.

  • Abdellaoui, Mohammed, Carolina Barrios, and Peter P. Wakker. (2007). “Reconciling Introspective Utility with Revealed Preference: Experimental Arguments Based on Prospect Theory,” Journal of Econometrics 138, 356–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, Mohammed, Han Bleichrodt, and Corina Paraschiv. (2007). “Measuring Loss Aversion under Prospect Theory: A Parameter-Free Approach,” Management Science 53, 1659–1674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, Steffen, Glenn Harrison, Morten Lau, and E. Elisabet Rutström. (2007). “Behavioral Econometrics for Psychologists,” Journal of Economic Psychology (forthcoming).

  • Baucells, Manel and Antonio Villasis. (2006). “Stability of Risk Preferences and the Reflection Effect of Prospect Theory,” Working Paper, IESE.

  • Beattie, Jane, and Graham Loomes. (1997). “The Impact of Incentives upon Risky Choice Experiments,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 14, 155–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benartzi, Shlomo, and Richard H. Thaler. (1995). “Myopic Loss Aversion and the Equity Premium Puzzle,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 110, 73–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, Han, and Jose L. Pinto. (2000). “A Parameter-Free Elicitation of the Probability Weighting Function in Medical Decision Analysis,” Management Science 46, 1485–1496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, Han, Jose L. Pinto, and Peter P. Wakker. (2001). “Making Descriptive Use of Prospect Theory to Improve the Prescriptive Use of Expected Utility,” Management Science 47, 1498–1514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Booij, Adam S. and Gijs van de Kuilen. (2007). “A Parameter-Free Analysis of the Utility of Money for the General Population under Prospect Theory,” Working Paper, University of Amsterdam.

  • Bostic, Raphael, R. J. Herrnstein, and R. Duncan Luce. (1990). “The Effect on the Preference Reversal of Using Choice Indifferences,” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 13, 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin F., and Robin M. Hogarth. (1999). “The Effects of Financial Incentives in Experiments: A Review and Capital–Labor–Production Framework,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 19, 7–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, Alain, and Michèle Cohen. (1994). “Risk Seeking with Diminishing Marginal Utility in a Non-Expected Utility Model,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 9, 77–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt, Robin, Chris Starmer, and Robert Sugden. (1998). “On the Validity of the Random Lottery Incentive System,” Experimental Economics 1, 115–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diecidue, Enrico, and Wakker, Peter P. (2001). “On the Intuition of Rank-Dependent Utility,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Springer 23(3), 281–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchart-Vincent, Nathalie and Olivier l’Haridon. (2008). “Monetary Incentives in the Loss Domain: An Experimental Comparison of Three Rewarding Schemes Including Real Losses,” Working Paper, HEC Business School.

  • Farquhar, Peter. (1984). “Utility Assessment Methods,” Management Science 30, 1283–1300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fennema, Hein, and Marcel van Assen. (1998). “Measuring the Utility of Losses by Means of the Trade-Off Method,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 17, 277–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, Richard, and George Wu. (1999). “On the Form of the Probability Weighting Function,” Cognitive Psychology 38, 129–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gul, Faruk. (1991). “A Theory of Disappointment Aversion,” Econometrica 59, 667–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, Chip, Steven Huddart, and Mark Lang. (1999). “Psychological Factors and Stock Option Exercise,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 114, 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hershey, J. C., and Paul J. H. Schoemaker. (1985). “Probability versus Certainty Equivalence Methods in Utility Measurement: Are They Equivalent?” Management Science 31, 1213–1231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt, Charles A., and Susan K. Laury. (2002). “Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects,” American Economic Review 92, 1644–1655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk,” Econometrica 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köbberling, Veronika, and Peter P. Wakker. (2005). “An Index of Loss Aversion,” Journal of Economic Theory 122, 119–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laughhunn, Dan J., John W. Payne, and Roy Crum. (1980). “Managerial Risk Preferences for Below-Target Returns,” Management Science 26, 1238–1249.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCord, Mark, and Richard de Neufville. (1986). “Lottery Equivalents: Reduction of the Certainty Effect Problem in Utility Assessment,” Management Science 32, 56–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myagkov, Mikhail, and Charles R. Plott. (1997). “Exchange Economies and Loss Exposure: Experiments Exploring Prospect Theory and Competitive Equilibria in Market Environments,” American Economic Review 87, 801–828.

