Skip to main content
Log in

MUDdy understanding

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper focuses on two questions: (1) Is understanding intimately bound up with accurately representing the world? (2) Is understanding intimately bound up with downstream abilities? We will argue that the answer to both these questions is “yes”, and for the same reason-both accuracy and ability are important elements of orthogonal evaluative criteria along which understanding can be assessed. More precisely, we will argue that representational-accuracy (of which we assume truth is one kind) and intelligibility (which we will define so as to entail abilities) are good-making features of a state of understanding. Interestingly, both evaluative claims have been defended by philosophers in the literature on understanding as the criterion of evaluation. We argue that proponents of both approaches have important insights and that, drawing on both their own observations and a few novel arguments, we can construct a more complete picture of understanding evaluation. We thus posit the theory of there being Multiple Understanding Dimensions. The main thing to note about our dualism regarding the evaluative criteria of understanding is that it accounts for the intuitions about cases underlying both previously held positions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By “downstream” abilities we mean that which one can do with the understanding, contrasted with that by which one comes to possess it.

  2. Hempel defends this most explicitly in (1965, pp. 248–249).

  3. For our purposes, we do not need a theory of what it means for something to be close to being true. See Oddie (2014) for a discussion of some interesting possibilities.

  4. This terminology is sub-optimal in at least two respects. First, where de Regt defines intelligibility as a property of theories, we treat it as a property of the understanding those theories lead to; this is motivated entirely by the absence of a good word for the property of being ability-conferring-understanding. Our usage is also not to be confused with that of Waskan et al. (2014), who treat intelligibility as a property of explanations that cause understanding.

  5. We suspect that some other putative virtues of understanding—such as mechanism or fecundity—can be captured in terms of the two discussed here, but are certainly open to the possibility that there are others.

  6. In other words, we are positing a one-to-many function between contexts and ordered tuples of values to be placed on each dimension of understanding evaluation, of which we have identified two.

  7. It is less clear how our criticisms apply to de Regt (2009b) than to de Regt (forthcoming). In the former, he does at points seem to suggest that accuracy is at least generally a good thing; if that is right, we take the current section to be a plea to return to an earlier position. That he has jettisoned accuracy entirely is also suggested by de Regt and Gijsbers (forthcoming).

  8. The terms are actually quoted by de Regt from Knuuttila (2009), but we take them to capture his ultimate position.

  9. The development of Copernican astronomy and its relation to simplicity is a complex issue. Kuhn (1957, p. 169) famously argues that the system’s apparent simplicity is an illusion (see also Palter 1970). However, even assuming it is simpler, that does not entail that it is more intelligible. Typical arguments regarding its simplicity (e.g., Wilson 2012) mainly address its metaphysical or mathematical simplicity, which is distinct from its intelligibility and ease of use, particularly by early adherents.

  10. By this we just mean those who produce or believe in hepatoscopy. Perhaps fortunately, there does not seem to be an existent word for this.

  11. We thank an anonymous reviewer for stressing the importance of establishing this point.

  12. For a thorough discussion of the structure of scientific theories, see Winther (2015). Our goal in outlining the features of hepatoscopy theory in our imagined world was to make sure it satisfied the conditions of all of the syntactic, semantic, and pragmatic accounts of what makes something a theory.

  13. We again thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out that it is consistent with our view that hepatoscopists in such a world contain some minimal understanding.

  14. As that work has not yet been published, much of what we say here might prove off the mark—however, we do think it can be a useful guide to at least the kind of maneuvers open to de Regt, and what we would say about them.

  15. Of course, if our current theories also are representationally inaccurate, that would be a mark against our current understanding as well. We think that this is a feature of our view, rather than a bug—it would be mere temporal chauvinism to assume that our understanding is unimpeachable. If one imagines a future where we discover that our present theories were inaccurate, we anticipate that we would take this as a mark against our present understanding to precisely the degree of the inaccuracy. To soften this conclusion, notice that our current theories can still have some representational accuracy even if they are not completely true, so they might still score reasonably well along both dimensions of evaluation, even if they do not achieve maximal scores.

  16. A scenario where it is better if one teammate does not score does occur periodically, for example near the end of Super Bowl XLVI.

  17. At least, post-acquisition abilities cannot be a direct measure. They could correlate with abilities involved in understanding acquisition, but they will not on these views directly contribute to understanding’s value. We thank Kareem Khalifa for this point.

  18. For those who are curious, the rules (as stated in Roach et al. 2013, p. 42) are:

    1. (1)

      Walk randomly until you encounter a grain.

    2. (2)

      If you have a grain, drop it.

    3. (3)

      If you do not have a grain, pick one up.

    4. (4)

      Repeat.

  19. In principle, one could perhaps also make the same move for the super lucky hepatoscopist, for whom it is the case that not only are her predictions correct, but she happens to be situated in a neighborhood of possible worlds where predictions made in nearby worlds would be correct as well. We think the present example, where the link between the representation and the correctness of its predictions is not entirely accidental, is more persuasive.

  20. Khalifa treats de Regt’s “skill condition” and “intelligibility condition” separately; however, as intelligibility is defined at least in large part by what one can do with a theory, we take the latter (at least in our expanded formulation) to be an instance of the former.

  21. At least, the earlier work we have reviewed here. Space requires us to gloss over several other pieces e.g. Khalifa (2011), and the various subtleties they entail. Since our end point will be a general sympathy for his latest formulation, our difficulties with all earlier formulations are less critical to our project.

