Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Philosophy of Science and Education

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This is a vast and vague topic. In order to do justice to it one has to write a book or maybe more than one. For it can be understood in quite different ways and on different levels For example you may think mainly of the historical aspect, that is how philosophy of science developed in the last hundred or so years and how its influence on education changed; you may think of quite different schools of philosophy, from Marxist or positivist to such exotic but at some places influential philosophic positions like that of Rudolph Steiner; of course, you may limit the subject to special fields like epistemology, theory of scientific methodology, or, what has become fashionable recently, sociology of knowledge which may have a considerable bearing on physics teaching (Collins and Shapin 1983; Jung 1985). Again we may think of the topic treated by a philosopher, a scientist, an educationalist, a teacher, which would mean quite a difference. I am trying here to speak as an educationalist, with the physics teacher in mind: this is my vocational perspective as someone who educates physics teachers. Of course, our main concern is the contribution of science, especially physics, to general education, which integrates many of the special topics mentioned. Philosophy of science comes in because it is not at all clear what science and physics is, and what of it should be taught, and how such chosen parts should be taught. I also take this opportunity to give an idea of the longstanding tradition of this discussion in Germany, connected with names like Wagenshein, Litt, Heisenberg and many others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The following quotation translated from a paper of Matilde Vicentini illustrates the point quite clearly:

    I conclude with an observation of a friend, an adult, with whom the kinetic model of gases and its educational relevance had been discussed at length, in view of the possibility of a programme (TV or radio) of popularization of science:

    You see, the problem is not the acceptance that in a gas or in a liquid the molecules are in motion, the possibility of movement of gases and liquids is obvious; it is this piece of marble (pointing to a paperweight on my desk) that makes it difficult for me to accept it. It is so compact, smooth, solid, static…..that, following my intuition, molecules inside it must be so rigidly connected to be still. (M. Vicentini, Le rappresentazioni mentali: problema di ricerca ed esempi. Manuse)

  2. The scheme is illustrated in the dialogue: “Why are you drunk?” “I always get drunk”—nice explanation.

  3. See 1987, p. 53, quoted later on.

  4. The following short quotation shows a very mundane reason for preferring theory over experimentation, which, moreover, illustrates qualitative changes in the way research is done today:

    If you were a bright young scientist, would you go into high-energy physics now? I think you could still say there is glamour in doing theory and that great cosmic questions are being addressed. But what is the attraction for an experimentalist …? (West in Cooper and West 1988, p. 194 C)

    It will become more and more difficult to get people to go into high-energy physics as the time-scale for doing experiments grows an order of magnitude equal to a person's lifetime. (Raby in Cooper and West 1988, p. 194 C)

  5. Hacking (1983, espec. p. 155ff.) has many historical examples of experimentation being not a test of theoretical predictions, it is just—in Glashow's words—“sit back and see what surprises us.”

  6. This is the phrase of Peirce in his statement referring to Kant:

    Nothing can be more completely false than that we can experience only our own ideas. (6.95)

  7. As far as I can see, only Schlick (1925, chap. 18) tackled that problem, in vain as I think.

  8. The recovery from this shock is obvious by many published books and articles, e.g. Rescher (1987), Batens and van Bendegem (1988), Siegel (1987) to name a few. The following statement from the preface by Batens and van Bendegem sets the motor for the new phase:

    The progressive destruction of the received view has been a fascinating and healthy experience. At present, the period of destruction is over. A richer and more equilibrated analysis … is possible and is being carried out. (p. vii)

  9. This conception of explanation as reduction is extensively discussed with a lot of examples from physics discussed in Aronson (1984), a valuable contribution to the discussion.

  10. An example of such a debate between eminent philosophers can be found in Cohen et al. (1976).

  11. You need not go as far as Peirce writing:

    People wonder, too, how dead matter can excite feelings in the mind. For my part, instead of wondering how it can be, I feel much disposed to deny downright that it is possible … and I prefer to guess that it is a psychic feeling of red without us which arouses a sympathetic feeling of red in our senses. (Coll. Pap. 1.311)

    Nevertheless, some categorical extension of physics seems to be unavoidable. An example is, of course, W. Sellar's introduction of sensa. The structure of his argument can best be learned not from his many books but from his Reply to Cornman (Sellars 1971, esp. 423–428).

  12. See also my review of van Fraassen's The Image of Science, Physica Didactica (1982), 103–106.

  13. Thirty years ago, Achinstein (1969) argued that observation terms and theoretical terms cannot be separated. The debate has wandered off this language level in the direction of the question: what can be termed observation? Brown's “definition”: p. 93 is too complicated to discuss here. “Observation” in this sense has much to do with what Hacking (1983) has termed “intervening”.