    Google Scholar 

  • Payne, John W., Dan J. Laughhunn, and Roy Crum. (1980). “Translation of Gambles and Aspiration Level Effects in Risky Choice Behavior,” Management Science 26, 1039–1060.

    Google Scholar 

  • Payne, John W., Dan J. Laughhunn, and Roy Crum. (1981). “Further Tests of Aspiration Level Effects in Risky Choice Behavior,” Management Science 27, 953–958.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, Matthew. (2000). “Risk Aversion and Expected-Utility Theory: A Calibration Theorem,” Econometrica 68, 1281–1292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, Leonard J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoemaker, Paul J.H. (1990). “Are Risk-Attitudes Related Across Domains and Response Modes?” Management Science 36, 1451–1463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris. (2000). “Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk,” Journal of Economic Literature 28, 332–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris, and Robert Sugden. (1991). “Does the Random-Lottery Incentive System Elicit True Preferences? An Experimental Investigation,” American Economic Review 81, 971–978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stott, Henry P. (2006). “Cumulative Prospect Theory’s Functional Menagerie,” The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 32, 101–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Craig Fox. (1995). “Weighing Risk and Uncertainty,” Psychological Review 102, 269–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. (1992). “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. Kip, and William N. Evans. (2006). “Behavioral Probabilities,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 32, 5–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, Peter P., and Daniel Deneffe. (1996). “Eliciting von Neumann-Morgenstern Utilities when Probabilities Are Distorted or Unkown,” Management Science 42, 1131–1150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, George, and Richard Gonzalez. (1996). “Curvature of the Probability Weighting Function,” Management Science 42, 1676–1690.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Peter Wakker and two anonymous referees provided helpful comments. Mohammed Abdellaoui and Olivier L’Haridon’s research was supported by the French National Research Agency (ANR, Risk Attitude). Han Bleichrodt’s research was supported by a grant from the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mohammed Abdellaoui.

Appendices

Appendix 1

1.1 Illustration of questions

Fig. 3
figure 3

Illustration of a task in the gain domain

Fig. 4
figure 4

Illustration of a task in the mixed domain

Appendix 2

2.1 Explanation of the bisection method

The bisection method used to generate the iterations is illustrated in Table 10 for L 1 for \(p_\ell = {1 \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {1 3}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} 3}\) and the elicitation of \(L_6^ * \) for \(p_g = p_\ell = {1 \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {1 2}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} 2}\). The prospect that is chosen is printed in bold. Starting values in the iterations were always chosen so that prospects had equal expected value. Depending on the choice made, the certain outcome was increased or decreased. The size of the change was always half the size of the change in the previous question with the restriction that numbers should always be a multiple of 10. When a number was not a multiple of 10 it was rounded downwards. The method resulted in an interval within which the indifference value should lie. The midpoint of this interval was taken as the indifference value. For example, in Table 10 the indifference value for \(L_6^ * \) should lie between −3,960 and −3,680. Then we took as the indifference value −3,820. In the elicitation of utility on the gain and loss domains, the certainty equivalents were elicited in five iterations. In the elicitation of the loss aversion coefficients, we used six iterations. We used one additional iteration in the elicitation of the loss aversion coefficients because the intervals \(G_j^ * - L_j^ * \) were larger than the intervals |x j  − y j |.

Table 10 An illustration of the bisection method

Appendix 3

Table 11 Overview of the individual results (standard errors are in parentheses)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H. & L’Haridon, O. A tractable method to measure utility and loss aversion under prospect theory. J Risk Uncertainty 36, 245–266 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9039-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9039-8

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation