Skip to main content
Log in

Analytical Sociology: A Bungean Appreciation

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Analytical sociology, an intellectual project that has garnered considerable attention across a variety of disciplines in recent years, aims to explain complex social processes by dissecting them, accentuating their most important constituent parts, and constructing appropriate models to understand the emergence of what is observed. To achieve this goal, analytical sociologists demonstrate an unequivocal focus on the mechanism-based explanation grounded in action theory. In this article I attempt a critical appreciation of analytical sociology from the perspective of Mario Bunge’s philosophical system, which I characterize as emergentist systemism. I submit that while the principles of analytical sociology and those of Bunge’s approach share a lot in common, the latter brings to the fore the ontological status and explanatory importance of supra-individual actors (as concrete systems endowed with emergent causal powers) and macro-social mechanisms (as processes unfolding in and among social systems), and therefore it does not stipulate that every causal explanation of social facts has to include explicit references to individual-level actors and mechanisms. In this sense, Bunge’s approach provides a reasonable middle course between the Scylla of sociological reification and the Charybdis of ontological individualism, and thus serves as an antidote to the untenable “strong program of microfoundations” to which some analytical sociologists are committed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Elster (2007: 455, quoted in Hedström and Ylikoski 2010a: 58) observes, “[w]hat one might call the ‘analytical turn’ in social sciences…rests…on a near-obsessive concern with clarity and explicitness”.

  2. See e.g., Bunge (1989b, 1995, 1996: 359–387, 1999: 87–101, 2001b); cf. Oldenburg (2007); Balog (2008); Cherkaoui (2003).

  3. Emergentist systemism postulates that (1) every thing and every idea is either a system or an actual or potential component of a system, where a system is defined as a complex object whose components are held together by strong (logical, physical, biological, or social) bonds; (2) every system possesses at least one emergent (systemic, global) property absent from their components; (3) every concrete (real, material) system can be analyzed into a definite (albeit changeable) composition, environment (endo- and exo-)structure, and mechanism(s), and the model that incorporates these four aspects is called the CESM model (see Wan 2011).

  4. See e.g., Sawyer (2004); Boudon (1999); Langlois (1983); Kroneberg (2008: 224n); cf. Demeulenaere (2011: 8–9).

  5. For some notable and important works, see Alexander et al. (1987); Sibeon (2004); Greve et al. (2008); Martin (2009); O’Donnell (2010); Martin and Dennis (2010); Elder-Vass (2010).

  6. Human agency here is understood as “the capacity not only to reproduce, but also (under certain conditions) to creatively reconfigure and transform the relational structures within which action unfold” (Emirbayer 1996: 122).

  7. In describing and analyzing a system, one has to take into account (a) what it consists of (its composition); (b) the environment in which it is located (its environment); (c) how its components and environmental items are related to one another (its endostructure and exostructure); and (d) how it works, or what makes it what it is (its mechanism[s]). See e.g., Bunge (1998: 61–64, 105–107, 2003: 35–37, 2006a: 124–129, 2006b: 10–11, 2010b: 378–379).

  8. As Wolfgang Hofkirchner (2007: 477) points out, it was Bunge, “who contrary to most scholars of systems thinking introduced the notion of processes in the definition of systems”. But it should always be remembered that processes do not exist independently of the entities in or among which they occur. See Bunge (2001a: 32–33, 1977: 268–270) for critical discussions of “radical” dynamicism as represented by, among others, Alfred North Whitehead’s process metaphysics.

  9. In the words of Moessinger (2008: 237–238, emphasis added): “A process is an interaction between the components of a system and/or between this system and its environment, capable of producing or preventing change in the system or its components”. Note that in the social realm, these interactions do not take place exclusively between individual actors, since supra-individual actors (collective and corporate actors) play important roles in these processes. See the section on the ontological status of supra-individual actors.

  10. This means that the focus on social action is not an end in itself, but serves to explain social facts (Kroneberg 2008: 224).

  11. “Human beings are the creators, reformers, and destroyers of all human social systems, and social laws and rules are nothing but the patterns of being and becoming of such systems” (Bunge 1998: 122). See also Esser (1994: 184); Vaughan (2009: 701); Hedström (2009: 333); Hedström and Ylikoski (2010a: 60).

  12. See also Hedström and Ylikoski (2010a: 60, 2010b: 393–395); Esser 1994: (181–182); Wright et al. (1992: 125–126); Mantzavinos (2009).

  13. For example, the action-theoretical microfoundations of sociological explanation can be flexibly based on a variety of models, such as homo sociologicus, homo economicus, homo reciprocans, homo emotionalis, homo aestimans, homo creativus, or whatever suits one’s explanatory purposes.

  14. Hedström and Ylikoski (2010a: 60, see also 2010b: 395) argue forcefully that rational choice theory is “built upon implausible psychological and sociological assumptions”. As for Hedström’s realist distinction between descriptively incomplete and descriptively false assumptions, and his unequivocal criticism of the latter, see especially Hedström (2005: 62–63, 148–149); Hedström and Ylikoski (2010a: 60–61, 2010b: 394–395); cf. Esser (1993: 120–140); Kiser (1999); Kroneberg (2008: 237–238); Udehn (2001: 288–309). Note that analytical sociologists are interested in rational choice theory not for empirical reasons, but for methodological reasons: RCT is a formal theory that “advocates the same virtues of clarity and precision as analytical sociology does” (Hedström and Ylikoski 2010b: 394).

  15. Bunge (1996: 386) also contends that rationality should be conceptualized in a broader, richer way. See also his critique of Coleman’s linear system of action (Bunge 1998: 79–83).

  16. See also e.g., Boudon (1996, 1997, 2003, 2006, 2011).

  17. Bunge had once been enthusiastic about the rational choice approach because “it has all the trappings of exactness—a feature irresistible to the founder of the Society for Exact Philosophy” (Bunge 2001c: 409). But he later came to abandon this seemingly scientific but seriously flawed approach in the 1970s, and has subjected it to searching criticism. As he argues, the precise form of the utility function, a central concept of RCT, is seldom specified, and even when the function is mathematically well-defined, it is rarely checked against empirical data. Importantly, the findings of experimental economics have decisively refuted the main postulates of RCT. (As Bunge [2007: 545] puts it: “If falsity were enough to drop a theory, the thousands of rational choice theories would quickly be consigned to the dustbin of intellectual history”.) RCT is therefore both conceptually fuzzy and empirically untenable.

  18. Cf. e.g., Barbalet (1998, 2002); Sayer (2005); Elster (1999, 2007: 145–161, 2009); Kron and Grund (2010: 13–14).

  19. It should also be noted that most analytical sociologists would agree with Bunge’s emphasis on (1) the social embeddedness of action, (2) the entire process and outcome of practical action, and (3) the dimension of “protest” and its effects on society largely ignored by action theorists (Bunge 1998: 308–309).

  20. This explains why Mahner and Bunge (1997: 176) write that “a moderate dose of methodological—not ontological—individualism may be a healthy antidote to naïve holism”, since methodological individualism (in the broadest sense) holds that wholes can be understood if analyzed into their parts.

  21. In Bunge’s CESM model of society, “social structure” stands for the set of relations among the members of a given social system and among these and items in the system’s environment, while the total social structure of a society is defined as “the union of its biological, economic, political, and cultural structures” (Bunge 1998: 66). On this view, importantly, “structure” is an emergent property of a system and therefore not a thing (Bunge 2010a, b: 375, 379; cf. Wan 2011: 128n).

  22. One reviewer correctly points to the similarity between the situational logic/mechanism as emphasized by analytical social scientists and Margaret Archer’s morphogenetic approach. In fact, Archer herself employs this term in explaining how institutional and cultural configurations define different situational logics that predispose agents towards specific courses of (strategic) action (see e.g., Archer 1995; Creaven 2000).

  23. For more discussion, see Sect. 5 below. A similar perspective to structural individualism is “actor-centered institutionalism”, which seeks to integrate action-theoretic and institutionalist perspectives (e.g., Mayntz and Scharpf 1995; Scharpf 1997; Schimank 2004; Kron 2010: 17–51). Also of relevance here are the works of the Nobel laureate Elinor Ostrom, who has developed a comprehensive critique and reconstruction of collective action theory by taking micro-situational and broader contextual factors seriously (see e.g., Ostrom 2007, 2010; Vollan and Ostrom 2010; Poteete et al. 2010).

  24. See also Franks (2010); Turner (2007); Fehr and Gintis (2007); Reddy (2009); Pickel (2005).

  25. With the help of the theory of “action and its environments” elaborated by Alexander (e.g., 1987) and Emirbayer (1996), we can say that the emphasis on situational and action-formation mechanisms discussed here well captures the fact that action unfolds within a plurality of cultural, social-structural, and social psychological environments or contexts.

