Skip to main content
Log in

An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue for an intentional conception of representation in science that requires bringing scientific agents and their intentions into the picture. So the formula is: Agents (1) intend; (2) to use model, M; (3) to represent a part of the world, W; (4) for some purpose, P. This conception legitimates using similarity as the basic relationship between models and the world. Moreover, since just about anything can be used to represent anything else, there can be no unified ontology of models. This whole approach is further supported by a brief exposition of some recent work in cognitive, or usage-based, linguistics. Finally, with all the above as background, I criticize the recently much discussed idea that claims involving scientific models are really fictions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Cartwright N.D. (1999) The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2009). Informational versus functional theories of scientific representation. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9502-3.

  • Contessa, G. (2009). Scientific models as fictional objects. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9503-2.

  • Dennett D.C. (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. Simon & Schuster, Inc, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine A. (1993) Fictionalism. Midwest studies in philosophy 18: 1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere R.N. (1988) Explaining science: A cognitive approach. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R.N. (1994) The cognitive structure of scientific theories. Philosophy of Science 61: 276–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R.N. (2006) Scientific perspectivism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice H.P. (1969) Utterer’s meaning and intentions. Philosophical Review 66: 377–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G. (1987) Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M.S., Morrison M. (eds) (1999) Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K.R. (1978) Natural selection and the emergence of mind. Dialectia 32: 339–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler I. (1963) The anatomy of inquiry: Philosophical studies in the theory of science. Knopf, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith E.E., Medin D.L. (1981) Categories and concepts. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez M. (2003) Scientific representation: Against similarity and isomorphism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17: 225–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez M. (2004) An inferential conception of scientific representation, Philosophy of Science 71: 767–779

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez M. (Eds.) (2009) Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1969) Studies in the methodology and foundations of science: Selected papers from 1951 to 1969. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (2008a). Of course idealizations are incommensurable! In L. Soler, H. Sankey, & P. Hoyningen-Huene (Eds.), Rethinking scientific change and theory comparison: Stabilities, ruptures, incommensurabilities? Kluwer.

  • Teller, P. (2008b). Representation in science. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to the philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2009). Missing systems and the face value practice. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9507-y.

  • Tomasello M. (2003) Constructing a language: A usage-based theory of language acquisition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaihinger, H. (1935). The philosophy of ‘As If’: A system of the theoretical, practical and religious fictions of mankind (C. K. Ogden, Trans.). New York: Barnes & Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Frassen, B. C. (2000). The theory of tragedy and of science: Does nature have a narrative structure. In Sfendoni-Mendou (eds), Aristotle and contemporary science (Vol. 1). New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton K.L. (1990) Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ronald N. Giere.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Giere, R.N. An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese 172, 269 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9506-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9506-z

Keywords

Navigation