  14. I think it is again Peirce who very clearly discriminated between sensation and perceptual judgment and who pointed to the fact that only perceptual judgments are part of science: no judgment, no application of logic. (See e.g. Coll. Pap. 6.95) It should be noted that we do rely on perceptual judgments only when there are proper circumstances, e.g. “normal functioning” of bodily organs—which can now be partially controlled by science.

  15. Of course, idealisation on this level depends on perspective idealisation, i.e. “pattern recognition” (cf. Ziman 1979, chap. 3.2). The problem is well-known in the philosophy of mathematics. Peirce, with his background of historical knowledge, was already quite clear on this point: a “token” has to be identifiable and this implies a “lawlike” character.

  16. Fashionable eastern doctrines lurk in the background: without the vice of thinking and thus discriminating, there is the blissful, salvaging all-is-one. But the fundamental supposition is that nature (or “being”) is not a process of differentiation and discrimination in itself, and that in nature apart from our fictional attacks there is no conceptual functioning. Eastern doctrines gain some appeal with western irritated and stress intellectuals. We should not follow that trend.

  17. For examples, see for instance Laudan's (1981).

  18. This is another of my “first books”, a gift again in 1943.

  19. This message can easily be drawn from Goodman's (1986).

  20. He died in his nineties in 1988 after receiving the first didactic aware of the Deutsche Physikalische Gesellschaft in 1987.

  21. We owe to the French philosopher Ellul a balanced analysis of the political movements “Nazism” and “fascism” as expression of this romantic protest, see 1974, espec. IV 1: “Revolt and revolution in national socialism”.—The Marxist analysis of "fascism" is one-sided for the simple reason that Marxists unwaveringly believed in science and technology and the progress ensuing. In this respect, they are simply fulfilling capitalism, see also Ellul's (1974).

  22. In modern system theory, this is expressed by terming man a “self-referential” system. Though system theory is beginning to spread to educational philosophy now (see Schmidt 1987), I cannot go critically into this important new approach. The reductionist program has recently been analysed by Halstedt (1988) and Sutter (1988).

  23. My disagreement begins with his “primary world”. He has no theory of the way different aspects are connected as for example. Whitehead has constructed. I cannot accept that the results of science are merely a superstructure. As Aristotle put it: What is first for man need not to be first for nature. There are good reasons to believe that science gains much more intimate knowledge of reality than a superstructure could carry.

  24. This is reminiscent of Tillich's teaching in Frankfurt in the early thirties before emigrating to USA. He spoke of a “kairos”, a state of awaiting and avoiding premature fixations.

  25. Of course, a similar position is Whitehead's in his doctrine of societies. Around the same time Bertallanfy developed his biological theory of a stratification of systems, a forerunner of today's “synergetics” and thermodynamics of open systems.

  26. I only know it from a German translation.

  27. It is decades ago that Hund wrote:

    To bring in too much of the results of modern physics is not advisable. In order to understand even relatively simple things such as the constitution of the atom from nucleus and electrons, such a big chain [made] out of observations and arguments is necessary, that only very few students are able to experience in that way what it means to think physically. (Hund 1930, p. 382)

    Some years ago I asked him if he still agrees with this old statement. He did not remember having written it.

  28. But my first reading about quantum mechanics—apart from listening to Madelung's lectures—was Reichenbach's Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics.

  29. See e.g. Gibbins (1987, p. 118ff.), Herbert's (1985), though on the whole valuable, deserves some reservations. The same is, I think, true for Hey and Walters (1987).

  30. Examples have been discussed e.g. in Jung and Wiesner (1984). Concerning quantum mechanics, see Wiesner's dissertation published (1989).

References

  • Adair, R. K. (1987). The great design: Particles, fields and creation. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aronson, J. L. (1984). A realist philosophy of science. London, Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batens, D., van Bendegem, J. P. (Eds.). (1988). Theory and experiment: recent insights and new perspectives on their relation. Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Bell, J. S. (1988). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevilacqua, F. (1983). The principle of conservation of energy and the history of classical electromagnetic theory. Pavia: La Goliardica Pavese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. I. (1987a). Observation and objectivity. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. I. (1987b). Naturalising observation. In Nersessian (Ed.), pp. 179–194.

  • Buchdahl, G. (1983). Styles of scientific thinking. In F. Bevilacqua & P. J. Kennedy (Eds.), pp. 106–112. [Reprinted in Science & Education 1993, vol. 2, no 2, 149–168].

  • Buchwald, E. (1958). Bildung durch Physik. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, R. S., Feyerabend, P. K., & Wartofsky, M. W. (Eds.). (1976). Essays in memory of Imre Lakatos. Boston: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, S. H. (Ed.). (1982). Sociology of scientific knowledge. A source book. Bath: Bath University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. M., & Shapin, S. (1983). The historical role of the experiment. In: Bevilacqua/Kennedy (Ed.), pp. 282–292.