  26. The structure of and conditions for such collective (joint, shared) intentions have been the focus of much debate, since intentionality is generally deemed as a feature of individual minds or brains .

  27. See also Marsden (2006: 70); Elder-Vass (2010: 152–154, 158–60); Udehn (2001: 295–296).

  28. Note that, however, Archer (1995: 258, see also 2011: 84) uses the term “corporate agents” to refer to those who are “aware of what they want, can articulate it to themselves and others, and have organized in order to get it”, and are able to “engage in concerted action to re-shape or retain the structural or cultural feature in question”. Both collective and corporate actors are therefore candidates for “corporate agents” in Archer’s sense.

  29. The most prominent among them include the nuances between different types of composite actors (e.g., Scharpf 1997; Geser 1990, 1992; Coleman 1990; Sibeon 2004; King et al. 2010), the conditions of joint actions and group agency (e.g., Pettit and Schweikard 2006; Pettit 2009; List and Pettit 2011), collective intentionality (e.g., Tollefsen 2002; Saaristo 2006; Chant 2007; Gilbert 2007) and plural subjecthood (e.g., Gilbert 2000; Sheehy 2006), and the logic of “team reasoning” (e.g., Sudgen 2003; Bacharach 2006; Gold and Sugden 2007; Colman et al. 2008) and “we-reasoning” (e.g., Tuomela 2007a, b; Hakli et al. 2010).

  30. Adloff (2006: 4) admits that a “class” is not an “acting unit”, but his reason is that it lacks the ability to “steer its actions quasi-intentionally and self-reflexively”.

  31. See, among others, Wight (2004: 296); Lichbach and de Vries (2007); Maurer and Schmid (2008); Blom and Morén (2011: 64–65). Bunge (1998: 88, 106, 1999: 56, 2006a: 122–123, 131, 2009: 19) himself also writes of such macro-social mechanisms as production and exchange, technological innovation, price formation, wealth redistribution, consumerism, deindustrialization, ethnic conflicts, social cohesion, social control, nation-building mechanisms (e.g., compulsory elementary schooling), various “economic and political segregation mechanisms” allegedly overlooked by the pioneering analytical social scientist Thomas Schelling, and so forth.

  32. I thank one reviewer for making this criticism.

  33. A more popular translation by Wolfgang Mommsen (1965: 44n) is “exorcise the spectre of collective conceptions which still lingers among us”.

  34. This is exactly what the situational mechanism is about (recall the Sect. 3).

  35. Bunge’s emergentism asserts that all facts (states or changes of states [events and processes]), whether chemical, mental, or social, occur in material things. Contrary to physicalism (eliminative materialism), it maintains that supra-physical things, from organisms to social systems, are real/material.

  36. Hedström (2005: 25; see also e.g., Hedström and Ylikoski 2010b: 389) follows Machamer et al. (2000) in defining mechanisms as consisting of “entities (with their properties) and the activities that these entities engage in, either by themselves or in concert with other entities”. This view is referred to by Glennan (2010) as the “mechanistic systems approach”, developed mainly by philosophers of the life sciences. For more discussion on the commonalities and differences between Bunge’s and analytical sociologists’ conceptions of “mechanism”, see Wan (2011: 145–148). Notwithstanding the differences, both sides would agree that “since any ‘event’ or ‘process’ ultimately refers to entities and activities…, a definition that focuses on entities/properties/activities triads seems more accurate than a definition which refers generically to such notions as ‘events’ or ‘processes’” (Manzo 2010: 150). In my view, Bunge’s CESM model and his general systems philosophy provide a coherent ontological basis for conceptualizing these “entities”, “activities”, and “processes”.

  37. In a recent article, Jepperson and Meyer (2011: 68) make a strong case against “assigning privileged status to individualist explanation” by meticulously examining the existing literature on the connections between Protestantism and capitalist development. However, their accusation of the mechanism-based explanation is unsubstantiated, since they simply oppose it to “the theoretical task of attending to the multiple levels of analysis involved in sociological explanation”. As we have seen, once the dogmatic insistence on individualist microfoundations is abandoned, mechanism-based explanations will be perfectly in tune with multi-level analysis. For example, Lichbach and de Vries (2007) distinguish among macro-, meso-, and micro-level mechanisms (e.g., economic mechanisms and political behavior mechanisms taking place at the macro and micro levels respectively) that should be taken into consideration in a multi-level analysis of the mobilization of globalized protest movements. Likewise, in his study of the global order and the post-communist transformation, Pickel (2006) makes extensive use of, for example, nationalism as a nationalizing mechanism, which takes place not merely “at global, regional, state-society, and local levels”, but “in political, cultural, economic, and biosocial systems and organizations of all sorts” (Pickel 2006: 135).