  22. Moreover, we would argue that Newton’s explanation was actually better than phlogiston-theorists’ along both axes of evaluation since, given how relatively flat nearby space is and how relatively slow nearby objects move, it in many respects still paints a reasonable representational picture of the universe (note that representational accuracy can obtain even in the absence of strict truth). Deciding this contentious point however is well beyond the scope of this paper. For one discussion of what is at issue, see Couvalis (1997, Chap. 4), or de Regt and Gijsbers (forthcoming).

  23. Note that even the constructive empiricism of Van Fraassen (1980)—which says that scientific theories aim at empirical adequacy rather than truth—still places importance on representational accuracy. While posits of theoretical unobservables might not need be accurate in the traditional sense, the goodness of claims about observable phenomena will still require representational accuracy.

  24. Even philosophers who think that understanding is actually a crucial component of explanation (Wilkenfeld 2014; Waskan et al. 2014) grant that we cannot just feel when such understanding obtains.

  25. Actually there might be such a link, per Barański et al. (2014), but it seems safe to say that most people who assume organic food is healthier are not staying up-to-date on the cutting edge of the debate.

References

  • Barański, M., Średnicka-Tober, D., Volakakis, N., Seal, C., Sanderson, R., Stewart, G. B., et al. (2014). Higher antioxidant and lower cadmium concentrations and lower incidence of pesticide residues in organically grown crops: A systematic literature review and meta-analyses. British Journal of Nutrition, 112, 794–811.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2012). Is water H2O?: Evidence, realism and pluralism. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Couvalis, G. (1997). The philosophy of science: Science and objectivity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2009a). The epistemic value of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 585–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2009b). Understanding and scientific explanation. In H. W. De Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 21–42). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (forthcoming). Scientific understanding: Truth or dare? Synthese.

  • de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144(1), 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W., & Gijsbers, V. (forthcoming). How false theories can yield genuine understanding. In S. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

  • Elgin, C. (2007). Understanding and the facts. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2010). The goal of explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(4), 337–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science by Carl G. Hempel. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. (2013). Explanation, understanding, and unrealistic models. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(3), 523–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (forthcoming). Understanding phenomena. Synthese.

  • Khalifa, K. (2011). Understanding, knowledge, and scientific antirealism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 83(1), 93–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2012). Inaugurating understanding or repackaging explanation? Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 15–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2013). The role of explanation in understanding. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(1), 161–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (in press). Understanding: An epistemology of scientific explanation.

  • Knuuttila, T. (2009). Isolating representations versus credible constructions? Economic modelling in theory and practice. Erkenntnis, 70(1), 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1957). The Copernican revolution: Planetary astronomy in the development of western thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Bihan, S. (forthcoming). Enlightening falsehoods: A modal view of scientific understanding. In S. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2009). Understanding without explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 43–63). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnusson, M. K., Arvola, A., Hursti, U. K., Åberg, L., & Sjödén, P. (2003). Choice of organic foods is related to perceived consequences for human health and to environmentally friendly behaviour. Appetite, 40(2), 109–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michel, C., Velasco, C., Gatti, E., & Spence, C. (2014). A taste of Kandinsky: Assessing the influence of the artistic visual presentation of food on the dining experience. Flavour, 3(1), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2012). Idealizations and scientific understanding. Philosophical Studies, 160(2), 237–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2014). Truthlikeness. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2014 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/truthlikeness/.

  • Palter, R. (1970). An approach to the history of early astronomy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 1(2), 93–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roach, J., Ewert, W., Marks, R., & Thompson, B. B. (2013). Unexpected emergent behaviors from elementary swarms. In 2013 45th Southeastern symposium on system theory (SSST) (pp. 41–50).

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith-Spangler, C., Brandeau, M. L., Hunter, G. E., Bavinger, J. C., Pearson, M., Eschbach, P. J., et al. (2012). Are organic foods safer or healthier than conventional alternatives? A systematic review. Annals of Internal Medicine, 157(5), 348–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2013). No understanding without explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(3), 510–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69(2), 212–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford/New York: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waskan, J., Harmon, I., Horne, Z., Spino, J., & Clevenger, J. (2014). Explanatory anti-psychologism overturned by lay and scientific case classifications. Synthese, 191(5), 1013–1035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190, 997–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2014). Functional explaining: A new approach to the philosophy of explanation. Synthese, 191, 3367–3391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A., & Hellmann, J. K. (2014). Understanding beyond grasping propositions: A discussion of chess and fish. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 48, 46–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A., Plunkett, D., & Lombrozo, T. (forthcoming). Depth and deference: When and why we attribute understanding. Philosophical Studies.

  • Wilson, D. B. (2012). Simplicity in the Copernican revolution: Galileo, Descartes, Newton. In J. Z. Buchwald (Ed.), A master of science history: Essays in honor of Charles Coulston Gillispie (pp. 123–133). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2006). Wandering significance: An essay on conceptual behavior. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2015). The structure of scientific theories. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Henk de Regt for comments on this draft, Tania Lombrozo for her continued support, Kareem Khalifa for clarification regarding his views and comments on a draft, Don Hubin for a particularly poignant question regarding Copernican astronomers, Soazig Le Bihan for invaluable conversation, helpful referee comments, and the John Templeton Foundation Varieties of Understanding grant and its administrators for funding the present research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel A. Wilkenfeld.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wilkenfeld, D.A. MUDdy understanding. Synthese 194, 1273–1293 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0992-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0992-x

Keywords

Navigation