  • Cooper, N. G., & West, G. B. (Eds.). (1988). Particle physics: A Los Alamos primer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. C. W., & Brown, J. R. (Eds.). (1988). Superstrings: A theory of everything?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkana, Y. (Ed.). (1974). The interaction between science and philosophy. Atlantic Highlands, HJ: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellul, J. (1974). Von der Revolution zur Revolete. Hamburg: Hoffmann unde Campe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. (1986). The neglect of experiment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gerhardt, V. (1988). Pathos und Distanz—Studien zur Philosophie Friedrich Nietzsches. Stuttgart: Reclam Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbins, P. (1987). Particles and Paradoxes: The limits of quantum logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1986). Ways of worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett Publ. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Univ. of Cambridge Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1970). Hypotheses Fingo. In: Butts-Davis (Eds.).

  • Hastedt, H. (1988). Das Leib-Seele-problem. Frankfurt Am Main: Suhrkamp.

  • Heisenberg, W. (1956). Das Naturbild de heutigen Physik. Hamburg: Rowohlt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1970). Abschluß der Physik? Süddeutsche Zeitung, Julbiläumsbeilage vom 6.0kt., S.44.

  • Herbert, N. (1985). Quantum reality, beyond the new physics. New York: Anchor Press/Doubleday. (Deutsch 1987).

  • Hesse, M. (1970). Is there an independent observation language? In Colodny (Ed.).

  • Hey, T., & Walters, P. (1987). The quantum universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hund, F. (1930). Die wissenschaftliche Erziehung in den Naturwissenschaften. Mathematik und Physik. In: Nohl-Pallat, Bd. III.

  • Jung, W. (1983). Anstöße. Ein Essay über die Didaktik der Physik und ihre Probleme. Frankfurt a.M: Diesterweg.

  • Jung, W. (1985). New history and sociology of science (NHS) und die Ziele des Physikunterrichts. In Physik und Didaktik, vol. 13, pp. 257–262.

  • Jung, W., & Wiesner, H. (1984). Kontroverse Duetungen der Quantenphysik als Gegenstand des Physikunterrichts. In: Praxis der Naturwissenschaftern P/C 33, pp. 276–281.

  • Knorr-Cetina, K. D., & Mulkay, M. (Eds.). (1983). Science observed: Perspectives on the social study of science. London: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1982). Metaphor in Science. In: Ortony (Ed.), pp. 409–419.

  • Lakatos, I. (1972). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos & Musgrave (Eds.).

  • Laudan, L. (1981). Science and hypothesis: Historical essays on scientific methodology. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Litt, T. (1959). Naturwissenschaft und Menschenbildung, 3.erw. Auflage. Heidelberg: Quelle & Meyer.

  • Müller, A. (1974). Quantum mechanics: A physical world picture. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neil, R. E. (1970). The mushroom crowd. In: Karplus (Ed.), pp. 250–260.

  • Polanyi, M. (1959). The study of man. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. Garden City, New York: Doubleday & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1974). The roots of reference. New York: Doubleday (deutsch: Suhrkamp 1989).

  • Rescher, N. (1987). Scientific realism. Dordrecht: Reidel Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrlich, F. (1987). From paradox to reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M. (1920). Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, S. J. (Hrsg.). (1987). Der Diskurs des Radikalen Konstruktivismus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

  • Sellars, W. (1971). Science, sense impressions, and sensa: A reply to cornman. In: Review of Metaphysics, vol. 24, no. 3, pp. 391–447

  • Shapere, D. (1985). Observation and the scientific enterprise. In: P. Achinstein & O. Hannaway (Eds.), Chap. 2.

  • Shapere, D. (1987). Method in the philosophy of science and epistemology: How to inquire about inquiry and knowledge. In: Nersessian (Ed.), pp. 1–40.

  • Siegel, H. (1987). Relativism refuted: A critique of contemporary epistemological relativism. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, H. (1985). Modestly radical empiricism. In: P. Achinstein & O. Hannaway (Eds.), Chap. 1.

  • Solymar, L., & Walsh, D. (1984). Lectures on the electrical properties of matter. Oxford/New York/Toronto: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaemann, R., & LÖW, R. (1981). Die Frage Wozu? Geschichte und Widerentdeckung des teleologischen Denkens. München: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutter, A. (1988). Göttliche Maschinen. Die Automatan für Lebendiges. Frankfurt a.Main: Athenäum Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillich, P. (1956). Systematische Theologie Bd.I. Stuttgart: Evangelisches Verlagswerk.