  38. Bunge (2003: 136, see also 1998: 73, 2010a: 90) also writes of a “well-known finer-level distinction…between individual actor (nano), firm (micro), cartel (meso), national economy (macro), and world economy (mega)” in his discussion of inter-level relations.

  39. Indeed, Bunge has made it clear that complex systems typically undergo several (more or less intertwined) processes at different levels. This also holds true in the case of evolutionary biology. As Bunge (2010a: 81) points out, most biologists agree that evolution “has resulted from the concurrent operation of mutation, environmental selection, niche construction, hybridization (mainly in plants), and a few other mechanisms present on all levels, from molecule to whole organism to population to community”. It is these multi-level interactions and assorted concurrent mechanisms that radical reductionists, such as the propagandists of “one-level, gene-based views” (Gould 2001: 224), typically lose sight of because of their “desire to explain all larger-scale phenomena by properties of the smallest constituent particles” (Gould 2001: 225).

References

  • Abell, P., et al. (2010). Causal and constitutive relations, and the squaring of Coleman’s diagram: Reply to Vromen. Erkenntnis, 73(3), 385–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adloff, F. (2006). Religion and social-political action: The Catholic church, Catholic charities, and the American welfare state. International Review of Sociology, 16(1), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J. C. (1987). Action and its environments. In J. C. Alexander, et al. (Eds.), The micro-macro link (pp. 289–318). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J. C., et al. (Eds.). (1987). The micro-macro link. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C. (2008). Housing market renewal and social class. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. S. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. S. (2000). Being human: The problem of agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. S. (2011). Morphogenesis: Realism’s explanatory framework. In A. M. Maccarini, et al. (Eds.), Sociological realism (pp. 59–94). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacharach, M. (2006). In N. Gold & R. Sugden (eds.), Beyond individual choice: Teams and frames in game theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Balog, A. (2008). Makrophänomene und “Handlungstheorie”. Colemans Beitrag zur Erklärung sozialer Phänomene. In J. Greve, A. Schnabel, & R. Schützeichel (Eds.), Das Mikro-Makro-Modell der soziologischen Erklärung. Zur Ontologie, Methodologie und Metatheorie eines Forschungsprogramms (pp. 251–266). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbalet, J. M. (1998). Emotion, social theory, and social structure: A macrosociological approach. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barbalet, J. M. (Ed.). (2002). Emotions and sociology. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbera, F. (2004). Meccanismi sociali. Elementi di sociologia analitica. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbera, F. (2006). A star is born? The authors, principles and objectives of analytical sociology. Papers: Revista de Sociologia, 80, 31–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, A. (2008). The mother of all “isms”: Organizing political science around causal mechanisms. In R. Groff (Ed.), Revitalizing causality: Realism about causality in philosophy and social science (pp. 205–219). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blom, B., & Morén, S. (2011). Analysis of generative mechanisms. Journal of Critical Realism, 10(1), 60–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (1981). The logic of social action: An introduction to sociological analysis. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (1996). The “cognitivist model”: A generalized “rational-choice model”. Rationality and Society, 8(2), 123–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (1997). The moral sense. International Sociology, 12(1), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (1999). Foreword. In M. Bunge (Ed.), The sociology-philosophy connection (pp. xi–xv). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (2003). Beyond rational choice theory. Annual Review of Sociology, 29, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (2006). Utility or rationality? Restricted or general rationality? In R. Arena & A. Festré (Eds.), Knowledge, beliefs and economics (pp. 155–178). Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (2007). Which theory of behaviour for the social sciences? In F. Castellani & J. Quitterer (Eds.), Agency and causation in the human sciences (pp. 197–212). Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (2011). Ordinary rationality: The core of analytical sociology. In P. Demeulenaere (Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms (pp. 33–49). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R., & Bourricaud, F. (1989). A critical dictionary of sociology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brante, T. (2001). Consequences of realism for sociological theory building. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 31(2), 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brym, R. J., & Hamlin, C. (2009). Suicide bombers: Beyond cultural dopes and rational fools. In M. Cherkaoui & P. Hamilton (Eds.), Raymond Boudon: A life in sociology (Vol. 2, pp. 83–96). Oxford: Bardwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1977). Treatise on basic philosophy. Vol. 3. Ontology I: The furniture of the world. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1981). Scientific materialism. Boston, USA: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1989a). Treatise on basic philosophy. Vol. 8. Ethics: The good and the right. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1989b). Game theory is not a useful tool for the political scientist. Epistemologia, 12(1), 195–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1995). The poverty of rational choice theory. In I. Jarvie & N. Laor (Eds.), Critical rationalism, metaphysics and sciences (Vol. 1, pp. 149–168). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1996). Finding philosophy in social science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1998). Social science under debate: A philosophical perspective. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1999). The sociology-philosophy connection. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2000). Ten modes of individualism—none of which works—and their alternatives. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 30(3), 384–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2001a). Philosophy in crisis: The need for reconstruction. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2001b). Rational choice theory: A critical look at its foundations. In M. Mahner (Ed.), Scientific realism: Selected essays of Mario Bunge (pp. 303–319). Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2001c). Systems and emergence, rationality and imprecision, free-wheeling and evidence, science and ideology: Social science and its philosophy according to van den Berg. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 31(3), 404–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003). Emergence and convergence: Qualitative novelty and the unity of knowledge. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2006a). Chasing reality: Strife over realism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2006b). A systemic perspective on crime. In P.-O. H. Wikström & R. J. Sampson (Eds.), The explanation of crime: Context, mechanisms, and development (pp. 8–30). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2007). Review of moral sentiments and material interests. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 37(4), 543–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2009). Political philosophy: Fact, fiction and vision. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2010a). Matter and mind: A philosophical inquiry. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2010b). Soziale Mechanismen und mechanismische Erklärungen. Berliner Journal für Soziologie, 20, 371–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M., & Ardila, R. (1987). Philosophy of psychology. New York: Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chant, S. R. (2007). Unintentional collective action. Philosophical Explorations, 10(3), 245–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherkaoui, M. (2003). Les transitions micro-macro Limites de la théorie du choix rationnel dans les Foundations of Social Theory. Revue française de sociologie, 44(2), 231–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. S. (1974). Power and the structure of society. New York: Norton.

  • Coleman, J. S. (1982). The asymmetric society. Syracuse, N.Y.: Syracuse University Press.

  • Coleman, J. S. (1990). Foundations of social theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colman, A. M., Pulford, B. D., & Rose, J. (2008). Team reasoning and collective rationality: Piercing the veil of obviousness. Acta Psychologica, 128(2), 409–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Creaven, S. (2000). Marxism and realism: A materialistic application of realism in the social sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crossley, N. (2010). Towards relational sociology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahrendorf, R. (1959). Class and class conflict in industrial society. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeLanda, M. (2006). A new philosophy of society: Assemblage theory and social complexity. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeulenaere, P. (2011). Introduction. In P. Demeulenaere (Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms (pp. 1–30). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Donati, P. (2010). Relational sociology: A new paradigm for the social sciences. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The causal power of social structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1999). Alchemies of the mind: Rationality and the emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2007). Explaining social behavior: More nuts and bolts for the social sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2009). Emotions. In P. Hedström & P. Bearman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of analytical sociology (pp. 51–71). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emirbayer, M. (1996). Useful Durkheim. Sociological Theory, 14(2), 109–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esser, H. (1993). Soziologie. Allgemeine Grundlagen. New York: Campus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esser, H. (1994). Explanatory Sociology. Soziologie, special edition, 3, 177–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esser, H. (1999). Soziologie. Spezielle Grundlagen. Band 1: Situationslogik und Handeln. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Gintis, H. (2007). Human motivation and social cooperation: Experimental and analytical foundations. Annual Review of Sociology, 33(1), 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fotopoulos, T. (2000). Systems theory and complexity: A potential tool for radical analysis or the emerging social paradigm for the internationalised market economy? Democracy and Nature, 6(3), 421–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franks, D. D. (2010). Neurosociology: The nexus between neuroscience and social psychology. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, C. (2008). Internet and society: Social theory in the information age. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geser, H. (1990). Organisationen als soziale Akteure. Zeitschrift für Soziologie, 19(6), 401–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geser, H. (1992). Towards an interaction theory of organizational actors. Organization Studies, 13(3), 429–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2000). Sociality and responsibility: New essays in plural subject theory. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2007). Searle and collective intentions. In S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Intentional acts and institutional facts: Essays on John Searle’s social ontology (pp. 31–48). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2010). Ephemeral mechanisms and historical explanation. Erkenntnis, 72(2), 251–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, N., & Sugden, R. (2007). Collective intentions and team agency. Journal of Philosophy, 104(3), 109–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2001). The evolutionary definition of selective agency, validation of the theory of hierarchical selection, and fallacy of the selfish gene. In R. S. Singh, et al. (Eds.), Thinking about evolution: Historical, philosophical, and political perspectives (pp. 208–234). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greshoff, R. (2010). Brauchen wir eine neue Theorienvergleichsdebatte? Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Forum 2, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greshoff, R., Huinink, J., & Schimank, U. (2011). Aggregation dynamics of multi-level actor constellations: Introductory paper. Welfare Societies working papers, no. 02/2011. Bremen: Research Network “Welfare Societies”.