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wagenschein, M. (1959). Zum Befriff des exemplarischen Lehrens. Weinheim-Berlin: Verlag J. Beltz.

  • Wagenschein, M. (1960). Zur Didaktik des naturwissenschaftlichen Unterrichts. Zeitschrift für Pädogogik. 2.Beiheft.

  • Wagenschein, M. (1961). Die pädagogische Dimension der Physik. Braunschweig: Westermann. (3. ergänzte Auflage 1971).

  • Wagenschein, M. (1966). Ursprüngliches Verstehen und Exaktes Denken. Bd.1. Stuttgart: E.Klett Verlag.

  • Wagenschein, M. (1966). Zum Problem des genetischen Lehrens. Zeitscghrift für Pädogogik, 12 Heft 4, 305–330.

  • Wagenschein, M. (1968). Die Sprache im Physikunterricht. Zeitschrift für Pädogogik. 7. Beiheft.

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1929). The anatomy of some scientific ideas. In The aims of education and other essays, chap. 9. New York: MacMillan (First published 1917) I quote from the Mentor Book edition of 1949.

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1941). Process and reality. New York: The Social Science Book Store (Reprint of the original 1929).

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1948a). Adventures of ideas. New York: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1948b). Essays in science and philosophy. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesner, H. (1989). Beiträge zur Didaktik über Quantenphysik in der Oberstufe. (Dissertation Unversität Frankfurt 1988). Essen: Westarp Verlag.

  • Wölfflin, H. (1915). Kunstegeschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Das Prolem der Stilentwicklung in der neueren Kunst. F. München: Bruckmann 1943 (1.Aufl. 1915).

  • Ziman, J. (1968). Public knowledge. The social dimension of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziman, J. (1978). Reliable knowledge: An exploration of the grounds for belief in science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Walter Jung.

Appendices

Appendix A, Walter Jung Biographical Statement [Provided by W.J., June 1992]

Walter Jung was born on February 6th 1926 in Darmstadt, Germany. He was a member of the Germany forces in the Second World War and after returning from American and English Prisoner of War camps studied mathematics, physics, philosophy and sociology in the years 1946–1951. Important influences on him were Madelung in physics, Hans-Georg Gadamer and Charles Hartshorne in philosophy, and Theodor Adorno in sociology. He worked with Adorno in preparing a German edition of Studies in Prejudice. He was a teacher in an experimental school 1953–1961; director of an institute for further training of teachers (science and mathematics) in Frankfurt (1961–1967); and professor for the teaching of physics (Didaktik der Physik) in the Hochschule für Erziehung and professor in the physics department at the University of Frankfurt (1967–1970) where he was Dean of the faculty for two terms, and a member of numerous university committees. He was a member of the Advisory Board of the Leibniz-Institute for Science Education (IPN) at the University of Kiel; editor of the journal Physica Didactica; and was granted an honorary degree from the University of Frankfurt.

His early philosophical papers on Whitehead and Pierce were published in Philosophia Naturalis, Zeitschrift Für Philosohical Forschung, and Philosophia Rundschau. He conducted research and published over 150 articles and books in the field of mathematics and physics teaching. He participated in the writing of physics curricula, and studied student conceptions in various areas of physics (mechanics, optics, electricity, quantum mechanics); he reflected and wrote on the aims of physics teaching and on the bearing of history and philosophy on physics teaching. In 1991 he was appointed an Emeritus professor of Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universität Frankfurt am Main.

[Walter Jung died May 29, 2011]

Appendix B: English Publications of Walter Jung

Jung, W.: 1983, ‘Toward Preparing Students for Change: A Critical Discussion of the Contribution of the History of Physics to Physics Teaching’. In F. Bevilacqua & P.J. Kennedy (eds.) Using History of Physics in Innovatory Physics Education, Pavia University, pp. 6–57.

Jung, W.: 1986, `Cognitive Science and the History of Science’. In P.V. Thomsen (ed.) Science Education and the History of Physics, University of Aarhus, pp. 24–54.

Jung, W.: 1987, ‘Understanding Students’ Understanding: The Case of Elementary Optics, Proceedings of the Second International Seminar: Misconceptions and Educational Strategies in Science and Mathematics, Vol. 3 Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp. 268–277. Available at: http://www.mlrg.org/misconproceedings3and4.html.

Jung, W.: 1993, ‘Uses of Cognitive Science to Science Education’, Science & Education 2(1), 31–56. [Jung 1986].

Jung, W.: 1994, ‘Preparing Students for Change: The Contribution of the History of Physics to Physics Teaching’, Science & Education 3(2), 99–130. [Jung 1983].

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Jung, W. Philosophy of Science and Education. Sci & Educ 21, 1055–1083 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9497-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9497-x

Keywords

Navigation