  • Greve, J., Schnabel, A., & Schützeichel, R. (Eds.). (2008). Das Mikro-Makro-Modell der soziologischen Erklärung. Zur Ontologie, Methodologie und Metatheorie eines Forschungsprogramms. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hakli, R., Miller, K., & Tuomela, R. (2010). Two kinds of we-reasoning. Economics and philosophy, 26(3), 291–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, C. L. (2002). Beyond relativism: Raymond Boudon, cognitive Rationality, and critical realism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1981). Philosophical aspects of the macro-micro problem. In K. Knorr-Cetina & A. V. Cicourel (Eds.), Advances in social theory and methodology: Toward an integration of micro- and macro-sociologies (pp. 139–160). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1993). Social being (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1997). Crews, clubs, crowds, and classes: “The social” as a discursive category. In J. D. Greenwood (Ed.), The mark of the social: Discovery or invention? (pp. 199–212). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Madden, E. H. (1975). Causal powers: A theory of natural necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P. (2005). Dissecting the social: On the principles of analytical sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P. (2009). The analytical turn in sociology. In P. Hedström & B. Wittrock (Eds.), Frontiers of sociology (pp. 331–342). Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Bearman, P. (2009). What is analytical sociology all about? An introductory essay. In P. Hedström & P. Bearman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of analytical sociology (pp. 3–24). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Swedberg, R. (1996). Social Mechanisms. Acta Sociologica, 39(3), 281–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Swedberg, R. (1998). Social mechanisms: An introductory essay. In P. Hedström & R. Swedberg (Eds.), Social mechanisms: An analytical approach to social theory (pp. 1–31). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Ylikoski, P. (2010a). Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology, 36, 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Ylikoski, P. (2010b). Analytical sociology. In I. Jarvie & J. Zamora-Bonilla (Eds.), The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of social sciences (pp. 386–398). London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heintz, B. (2004). Emergenz und Reduktion: Neue Perspektiven auf das Mikro-Makro-Problem. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 56(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofkirchner, W. (2007). A critical social systems view of the internet. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 37(4), 471–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoover, K. D. (2001). Causality in macroeconomics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jepperson, R., & Meyer, J. W. (2011). Multiple levels of analysis and the limitations of methodological individualisms. Sociological Theory, 29(1), 54–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joas, H. (1996). The creativity of action. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joas, H. (2004). The changing role of the social sciences: An action-theoretical perspective. International Sociology, 19(3), 301–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. P. (2008). Contemporary sociological theory: An integrated multi-level approach. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1997). Individualism and the unity of science: Essays on reduction, explanation, and the special sciences. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (2002). Social sciences. In P. Machamer & M. Silberstein (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science (pp. 290–311). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, B., Felin, T., & Whetten, D. (2010). Finding the organization in organization theory: A meta-theory of the organization as social actor. Organization Science, 21(1), 290–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiser, E. (1999). Comparing varieties of agency theory in economics, political science, and sociology: An illustration from state policy implementation. Sociological Theory, 17(2), 146–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kontopoulos, K. M. (1993). The logics of social structure. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kron, T. (2010). Zeitgenossische soziologische Theorien. Zentrale Beitrage aus Deutschland. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kron, T., & Grund, T. (2010). Einführung in die Diskussion zur Analytischen Soziologie. In T. Kron & T. Grund (Eds.), Die Analytische Soziologie in der Diskussion (pp. 7–27). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kroneberg, C. (2008). Methodologie statt Ontologie. Das Makro-Mikro-Makro-Modell als einheitlicher Bezugsrahmen der akteurstheoretischen Soziologie. In J. Greve, A. Schnabel, & R. Schützeichel (Eds.), Das Mikro-Makro-Modell der soziologischen Erklärung. Zur Ontologie, Methodologie und Metatheorie eines Forschungsprogramms (pp. 357–371). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroneberg, C. (2011). Die Erklärung sozialen Handelns. Grundlagen und Anwendungen einer integrativen Theorie. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. (2009). Two concepts of mechanism: Componential causal system and abstract form of interaction. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23(2), 143–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurki, M. (2008). Causation in international relations: Reclaiming causal analysis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langlois, R. N. (1983). Systems theory, knowledge, and the social sciences. In F. Machlup & U. Mansfield (Eds.), The study of information: Interdisciplinary messages (pp. 581–600). New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichbach, M., & de Vries, H. G. E. (2007). Contentious politics and social movements. In C. Boix & S. C. Stokes (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of comparative politics (pp. 461–496). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1998). Microfoundations, method, and causation: On the philosophy of the social sciences. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (2010). Action in history and social science. In T. O’Connor & C. Sandis (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of action (pp. 401–409). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (1995). Social systems (J. Bednarz, Jr., & D. Baecker, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  • Maccarini, A. M. (2011). Towards a new European sociology. In A. M. Maccarini, et al. (Eds.), Sociological realism (pp. 95–121). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M., & Bunge, M. (1997). Foundations of biophilosophy. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mantzavinos, C. (2009). A note on methodological individualism. In M. Cherkaoui & P. Hamilton (Eds.), Raymond Boudon: A life in sociology (Vol. 1, pp. 211–215). Oxford: Bardwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzo, G. (2007). Variables, mechanisms, and simulations: Can the three methods be synthesized? Revue française de sociologie, 48(supplement), 35–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzo, G. (2010). Analytical sociology and its critics. European Journal of Sociology, 51(1), 129–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marchionni, C. (2008). Explanatory pluralism and complementarity: From autonomy to integration. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 38(3), 314–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marsden, P. V. (2006). Coleman, James S. In J. Beckert & M. Zafirovski (Eds.), International encyclopedia of economic sociology (pp. 69–71). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, J. L. (2009). Social structures. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, P. J., & Dennis, A. (Eds.). (2010). Human agents and social structures. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, A., & Schmid, M. (2008). Mechanismen in der erklärenden Soziologie. Zur Logik und Forschungspraxis mechanismischer Erklärungen am Beispiel des Machtmechanismus. In K.-S. Rehberg (Ed.), Verhandlungen des 33. Kongresses der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Soziologie in Kassel 2006 (pp. 2881–2895). Frankfurt am Main: Campus Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayntz, R., & Scharpf, F. W. (1995). Der Ansatz des akteurzentrierten Institutionalismus. In R. Mayntz & F. W. Scharpf (Eds.), Gesellschaftliche Selbstregelung und politische Steuerung (pp. 39–72). Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moessinger, P. (2008). Voir la société: Le micro et le macro. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mommsen, W. (1965). Max Weber’s political sociology and his philosophy of world history. International Social Science Journal, 17(1), 23–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouzelis, N. (2008). Modern and postmodern social theorizing: Bridging the divide. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noguera, J. A. (2006). Introduction: Why we need an analytical sociological theory. Papers: Revista de Sociologia, 80, 7–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noguera, J. A., et al. (2009). Por un giro analítico en sociología. Revista Internacional de Sociología, 67(2), 435–456.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell, M. (Ed.). (2010). Structure and agency (Vol. 1–3). London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oldenburg, L. (2007). Bunge vs. Esser- Eine Analyse von Kritik an der Rational-Choice-Theorie. Norderstedt: GRIN Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2007). Collective action theory. In C. Boix & S. C. Stokes (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of comparative politics (pp. 186–208). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2010). Beyond markets and states: Polycentric governance of complex economic systems. American Economic Review, 100(3), 641–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panebianco, A. (2009). L’automa e lo spirito. Azioni individuali, istituzioni, imprese collettive. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2009). The reality of group agents. In C. Mantzavinos (Ed.), Philosophy of the social sciences: Philosophical theory and scientific practice (pp. 67–91). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P., & Schweikard, D. (2006). Joint actions and groups agents. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36(1), 18–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickel, A. (2005). The habitus process: A biopsychosocial conception. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 35(4), 437–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickel, A. (2006). The problem of order in the global age: Systems and mechanisms. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poteete, A. R., Janssen, M. A., & Ostrom, E. (2010). Working together: Collective action, the commons, and multiple methods in practice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, W. W., & Colyvas, J. (2008). Microfoundations of institutional theory. In R. Greenwood, C. Oliver, K. Sahlin, & R. Suddaby (Eds.), The Sage handbook of organizational institutionalism (pp. 276–298). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pozzi, D. R. (2007). System’s effects: Some comments on methodological individualism. L’Année sociologique, 57(1), 63–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, W. M. (2009). Saying something new: Practice theory and cognitive neuroscience. Arcadia: International Journal for Literary Studies, 44(1), 8–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rustagi, D., Engel, S., & Kosfeld, M. (2010). Conditional cooperation and costly monitoring explain success in forest commons management. Science, 330, 961–965.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saaristo, A. (2006). There is no escape from philosophy: Collective intentionality and empirical social science. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36(1), 40–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. K. (2004). The mechanisms of emergence. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(2), 260–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sayer, A. (2005). The moral significance of class. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sayer, A. (2010). Method in social science: A realist approach (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf, F. W. (1997). Games real actors play: Actor-centered institutionalism in policy research. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schimank, U. (2004). Der akteurzentrierte Institutionalismus. In M. Gabriel (Ed.), Paradigmen der akteurszentrierten Soziologie (pp. 289–301). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwinn, T. (1998). False connections: Systems and action theories in neofunctionalism and in Jürgen Habermas. Sociological Theory, 16(1), 75–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwinn, T. (2008). Individual and collective agency. In W. Outhwaite & S. P. Turner (Eds.), The Sage handbook of social science methodology (pp. 302–315). London: SAGE.

  • Selznick, P. (1992). The moral commonwealth: Social theory and the promise of community. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selznick, P. (1996). Institutionalism old and new. Administrative Science Quarterly, 41(2), 270–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheehy, P. (2006). The reality of social groups. Aldershot, England: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sibeon, R. (2004). Rethinking social theory. London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2005). Mechanisms and functional hypotheses in social science. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 941–952.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stichweh, R. (2000). Systems theory as an alternative to action theory? The rise of “communication” as a theoretical option. Acta Sociologica, 43(1), 5–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2003). The logic of team reasoning. Philosophical explorations, 6(3), 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. P. (2002). Collective intentionality and the social sciences. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 32(1), 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2007a). The philosophy of sociality: The shared point of view. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2007b). On the ontological nature of social groups. In S. Pihlström, et al. (Eds.), Approaching truth: Essays in honour of Ilkka (pp. 381–398). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, S. P. (2007). Social theory as a cognitive neuroscience. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 357–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Udehn, L. (2001). Methodological individualism: Background, history, and meaning. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Udehn, L. (2003). The methodology of rational choice. In S. P. Turner & P. A. Roth (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of the social sciences (pp. 143–165). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Udehn, L. (2011). The ontology of the objects of historiography. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 209–219). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan, D. (2009). Analytic Ethnography. In P. Hedström & P. Bearman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of analytical sociology (pp. 688–711). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Vollan, B., & Ostrom, E. (2010). Cooperation and the commons. Science, 330, 923–924.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wan, P. Y.-z. (2011). Reframing the social: Emergentist systemism and social theory. Aldershot, England: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1978). Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. In G. Roth & C. Wittich (Eds.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Wight, C. (2004). Theorizing the mechanisms of conceptual and semiotic space. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(2), 283–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wikström, P.-O. H. (2008). In search of causes and explanations of crime. In R. D. King & E. Wincup (Eds.), Doing research on crime and justice (2nd ed., pp. 117–140). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, E. O., Levine, A., & Sober, E. (1992). Reconstructing Marxism: Essays on explanation and the theory of history. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am deeply grateful to eight anonymous reviewers for their criticisms, suggestions, and encouragements. This article is the result of a research project supported by National Science Council, Taiwan (project number 100-2628-H-110-008-MY2) and the Asia-Pacific Ocean Research Center at National Sun Yat-sen University, Taiwan (project number 00C0302703).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Poe Yu-ze Wan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Wan, P.Yz. Analytical Sociology: A Bungean Appreciation. Sci & Educ 21, 1545–1565 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9427-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9427-3

Keywords

Navigation